Skip to main content

Full text of "Motivation of behavior"

See other formats


0^ 


UNIVERSITY 
OF  FLORIDA 
LIBRARIES 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2010  with  funding  from 

Lyrasis  IVIembers  and  Sloan  Foundation 


http://www.archive.org/details/motivationofbehaOObrow 


The  Motivation  of  Behavior 


McGRAW-HILL  SERIES  IN  PSYCHOLOGY 
Harry  F.  Harlow,  Consulting  Editor 


Barker,  Kounin,  and  Wright   •   Child  Behavior  and  Development 
Beach,   Hebb,   Morgan,   and   Nissen    •    The  Neuropsychology   of 

Lashley 
von  Bekesy  •  Experiments  in  Hearing 
Berlyne  •  Conflict,  Arousal,  and  Curiosity 
Blum  •  Psychoanalytic  Theories  of  Personality 
Brov^^n  •  The  Motivation  of  Behavior 
Brown  •  The  Psychodynamics  of  Abnormal  Behavior 
Brown  and  Ghiselli  •  Scientific  Method  in  Psychology 
Cattell  •  Personality 
Crafts,  Schneirla,  Robinson,  and  Gilbert  •  Recent  Experiments 

in  Psychology 
Deese  •  The  Psychology  of  Learning 
DoLLARD  AND  MiLLER  •  Personality  and  Psychotherapy 
DoRcus  AND  Jones  •  Handbook  of  Employee  Selection 
Ferguson  •  Personality  Measurement 

Ferguson  •  Statistical  Analysis  in  Psychology  and  Education 
Ghiselli  and  Brown  •  Personnel  and  Industrial  Psychology 
Gilmer  •  Industrial  Psychology 
Gray  •  Psychology  Applied  to  Human  Affairs 
Gray  •  Psychology  in  Industry 

Guilford  •  Fundamental  Statistics  in  Psychology  and  Education 
Guilford   •   Personality 
Guilford  •  Psychometric  Methods 
Haire  •  Psychology  in  Management 
Hirsh  •  The  Measurement  of  Hearing 
HuRLOCK  •  Adolescent  Development 
HuRLOCK  •  Child  Development 


HuRLOCK  •  Developmental  Psychology 

Johnson  •  Essentials  of  Psychology 

Karn  and  Gilmer  •  Readings  in  Industrial  and  Business  Psychology 

Krech  and  Crutchfield  •  Theory  and  Problems  of  Social  Psychology 

Lewin  •  A  Dynamic  Theory  of  Personality 

Lewin  •  Principles  of  Topological  Psychology 

Lewis  •  Quantitative  Methods  in  Psychology 

Maier  and  Schneirla  •  Principles  of  Animal  Psychology 

Miller  •  Language  and  Communication 

MisiAK  AND  Staudt  •  Catholics  in  Psychology:  A  Historical  Survey 

Moore  •  Psychology  for  Business  and  Industry 

Morgan  and  Stellar  •  Physiological  Psychology 

Page  •  Abnormal  Psychology 

Reymert  •  Feelings  and  Emotions 

Seashore  •  Psychology  of  Music 

Shaffer  and  Lazarus  •  Fundamental  Concepts  in  Clinical  Psy- 
chology 

SiEGEL  •  Nonparametric  Statistics:  For  the  Behavioral  Sciences 

Stagner  •  Psychology  of  Personality 

Tovv^nsend  •  Introduction  to  Experimental  Method 

Vinacke  •  The  Psychology  of  Thinking 

Wallen  •  Clinical  Psychology:  The  Study  of  Persons 

Waters,  Rethlingshafer,  and  Caldwell  •  Principles  of  Com- 
parative Psychology 

ZuBEK  and  Solberg  *  Humau  Development 

John  F.  Dashiell  was  Consulting  Editor  of  this  series  from  its  in- 
ception in  1931  until  January  I,  1950.  Clifford  T.  Morgan  was  Con- 
sulting Editor  of  this  series  from  January  1,  1950  until  January  1,  1959. 


THE  MOTIVATION 
OF  BEHAVIOR 


(co-  m  bl  Z. 

JUDSON  SEISE  BROWN 

Graduate  Research  Professor 
University  of  Florida 


McGRAW-HILL     BOOK     COMPANY,     INC, 

New  York       Toronto        London        1961 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Copyright  ©  1961  by  the  McGraw-Hill  Book  Company,  Inc.  Printed 
in  the  United  States  of  America.  All  rights  reserved.  This  book,  or 
parts  thereof,  may  not  be  reproduced  in  any  form  without  permission 
of  the  publishers.  Library  of  Congress  Catalog  Card  Number  60-14612 

08305 


PREFACE 

II 


Two  major  aims  have  served  as  guideposts  throughout  the 
writing  of  this  book.  The  more  important  of  these  has  been  to 
develop  a  tightly  reasoned,  systematic  analysis  of  the  concept  of 
motivation,  with  special  emphasis  upon  its  relative  utility  as  an 
explanatory  component  of  general  behavior  theory.  The  lesser 
goal  has  been  to  formulate  the  analysis  in  such  a  manner  as  to 
make  it  intelligible  to  the  advanced  undergraduate  or  beginning 
graduate  student  in  psychology. 

In  principle,  if  all  behavior  is  motivated,  any  book  about  mo- 
tivation should  encompass  all  of  psychology,  at  the  very  least. 
Since  such  inclusiveness  is  patently  impossible,  an  author  is  forced, 
in  reducing  his  task  to  manageable  proportions,  to  neglect  certain 
topics  of  special  interest  to  particular  readers.  He  must  be  selec- 
tive, therefore,  and  in  the  absence  of  widely  accepted  criteria  for 
evaluating  the  importance  of  each  and  every  area,  the  process 
of  selection  must  be  governed  primarily  by  idiosyncratic  factors. 
In  the  succeeding  pages,  for  example,  almost  no  consideration  is 
given  to  the  topic  of  sexual  behavior.  This  omission  should  not 
be  construed,  however,  as  reflecting  the  belief  that  there  are  no 
significant  motivational  aspects  to  sexual  behavior.  Rather  it  is  a 
consequence  of  the  conviction  that  while  much  is  known  of  the 
effects  of  hereditary  and  environmental  variables  upon  sexual  be- 
havior, especially  in  lower  mammals,  the  concept  of  sexual  motiva- 
tion has  thus  far  played  only  the  vaguest  of  roles  in  behavior 
theory  generally.  This  point  is  underscored  by  the  observation 
that  the  terms  drive  and  motivation  are  almost  never  used  in 
published  works  on  reproductive  activities,  even  when  such  works 


viii  PREFACE 

have  been  written  by  psychologists.  To  be  sure,  students  of  repro- 
ductive activities  are  concerned  with  motivated  behavior,  but  they 
have  shown  httle  interest  in  the  construct  of  sexual  motivation. 
Similarly  detailed  justifications  to  support  my  neglect  of  other 
topics,  such  as  hoarding  behavior,  taste  preferences,  and  the  vast 
Freudian  literature  on  unconscious  motivation,  would  lengthen 
this  preface  unduly.  It  need  only  be  said,  therefore,  that  in  some 
instances  I  was  unable  clearly  to  discern  the  motivational  impli- 
cations of  the  research,  in  certain  cases  my  fund  of  knowledge 
was  inadequate,  and  in  others  the  existing  literature  seemed  both 
adequate  and  extensive. 

Some  readers  may  feel  that  I  have  paid  undue  attention  to 
Hull's  multiplicative-drive  theory  of  motivation.  Here  I  must 
plead  guilty  to  the  belief  that  this  conception,  augmented  by 
other  theorists'  emendations,  is  the  most  explicitly  structured  of 
existing  views,  and,  at  present,  probably  the  most  useful  theory 
of  motivation  we  possess.  So  far  as  I  am  aware,  no  other  con- 
ception of  the  motivational  process  has  generated  so  much  ex- 
perimental work  or  led  to  such  varied  theoretical  inquiry.  Never- 
theless, on  a  number  of  occasions  I  have  suggested,  and  some- 
times defended,  the  possibility  that  Hull's  conception  is  either 
inadequate  or  noneconomical.  Rather  generally  throughout  the 
book,  and  particularly  in  Chapter  4,  serious  and  sympathetic  at- 
tention is  given  to  alternative,  nonmotivational  interpretations  of 
the  effects  of  so-called  motivational  variables  upon  behavior. 

Grateful  and  enthusiastic  acknowledgment  is  made  to  the  many 
individuals  who,  as  the  result  of  their  careful  and  intelligent  read- 
ing of  early  versions  of  the  manuscript,  did  much  to  improve  its 
clarity  and  precision.  In  this  respect,  I.  E.  Farber's  penetrating 
and  constructive  review  of  the  entire  manuscript  was  of  inesti- 
mable value.  The  unusually  discerning  and  appropriate  criticisms 
of  Bettina  Bass,  Richard  deCharms,  Kenneth  P.  Goodrich, 
Leonard  E.  Ross,  Charles  C.  Spiker,  and  Allan  M.  Wagner  evoke 
not  only  my  warmest  thanks  but  also,  frankly,  my  envy.  Robert 
S.  Witte,  who  used  a  preliminary  draft  of  the  manuscript  in  his 
motivation  classes  at  Cornell  College,  Mount  Vernon,  Iowa,  re- 
lieved some  of  my  qualms  concerning  the  suitability  of  the  ma- 
terial for  undergraduates,  and  in  addition  made  numerous  positive 


PREFACE  ix 

suggestions  for  the  improvement  of  the  manuscript.  Kenneth  W. 
Spence  repeatedly  guided  me  to  important  references  and  concepts, 
and  our  informal  discussions  have  been  of  great  value  in  helping 
me  toward  clearer  conceptions  of  difficult  problems. 

I  am  especially  grateful  to  my  wife,  Julia  S.  Brown,  for  her 
cheerful  and  painstaking  assistance  in  the  preparation  of  the  final 
manuscript  and  for  her  scholarly  criticisms  both  of  my  phraseology 
and  of  certain  of  my  arguments.  The  high-level  secretarial  assist- 
ance provided  at  various  times  by  Betty  Jean  Stoner,  Jean  Hansen, 
and  Sandra  Wood  is  a  pleasure  to  acknowledge,  as  is  the  biblio- 
graphic work  of  Marigold  Belloni. 

Some  of  that  priceless  commodity,  time  to  think  and  to  write, 
was  provided  by  the  Graduate  College  of  the  State  University  of 
Iowa  in  the  form  of  a  Graduate  Research  Professorship  during 
the  period  from  September  1956  to  January  1957.  Much  of  the 
theoretical  development  and  some  of  the  unpublished  experi- 
ments cited  in  Chapter  8  were  supported  by  a  small  grant 
(M-1789)  from  the  National  Institutes  of  Health. 

Permission  to  reproduce  figures  and  to  make  quotations  were 
granted  by  individual  authors  and  their  work  is  credited  in  each 
instance  as  a  citation  to  the  list  of  references.  Permission  to  quote 
and  reproduce  figures  was  also  granted  by  the  University  of 
Nebraska  Press,  Yale  University  Press,  the  New  York  Academy  of 
Sciences,  the  Journal  Press,  the  American  Journal  of  Psychology, 
the  Journal  of  Personality,  and  the  American  Psychological  Asso- 
ciation. The  cooperation  of  all  of  these  authors  and  organizations 
is  gratefully  acknowledged. 

Judson  S.  Brown 


CONTENTS 


Preface vii 

1 .  The  Psychologist's  Task  and  the  Problem  of  Motivation  .  1 

2.  Intervening  Variables  and  the  Definition  and  Measurement 

of  Drive 28 

3.  Primary  Sources  of  Drive 57 

4.  Motivational  and  Associative  Interpretations  of  "Motivated" 
Behavior 97 

5.  Learned  Responses  as  Sources  of  Drive 138 

6.  Motivational  Consequences  of  Frustration  and  Conflict  .  194 

7.  Motivational  Variables  and  Human  Performance             .  224 

8.  Motivational  Variables  and  Perception 266 

9.  Miscellaneous  Motivational  Problems 327 

References 365 

Name  Index 389 

Subject  Index 394 


CHAPTER 

miiiiiiiiiiiiii 


1 


The  Psychologist's  Task  and 
the  Probfem  of  Motivation 

Most  present-day  psychologists  would  probably  agree  that  their 
principal  task  is  to  study  and  to  strive  to  understand  the  behavior 
of  living  organisms,  both  human  and  subhuman.  To  accomplish 
this  aim,  the  psychologist,  if  he  wishes  to  proceed  in  a  scientific 
manner,  must  begin  by  making  dispassionate,  careful,  and  re- 
peated observations  of  the  activities  of  organisms  in  a  wide  variety 
of  circumstances.  He  must  observe  the  movements  they  make,  the 
sounds  they  utter,  the  objects  they  manipulate,  and  their  interac- 
tions with  other  organisms.  Moreover,  these  observations  must  be 
recorded  in  a  relatively  permanent  manner  so  that  they  can  be 
evaluated  and  analyzed  long  after  the  behavior  has  ceased  and  the 
process  of  observing  has  been  terminated.  Initially,  therefore,  the 
psychologist's  task  is  to  observe  the  actions  of  organisms  and  to 
record  what  he  has  seen  in  as  precise  and  accurate  a  manner  as 
possible.  These  recorded  bits  of  information  constitute  the  basic 
data  with  which  he  begins  his  work. 

The  psychologist  concentrates  his  attention  primarily  upon  the 
behavior  of  living  organisms,  not  upon  their  physiological  func- 

1 


2  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

tions,  their  anatomical  structure,  or  their  physical-chemical  com- 
position. Psychological  data  are  thus  derived  from  one  class  of 
events  and  the  data  of  other  sciences  from  different  classes. 
Because  of  this  one  may  maintain,  with  some  justifica- 
tion, that  the  subject  matter  of  psychology  is  unique  in  comparison 
with  the  subject  matter  of  other  disciplines. 

But  we  must  also  remember  that  there  is  almost  nothing  unique 
or  characteristically  "psychological"  about  the  methods  by  which 
the  psychologist  collects  his  raw  data.  His  observational  techniques 
are,  in  essence,  the  same  as  those  of  the  zoologist,  the  physiologist, 
and  the  physicist.  Sometimes  the  only  equipment  he  uses  is  a 
pencil  and  paper.  He  notes  whether  a  rat  turns  right  or  left  in  a 
maze;  he  counts  the  motorists  who  do  or  do  not  stop  for  a  red 
traffic  light;  he  tabulates  the  swallows  a  baby  makes  while  drink- 
ing a  bottle  of  milk;  he  records  the  number  of  mistakes  made  by 
a  student  on  an  intelligence  test.  On  other  occasions,  however, 
the  psychologist's  observations  cannot  be  made  without  the  help 
of  much  more  elaborate  equipment.  He  may  use  a  stop  watch  to 
measure  the  time  taken  by  a  student  in  completing  a  question- 
naire; he  may  employ  an  electronic  instrument  to  detect  and  record 
changes  in  the  resistance  of  the  skin  due  to  loud  sounds  or  painful 
stimuli;  he  may  use  the  physicist's  gauges  to  measure  the  force 
of  a  manual  movement.  But  whether  the  equipment  is  simple 
or  complex,  in  all  of  these  instances  the  psychologist  is  using  the 
well-known,  well-standardized  methods  of  the  natural  sciences. 
He  measures  the  vigor  of  a  movement  and  expresses  its  force  in 
physical  units  such  as  grams  or  pounds;  he  times  the  duration 
of  a  movement  in  seconds  or  minutes;  he  counts  the  frequencies 
of  events  of  many  kinds  and  records  the  results  in  standard  numeri- 
cal notations.  His  raw  data,  therefore,  when  tabulated  and  recorded 
are  simply  the  frequencies  with  which  certain  events  occur,  their 
magnitudes,  their  rates,  or  their  durations.  Considered  in  this 
restricted  sense,  as  frequency  counts,  quantities  that  change  with 
time,  amplitude  measurements,  and  the  like,  the  basic  data  of 
psychology  are  identical  with  the  basic  data  of  all  other  sciences. 
Psychological  data  could  not  be  obtained,  of  course,  save  for  the 
existence  of  living  organisms,  but  the  fundamental  observations 
are  made  by  methods  common  to  all  sciences  and  are  couched  in 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION  3 

the  language  of  the  natural  scientist,  not  in  any  special-purpose 
psychological  jargon. 

Defining  the  Responses  of  Organisms.  Since  we  have  maintained 
that  the  student  of  behavior  begins  by  observing  the  actions  or 
responses  of  organisms,  wt  must  next  consider  the  problem  of 
how  to  specify  or  define  a  response.  While  difficulties  may  arise 
at  the  conceptual  level,  in  actual  practice  few  problems  accompany 
the  delineation  of  events  that  will  be  called  responses.  Responses 
are  whatever  movements  or  classes  of  movements  or  actions  we 
decide  to  record  or  measure.  A  response  is  a  member  of  a  class  or 
set  of  objectively  recordable  events  attributable  to  whatever  organ- 
ism we  are  observing.  But  if  different  observers  are  to  agree  that 
a  response  has  occurred  (and  such  agreement  is  a  necessary  con- 
dition for  scientific  analysis),  they  must  all  be  governed  by  rules 
of  observation  that  specify  precisely  what  activities  are  to  be  in- 
cluded in  a  response  class.  For  example,  two  observers  will  usually 
agree  that  a  rat  has  turned  to  the  right  at  a  designated  point  in 
a  maze  if  it  turns  sharply  through  an  angle  of  90°.  But  what  if 
the  animal  veers  only  20°  to  the  right  of  its  original  line  of  move- 
ment? Is  this  a  right-turning  reaction?  It  is  or  is  not  a  "right  turn" 
depending  upon  what  limits  have  been  placed  upon  the  class  of 
movements  to  be  designated  right  turns.  The  selection  of  particular 
limits  is  a  matter  of  choice  at  the  outset,  being  governed  by 
hunches  or  prior  knowledge.  It  is  only  when  our  response-defining 
criteria  have  been  shown  to  be  unworkable  or  useless  that  they 
must  be  revised.  Thus  one  may  decide  to  call  a  movement  to 
the  right  a  right  turn  if  it  describes  an  angle  of  at  least  80  but 
not  more  than  100°.  Once  such  class  boundaries  have  been  speci- 
fied, any  competent  observer  can  decide  whether  a  given  turning 
movement  does  or  does  not  fall  within  the  prescribed  limits.  If  it 
does,  he  makes  a  tally  mark  on  his  record  sheet  and  the  response 
is  said  to  have  occurred. 

From  time  to  time  various  writers  (Bakan,  1953;  Nissen,  1954; 
Hall  and  Lindzey,  1957)  have  suggested  that  information  about 
eliciting  stimuli  is  essential  to  an  adequate  definition  or  description 
of  any  response.  This  appears  to  be  true  only  when  the  phrase 
"adequate  definition  or  description"  is  treated  as  though  it  were 
synonymous  with  "adequate  scientific  explanation."  Few  will  deny 


4     ,         THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

that  every  observable  action  of  an  organism  is  antedated  by  com- 
plex chains  of  related  events,  some  of  which  would  unquestionably 
qualify  as  "stimuli."  Quite  obviously,  therefore,  any  complete 
scientific  explanation  of  a  response  would  necessarily  contain  some 
reference  to  correlated  or  eliciting  stimuli. 

But  a  scientific  explanation  of  a  response  is  one  thing,  and  its 
definition  or  description,  for  purposes  of  scientific  observation,  is 
something  else.  The  activities  of  organisms  are  physical  events 
occurring  in  the  physical  world,  and  agreement  among  competent 
observers  as  to  the  occurrence  or  nonoccurrence  of  these  actions 
can  be  achieved  through  precisely  formulated  observational  rules. 
A  response  is  adequately  defined  when  the  criteria  for  its  observa- 
tion have  been  specified  in  detail.  For  this  purpose  information 
about  the  nature  or  presence  of  eliciting  stimuli  is  completely 
irrelevant.  In  making  his  raw  tally  marks,  an  investigator  need 
have  no  knowledge  of  the  stimulus  events  that  are  correlated 
with  the  behavior;  it  is  required  only  that  he  know  the  rules  of 
observation  and  how  to  operate  his  measuring  or  recording  equip- 
ment. In  fact,  the  behavior  scientist  can  spend  his  entire  life 
investigating  behavior  and  determining  whether  it  is  lawfully 
related  to  other  data  without  ever  getting  involved  in  the  question 
of  whether  he  is  indeed  studying  instances  of  what  others  might 
call  responses.  Incidentally,  the  assertion  that  an  action,  a  response, 
or  a  reaction  can  be  defined,  specified,  or  described  independently 
of  correlated  stimuli  does  not  imply  that  the  behavior  has  no 
stimulus  correlates.  It  means  simply  that  the  behavior  can  be 
identified  and  recorded  even  though  its  eliciting  stimuli  may  never 
be  discovered. 

Alternative  Definitions  of  Response  Classes.  As  we  have  seen, 
the  task  of  defining  a  response  is  not  especially  difficult  provided 
observational  criteria  can  be  specified  with  sufficient  precision. 
No  two  responses  are  ever  exactly  alike,  however,  and  hence  our 
criteria  of  observation  must  encompass  a  class  or  group  of  re- 
sponses. This  necessity  raises  the  further  question  of  exactly  where 
the  boundaries  of  the  response  class  should  be  fixed.  Prior  to  exten- 
sive study  we  have  no  way  of  knowing  whether  the  response 
domain  should  be  broad  or  narrow.  Important  laws  might  be 
obtained  with  one  criterion  of  class  membership  but  not  with 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION  5 

another.  In  the  absence  of  information  provided  by  experience, 
the  boundaries  of  response  classes  are  determined  by  the  best 
available  guesses  as  to  which  settings  will  prove  most  fruitful  in 
the  long  run.  Psychologists'  guesses  in  these  matters  have  differed 
widely,  however,  and  considerable  controversy  has  been  the  result. 
Because  of  this  difference  of  opinion  it  is  necessary  to  examine 
the  problem  in  greater  detail.  This  can  best  be  done,  perhaps, 
by  considering  several  of  the  alternative  response-class  definitions 
that  have  been  advocated  by  various  investigators.  Somewhat 
similar  discussions  of  response  classes  will  be  found  elsewhere 
(e.g.,  Davis,  1953;  Logan,  Olmsted,  Rosner,  Schwartz,  and  Stevens, 
1955). 

In  the  first  place,  some  students  of  behavior  are  quite  satis- 
fied to  work  with  a  very  limited  class  of  reactions  such  as  those 
provided  by  a  single  muscle  group  or  gland.  Pavlov  (1927),  in 
his  extensive  studies  of  salivary  conditioning  in  dogs,  used  a 
response-classification  scheme  of  this  kind.  A  dog  was  said  to  have 
"behaved"  or  "responded"  whenever  a  drop  of  saliva  was  seen  to 
fall  from  a  tube  attached  to  an  externalized  opening  of  its  salivary 
gland.  Hilden  (1937),  in  studying  conditioned  finger  withdrawal 
in  human  subjects,  recorded  electrical  potentials  originating  in 
the  muscles  controlling  the  finger.  A  "response"  in  this  instance 
was  defined  as  an  action-potential  burst  of  a  given  magnitude. 
Because  of  the  method  employed,  a  subject  was  said  to  be  reacting 
even  when  no  overt  movement  of  his  finger  could  be  detected. 
If  definite  rules  were  prescribed  for  reading  the  graphic  records 
of  electrical  muscle  activity,  different  observers  would  have  little 
difficulty  in  reaching  an  agreement  as  to  whether  a  response  had 
or  had  not  occurred.  The  psychologist  who  restricts  the  class  of 
recordable  reactions  to  the  activity  of  a  single  muscle  group  or 
gland  has  adopted  about  as  simple  a  classification  scheme  as  he 
can  use  and  still  maintain  that  he  is  studying  "behavior."  To 
move  farther  back  into  the  mechanisms  underlying  behavior,  by 
investigating,  say,  the  neural  events  preceding  the  contraction  of 
a  muscle,  would  take  one  into  the  traditional  field  of  physiology. 

A  second,  broader  way  of  categorizing  behavior  would  be  to 
limit  one's  observations  to  the  overt  movements  of  a  single  limb. 
Thus  one  might  tally  the  occurrence  of  a  response,  in  an  avoid- 


6  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

ance-conditioning  situation,  if  a  dog  were  to  lift  its  leg  at  least  V4 
inch  from  the  floor  during  a  certain  interval  following  the  presen- 
tation of  the  conditioned  stimulus.  This  way  of  categorizing 
behavior  differs  from  the  first  in  that  different  muscle  groups 
might  be  involved  on  each  occasion  when  the  leg  is  lifted.  But 
by  following  the  specified  rules  one  can  make  repeated  observa- 
tions of  the  "same"  behavior,  where  "sameness"  is  defined  as 
any  upward  movement  of  the  foot  of  at  least  V4  inch.  Such 
repeated  observations  are,  of  course,  essential  in  any  scientific 
investigation.  The  isolated  occurrence  of  a  single  muscle  twitch 
or  a  single  movement  or  a  single  act  of  aggression  is  of  little 
value  to  the  student  of  behavior.  Whether  the  criterion  of  move- 
ment is  set  at  V4  inch,  1  inch,  or  any  other  value  is  entirely  up 
to  the  psychologist  who  conducts  the  experiment. 

A  third  way  of  classifying  responses  is  to  combine  all  activities 
that  have  the  same  end  effect  upon  the  environment,  regardless 
of  which  specific  limbs  or  muscles  are  involved.  Thus,  in  studying 
the  behavior  of  children  or  adults,  any  action  resulting  in  injury 
to  another  person,  regardless  of  how  the  injury  was  produced, 
might  be  classified  as  an  aggressive  act.  Or,  in  studying  the  behavior 
of  rats  in  a  Skinner  box,  any  depression  of  the  bar  might  be  treated 
as  a  bar-pressing  response  irrespective  of  whether  the  bar  is  pressed 
by  the  rat's  foot,  tail,  head,  or  body.  Different  effectors  and  dif- 
ferent kinds  of  neural  integrations  would  be  involved  in  each  case, 
but  the  reactions  could  all  be  treated  as  identical  for  the  purpose 
of  counting  responses.  In  every  instance  of  this  kind  the,  experi- 
menter must  specify  the  criteria  to  be  met  by  the  reaction  if  it  is 
to  qualify  as  a  recordable  member  of  the  response  group  under 
study.  If  aggression  is  defined  in  terms  of  injury  to  others,  then 
the  child  who  throws  an  object  at  his  toy  box,  but  misses  and 
hurts  a  second  child,  is  exhibiting  aggression.  A  bar-pressing 
response  of  less  than  some  predetermined  amount  may  or  may 
not  be  included  as  a  member  of  the  class  of  bar-pressing  acts.  It 
would  not  be  included  if  it  does  not  activate  the  food  magazine 
or  the  automatic  electric  counter  that  tallies  the  actions.  Skinner 
(1938)  carries  this  procedure  to  its  logical  extreme.  His  experi- 
mental situations  are  often  structured  so  that  it  is  impossible, 
even  should  one  so  desire,  to  observe  how  the  rat  actually  does 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION  7 

press  the  lever  or  to  see  whether  partial  responses  are  being  made. 
Skinner  is  satisfied  to  determine  whether  a  response,  defined  and 
identified  in  quite  an  arbitrary  manner,  varies  lawfully  with 
changes  in  laboratory  operations.  If  the  response  does  not  manifest 
lawful  variation,  which  might  be  the  case  if  the  force  required  to 
depress  the  bar  were  markedly  increased,  then  the  response  class 
must  be  redefined  and  a  new  set  of  data  collected. 

Psychologists  who  observe  in  detail  what  an  animal  or  child 
does  in  a  lever-pressing  or  problem-box  situation  may  be  impressed 
by  either  the  uniformity  of  behavior  or  by  its  variability.  Guthrie 
and  Horton  (1946),  for  example,  in  studying  the  behavior  of 
cats  in  a  puzzle  box,  found  their  subjects'  reactions  to  be  highly 
stereotyped.  If  the  cat  got  out  of  the  box  by  hitting  the  release 
pole  with  its  tail  on  one  trial,  it  was  likely  to  perform  substantially 
the  same  set  of  movements  on  the  next  trial.  Others,  such  as 
Tolman  (1932),  have  been  struck  by  the  fact  that,  with  regard 
to  the  muscle  groups  involved,  behavior  is  highly  variable  from 
trial  to  trial.  It  is  asserted,  as  a  consequence,  that  the  animal 
is  not  learning  to  make  responses  mediated  by  activity  of  the 
same  efferent  channels  and  the  same  muscular  or  glandular  effec- 
tors. Each  of  these  points  of  view  is,  in  essence,  a  statement  of 
faith  as  to  how  behavior  should  be  classified  if  one  is  to  attain  to 
the  highest  level  of  understanding,  lawfulness,  and  predictive 
efficiency.  As  will  be  noted  shortly,  those  for  whom  the  variability 
of  the  underlying  mechanisms  looms  large  are  impressed  by  the 
constancy  of  the  end  result.  Such  writers  often  favor  the  view 
that  the  behavior  is  "purposive."  For  them  the  animal  seems  to 
know  that  regardless  of  which  foot  is  used  to  press  the  lever  the 
food  will  be  forthcoming. 

A  fourth  way  of  classifying  responses  is  to  combine  all  actions 
leading  to  the  satisfaction  of  the  same  psychological  or  biological 
need.  Suppose,  for  example,  that  we  have  developed  a  method  for 
making  reliable  determinations  of  an  individual's  "need  to  be 
aggressive."  Conceivably,  this  need  could  be  satisfied  by  physical 
assault  upon  other  persons  or  upon  inanimate  objects,  by  verbal 
insults,  by  self-inflicted  injury,  and  by  a  wide  variety  of  other 
actions,  including  imagined  attacks  upon  others.  If  each  of  these 
quite  different  types  of  behavior  leads  to  the  satisfaction  of  the 


8  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

same  need,  they  might  all  be  included  in  a  single  response  class. 
Similarly,  an  -animal  could  satisfy  its  need  for  water  by  lapping 
up  any  of  several  different  kinds  of  fluid  mixtures  containing 
water,  by  eating  wet  food,  or  by  licking  water  from  its  paws. 
Behavior  of  this  sort  is  even  more  variable  than  that  included 
under  our  third  method  of  classification,  since  it  involves  variations 
in  both  effectors  and  goal  objects.  Because  of  this  it  is  even  more 
likely  to  be  called  "purposive"  by  those  who  favor  the  use  of  such 
a  term. 

As  a  fifth  way  of  grouping  actions  into  classes  for  purposes  of 
study,  one  might  treat  as  class  members  all  reactions  involving 
the  same  determinants  or  causes,  regardless  of  the  specific  needs 
satisfied,  the  environmental  objects  affected,  or  the  limbs  or  muscle 
groups  involved.  For  instance,  if  one  could  decide  unambiguously 
that  certain  actions  are  controlled  by  the  "will,"  and  if  other 
observers  could  concur  in  these  decisions,  it  might  be  useful  to 
allocate  the  responses  to  a  "voluntary"  category.  Or  if  one  could 
ascertain  which  actions  are  governed  by  the  organism's  intentions, 
these  could  be  brought  together  into  a  class  of  purposive  actions. 
One  might  also  be  able  to  decide  that  certain  activities  are  deter- 
mined by  personality  traits  such  as  anxiety,  rigidity,  or  honesty 
and  thus  be  able  to  achieve  useful  groupings. 

In  concluding  this  discussion  of  criteria  for  classifying  responses, 
it  should  be  noted  that  as  we  progress  from  the  first  through  the 
fifth  method,  it  becomes  increasingly  difficult  to  get  different 
observers  to  agree  that  a  given  action  has  been  correctly  classified. 
Actions  can  be  defined  independently  of  any  potential  or  actual 
stimulating  conditions,  simply  by  setting  up  criteria  for  counting 
or  measuring.  But  the  criteria  must  be  such  that  other  impartial 
observers  can  obtain  similar  results  by  applying  the  criteria  under 
essentially  comparable  conditions.  Such  application  is  not  espe- 
cially difficult  with  the  first  three  methods,  but  it  becomes  a 
relatively  serious  problem  with  the  last  two. 

Incidentally,  there  is  no  reason  why  a  single  observer  could  not 
apply  more  than  one  of  these  methods  of  response  classification 
to  a  single  set  of  behavioral  data.  In  making  his  observations,  if 
an  experimenter  has  included  a  wide  variety  of  actions  and  stimu- 
lating conditions  and  if  these  have  been  carefully  recorded,  he 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION  9 

can,  on  later  occasions,  select  several  subsets  of  actions  in  accord- 
ance with  specific  but  different  criteria.  He  is  then  free  to  utilize 
whichever  subset  proves  most  useful  or  interesting. 

Once  criteria  have  been  chosen  for  use  in  recording  the  occur- 
rence of  responses,  the  psychologist's  next  step  is  to  search  for 
what  may  be  loosely  described  as  the  "causes"  of  behavior.  In 
attempting  to  understand  behavior  it  is  not  enough  to  record 
behavior  and  nothing  else.  One  could  note,  in  the  most  minute 
detail,  the  thousands  of  responses  made  by  an  organism  through- 
out its  life  and  yet  have  little  or  no  understanding  of  why  the 
behavior  occurred.  To  understand  behavior  one  must  look  for 
environmental  or  organic  conditions,  for  other  responses  of  the 
organism,  or  for  any  other  events  that  can  be  related  in  some 
meaningful  way  to  the  observed  behavior.  One  must  record  events 
or  quantities  other  than  the  behavior  under  study:  quantities  such 
as  temperature,  humidity,  degree  of  illumination,  sounds,  physio- 
logical states  of  the  organism,  number  and  kinds  of  previous 
experiences,  and,  on  many  occasions,  other  reactions  of  the  same 
or  different  organisms.  Because  the  task  of  defining  and  specifying 
these  additional  events  leads  to  some  controversy  among  psychol- 
ogists, we  digress  briefly  to  consider  the  problems  involved  in 
defining  the  stimulus. 

On  the  Definition  of  Stimuli.  Some  authors  have  maintained 
that  the  stimuli  for  behavior  can  be  defined  only  in  terms  of  the 
reactions  they  evoke.  Because  of  this  limitation  they  have  argued 
further  that  meaningful  relations  cannot  be  formulated  between 
responses  and  stimuli  since  the  two  variables  of  an  empirical  law 
must  be  independent.  From  one  point  of  view  these  are  correct 
assertions,  but  they  must  be  carefully  interpreted  and  extensively 
qualified. 

In  the  first  place,  by  using  the  methods  of  the  physical  sciences, 
we  can  specify  or  describe  a  multitude  of  physical  phenomena  in 
an  entirely  objective  manner.  Moreover,  this  can  be  done  quite 
adequately  without  referring  to  the  behavior  of  the  particular 
organisms  we  are  investigating.  We  can  measure  the  temperature 
of  the  air  that  surrounds  our  subjects,  the  brightness  of  lights  to 
which  they  are  told  to  respond,  the  intensity  of  sound  produced 
by  a  thunderclap,  the  number  of  grains  of  ragweed  pollen  per 


10  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

cubic  foot  of  air,  the  amplitude  of  radio  waves,  and  so  on.  These 
environmental  events  and  many  more  are  external  to,  and  inde- 
pendent of,  the  presence  or  behavior  of  the  subjects  of  our  psy- 
chological experiments.  For  the  moment  let  us  describe  these 
phenomena  by  the  term  physical  incidents. 

We  can  also  include  in  this  category  additional  incidents  at- 
tributable to  organisms  other  than  our  subjects.  The  patterns  of 
light  and  shadow  provided  by  the  movements  of  another  organism, 
the  assorted  sequences  of  sounds  it  produces,  or  its  physical  move- 
ments, are  phenomena  that  can  be  recorded  and  measured  by 
the  same  methods  one  uses  for  other  physical  incidents.  These 
incidents  do  originate  in  the  behavior  of  an  organism,  but  they 
can  be  observed  and  measured  independently  of  the  particular 
organisms  that  serve  as  our  subjects.  For  some  purposes  it  may 
be  desirable  to  distinguish  this  second  group  of  incidents  from 
the  first,  but  both  kinds  of  physical  occurrences  can  be  measured 
and  defined  by  the  methods  of  the  natural  scientist.  Assertions 
about  the  presence  of  any  one  of  these  incidents,  about  its  dura- 
tion in  time,  or  about  its  intensity  or  extensity,  depend  solely  upon 
objective  physical  measurements;  such  assertions  are  not  con- 
tingent upon  the  presence  of  the  organisms  whose  behavior  is 
under  study,  though  they  do  depend  upon  the  presence  of  the 
observing  and  recording  scientist. 

In  order  to  simplify  this  discussion  we  have  ignored  the  possi- 
bility that  certain  responses  may  have  physical  consequences  that 
can  be  correlated  with  subsequent  responses.  These  response-gen- 
erated physical  events  can,  in  principle,  be  measured  in  the  same 
ways  that  we  measure  events  external  to  our  subjects,  but  practical 
techniques  for  doing  so  remain  to  be  perfected. 

A  strong  case  can  be  made  for  the  view,  therefore,  that  the  raw 
data  with  which  the  psychologist  works  consist,  in  part,  of  (1) 
a  set  of  quantities  obtained  from  physical  measurements  of  the 
actions  of  his  subjects,  and  (2)  a  set  of  independent  quantities 
obtained  by  measuring  or  counting  physical  incidents  originating 
outside  of  his  reacting  subjects.  The  psychologist's  goal  is  to  under- 
stand the  first  set  of  quantities,  and  to  date  the  most  fruitful 
procedure  has  been  to  search  for  relations  between  elements  of 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION  1 1 

the  second  set  (the  environment)  and  elements  of  the  first  (be- 
havior). At  a  low  level  of  complexity,  the  ability  to  state  lawful 
relations  between  the  elements  of  these  two  sets  of  quantities 
constitutes  scientific  explanation  in  psychology. 

As  the  process  of  formulating  and  discovering  dependable  rela- 
tions between  these  two  sets  of  quantities  progresses,  the  psychol- 
ogist finds  that  some  physical  incidents  are  correlated  with  actions 
of  the  observed  organisms  and  some  are  not.  For  example,  he 
may  note  that  a  subject  exhibits  a  vigorous  startle  reaction  when- 
ever a  loud,  sharp  sound  is  presented.  On  the  other  hand,  a  rela- 
tionship may  never  be  found  between  intensity  of  cosmic  radiation 
reaching  earth  from  outer  space  and  any  recordable  bit  of  behavior. 
Both  the  loud  sound  and  the  cosmic  rays  are  physical  incidents, 
but,  so  far  as  we  now  know,  only  the  sound  is  closely  and  con- 
sistently related  to  behavior. 

As  a  consequence  of  numerous  observations,  the  psychologist 
can  point  to  a  great  many  physical  incidents  that  are  related, 
though  in  varying  degrees,  to  behavior.  Moreover,  he  frequently 
knows  how  long  the  physical  incidents  must  endure,  how  intense 
and  how  close  they  must  be  to  the  organism,  and  what  other 
characteristics  they  must  possess  if  they  are  to  correlate  with  a 
subject's  behavior.  On  the  basis  of  his  investigations,  therefore, 
the  psychologist  can  define  a  new  subclass  of  physical  incidents 
which,  though  they  differ  radically  from  one  another,  have  as  a 
common  characteristic  a  known  relatedness  to  actions.  It  is  to 
this  subclass  of  physical  incidents  that  the  name  stimuli  is  often 
given.  Thus,  to  describe  a  physical  incident  as  a  stimulus  is  simply 
to  assert  that  it  is,  as  a  consequence  of  empirical  findings,  known 
to  be  related,  or  to  have  been  related,  to  the  behavior  of  some 
organism  in  some  way.  The  assertion  that  a  stimulus  must  be 
defined  in  terms  of  a  response  stems  from  the  fact  that  responses 
are  involved  in  the  process  of  attaching  the  name  stimulus  to  a 
given  physical  incident.  But  the  inherent  physical  properties  of 
such  a  physical  incident  are  not  defined  by  appeal  to  responses, 
but  by  reference  to  physical  measurements.  Whether  a  physical 
event  is  to  be  called  a  stimulus  thus  depends  on  its  being  related 
to  responses;  but  what  it  is  as  a  physical  event  does  not.  The  term 


12  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

stimulus  is  simply  a  convenient  shorthand  expression  for  the  fact 
of  relatedness.  It  is  a  renaming  that  does  little,  in  and  of  itself, 
to  advance  our  understanding  of  basic  relations. 

In  connection  with  the  general  problem  of  deciding  which 
physical  incidents  might  be  chosen  for  inclusion  in  the  special 
class,  stimuli,  the  following  may  be  said:  The  responses  used  in 
empirical  demonstrations  of  relationships  to  physical  incidents 
may  be  of  several  different  types.  One  may  select  any  of  the 
response  classes  discussed  above  or  may  penetrate  more  deeply 
into  the  physiological  reactions  of  the  organism.  For  example,  one 
may  wish  to  assert  that  a  response  has  been  elicited  by  a  physical 
incident,  which  can  then  be  called  a  stimulus  if  any  afferent 
activity  whatever  was  noted  when  the  incident  occurred.  If  a  faint 
light  leads  to  electrical  activity  in  a  subject's  optic  nerve,  even 
though  no  overt  muscular  movements  occur,  one  may  say  the 
light  was  a  stimulus.  Alternatively,  one  may  choose  to  call  the 
light  a  stimulus  only  if  its  presentation  results  in  the  subject's 
saying  "I  see  something."  In  either  event,  reclassifying  the  light 
as  a  stimulus  is  a  consequence  of  observed  concomitant  action 
exhibited  by  the  subject.  At  present,  there  are  apparently  no 
clear-cut  reasons  for  choosing  one  kind  of  action  over  another. 

Before  turning  to  a  further  discussion  of  the  task  of  the  psy- 
chologist, we  should  note  that  irrespective  of  which  kind  of  activity 
or  response  is  used  as  the  criterion  for  relabeling  certain  physical 
incidents  as  stimuli,  the  relatedness  itself  is  dependent  upon  a 
great  many  variables  whose  presence  must  be  considered.  Thus  a 
light  may  qualify  as  a  stimulus  if  it  is  brighter  than  a  certain  min- 
imal value,  if  it  is  within  a  certain  distance  of  the  subject,  if  it  is 
located  at  a  certain  angle,  if  the  subject  is  not  too  fatigued  or  too 
bored,  if  response  A  is  used  rather  than  B,  and  so  on.  If  one  or 
more  of  these  conditions  is  not  fulfilled,  the  light  may  not  evoke 
a  measurable  reaction,  and  if  it  does  not,  then  at  that  moment  it 
does  not  meet  the  conditions  for  membership  in  the  class,  stimuli. 
A  thorough  understanding  of  behavior  requires  that  we  know 
precisely  when  and  under  what  conditions  a  given  physical  incident 
is  indeed  related  to  action.  The  task  of  discovering  the  nature  of 
these  relations  and  the  conditions  under  which  they  occur,  con- 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION  13 

stitutes  an  extensive  and  important  part  of  the  psychologist's  field 
of  endeavor. 


Types  of  Functional  Relations  Studied  by  the  Psychologist 

As  soon  as  the  psychologist  begins  to  observe  both  behavior 
and  the  environmental  circumstances  within  which  it  occurs,  he 
becomes  involved  in  determining  the  empirical  laws  that  hold 
between  and  within  the  two  sets  of  quantities.  In  the  following 
subsections  we  shall  describe  several  kinds  of  these  empirical  laws. 

Stimulus-Response  Relations.  Perhaps  the  simplest  kinds  of 
empirical  laws  with  which  the  psychologist  is  primarily  concerned 
are  those  in  which  the  reactions  of  a  subject  (or  subjects)  to 
systematically  varied  stimulus  conditions  are  recorded.  As  an 
illustration,  suppose  one  were  to  measure  the  mean  reaction  time 
of  a  group  of  subjects  to  each  of  several  different  intensities  of  a 
visual  signal  provided  by  a  light.  If  some  regular  change  in  reaction 
time  (R)  were  found  to  accompany  the  variations  in  light  intensity 
(S),  a  functional  connection  of  the  sort  commonly  called  an  S-R 
law  would  have  been  obtained.  Thus  an  S-R  law  is  an  empirical  re- 
lation between  measured  changes  in  some  aspect  of  the  physical 
environment  and  measured  variations  in  some  property  or  charac- 
teristic of  responses,  other  factors  being  held  constant. 

An  actual  S-R  relation  obtained  in  a  study  by  Hovland  and 
Riesen  (1940)  is  shown  in  Fig.  1:1.  As  can  be  seen  from  this 
figure,  these  investigators  found  that  mean  response  amplitude 
increased  as  the  intensity  of  the  tone  was  heightened.  The  response 
was  a  decrease  in  skin  resistance,  and  the  stimulus  was  a  1,000- 
cycle  tone  whose  intensity  above  the  subjects'  thresholds  was  ex- 
pressed in  decibels. 

In  actual  practice  a  function  of  this  kind  could  be  obtained 
either  from  repeated  tests  of  the  same  subjects,  using  the  five 
different  stimulus  values,  or  from  tests  of  a  different  group  of 
subjects  with  each  value.  In  either  case  the  resulting  S-R  function 
constitutes  a  summary  of  the  results  of  all  the  tests.  The  S-R  laws 
obtained  from  individual  subjects  would  probably  differ  consider- 
ably from  an  averaged  function  like  that  of  Fig.  1:1. 


14 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 
40 


30  60  90  120 

Sound  intensity  in  decibels  above  threshold 

Fig.  1:1.  A  simple  S-R  relation,  in  which  the  amplitude  of  a  galvanic  skin 
response  (GSR)  becomes  progressively  greater  as  the  intensity  of  a  sound 
stimulus  is  increased.   (Adapted  from  Hovland  and  Riesen,  1940.) 

R-R  Relations.  A  second  kind  of  empirical  law  frequently  ob- 
tained by  psychologists  may  be  described,  following  Spence  (1944), 
as  an  R-R  relation.  Such  a  law  is  obtained  by  plotting  one  set  of 
response  measures  against  another.  Suppose  we  administer  an 
arithmetic  aptitude  test  to  three  college  students,  who  are  required 
to  solve  as  many  addition  problems  as  possible  in  five  minutes. 
Suppose  further  that  student  A  solves  20  problems,  student  B 
solves  15,  and  student  C  solves  10,  These  scores  constitute  one 
measure  of  the  responses  of  each  student  to  the  stimuli  provided 
by  the  test  situation.  Now  imagine  that  the  same  test  is  given 
to  the  same  three  students  a  day  later,  and  the  scores  of  23,  18, 
and  13  are  obtained  by  A,  B,  and  C,  respectively.  The  results  of 
these  two  administrations  of  the  same  test,  if  plotted  graphically, 
would  look  like  Fig,  1:2.  This  constitutes  an  R-R  law  of  an  ex- 
tremely simple  and  elementary  sort. 

Nevertheless,  this  law  contains  the  essential  ingredients  for 
making  predictions  of  a  relatively  primitive  variety.  From  a  knowl- 
edge of  how  a  student  performs  on  the  first  day's  test  we  can 
predict,  with  a  certain  margin  of  error,  how  well  he  will  do  on 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION 


15 


24 


22  - 


-S20  - 


18  - 


"Si  16  - 


•2  14- 


12 


Student  A 


Student  B 


Student  C 


10 


15 
Addition  test  score  —  day  one 


20 


Fig.  1:2.  Hypothetical   R-R   relation    obtained   by   administering   the   same 
addition  test  to  the  same  subjects  on  each  of  two  successive  days. 


the  second  day.  This  assumes,  of  course,  that  the  relationship 
between  the  performances  on  days  one  and  two  is  essentially 
stable.  To  the  student  acquainted  with  elementary  test-construc- 
tion methods  it  will  be  apparent  that  this  simple  R-R  law  is  iden- 
tical in  form  to  the  relation  obtained  when  one  determines  the 
test-retest  reliability  of  a  test.  If  an  individual  gets  approximately 
the  same  absolute  or  relative  score  upon  repeated  administrations 
of  the  same  test,  or  comparable  forms  thereof,  the  test  is  said  to  be 
reliable.  It  measures  the  same  capacities  or  abilities  each  time 
it  is  administered. 

Different  K-K  laws  will  of  course  be  obtained  if  the  two  re- 
sponses are  measured  under  different  environmental  conditions 
and  by  different  tests.  To  illustrate,  the  three  students  of  the 
preceding  example  might  all  have  taken  the  same  elementary 
mathematics  course,  and  student  A  might  have  received  a  grade 
of  90,  student  B  a  grade  of  85,  and  C  a  grade  of  70.  When  these 
course  grades  are  plotted  against  the  first  day's  addition-test  scores 
for  the  same  students,  the  resulting  R-R  law  might  be  of  the  form 
shown  in  Fig.  1:3. 

An  R-R  law  such  as  this,  assuming  again  that  it  proves  to  be 
stable,  has  considerable  utility.  From  a  knowledge  of  a  student's 
score  on  the  addition  test  one  can  predict  his  course  grade,  and 


16 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


90 

Student  A 

0) 

^^-"''''^ 

•o 

^^^^ 

2 

^  85 

- 

•'''^ 

a, 

/Student  B 

3 

O 

A 

f 

o 

w  80 

X 

.o 

X 

ro 

E 

/ 

« 

X 

£  75 

/ 

ro 

S 

/ 

70 

-  *^tudent  C 

1                                                                 1 

10 


15 
Addition  test  score 


20 


Fig.  1:3.  Hypothetical  R-R  relation  between  the  scores  obtained  by  three 
students  on  a  simple  addition  test  and  the  grades  they  received  in  an  ele- 
mentary mathematics  course. 

vice  versa.  Readers  familiar  with  elementary  statistics  will  imme- 
diately recognize  this  relation  as  a  very  simple  scattergram  like 
those  used  in  connection  with  the  computation  of  coefficients  of 
correlation.  B<-B^  relationships  like  this  are  extensively  employed 
by  psychologists  who  work  in  the  areas  of  vocational  guidance, 
personnel  selection,  and  industrial  psychology.  If  one  can  success- 
fully predict,  from  the  results  of  a  short,  written  test,  how  well 
an  employee  will  do  in  a  certain  job  or  how  well  a  student  will 
perform  in  college,  substantial  savings  in  time  and  money  can  be 
effected. 

These  two  examples  of  K-K  laws  may  be  thought  of  as  lying 
at  the  extremes  of  a  continuum.  At  one  end  the  same  test  items 
are  presented  on  two  separate  occasions  in  the  same  environment, 
and  nearly  identical  responses  are  recorded.  At  the  other  extreme 
neither  the  responses  being  recorded  nor  the  two  test  situations  are 
markedly  similar.  By  making  the  test  conditions  and/or  the 
responses  the  same  or  different  we  can  achieve  a  wide  variety  of 
K-K  laws  that  may  be  placed  at  appropriate  positions  on  this 
continuum.  The  same  kinds  of  responses  might  be  recorded  on 
the  two  occasions,  but  the  testing  situations  might  be  quite  differ- 
ent. Or  the  situations  might  be  identical,  but  different  reactions 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION 


u 


might  be  recorded.  When  both  the  reactions  and  the  testing 
situations  differ,  as  in  our  second  example,  the  resultant  R-R 
function  is  like  those  obtained  in  the  process  of  validating  a  test. 
O-R  Relationships.  A  third  type  of  function  that  psychologists 
seek  to  establish  may  be  described  as  an  OR  law  (Spence,  1944). 
This  designation  refers  to  a  relation  in  which  the  independent 
variable  is  some  measurable  organic  characteristic,  property,  or 
state  of  an  organism  {or  of  different  groups  of  organisms),  and 
the  dependent  variable  is  some  reaction  or  response.  An  OR  law 
differs  from  an  S-R  law  in  that  the  independent  variable  in  the  S-R 
relationship  is  usually  a  physical  event  in  the  external  environment, 
whereas  in  the  OR  law  it  is  some  bodily  state  of  an  organism.  An 
example  of  an  OR  law  is  given  in  Fig.  1 :4  where  the  R  variable 
is  the  number  of  times  female  rats  crossed  an  electrified  grid  to 
reach  a  male  and  the  O  variable  is  the  stage  of  the  estral  cycle 
as  defined  by  histological  examinations  of  the  vaginal  mucosa. 
In  this  experiment  (Warner,  1927)  all  of  the  subjects  were  first 
tested  in  the  obstruction  box  and  were  then  classified  into  separate 
groups  according  to  the  results  of  the  histological  tests.  In  a  sense, 


ra  ^       oi2 


Stages  of  estral  cycle 

Fig.  1:4.  An  example  of  an  OR  law.  The  organic  variable  (O)  plotted  on 
the  base  line  is  the  stage  of  the  female  estral  cycle,  and  the  response  variable 
(R)  on  the  ordinate  is  the  number  of  times  the  female  rats  crossed  an  elec- 
trified grid  to  reach  a  male.  (Adapted  from  Warner,  1927.) 


18  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

estrous  level  was  thus  varied  by  choosing  subgroups  of  subjects 
who  fell  at  each  stage. 

Specific  values  of  an  O  variable  are  usually  determined  by  means 
of  standardized  physical  methods  of  measurement.  For  instance, 
the  basic  method  used  to  compute  percentage  of  alcohol  in  the 
blood  of  automobile  drivers  charged  with  intoxication  probably 
involves  chemical  analyses  of  blood  samples.  Under  certain  condi- 
tions, however,  comparable  results  could  be  obtained  from  be- 
havioral data.  Thus  if  a  reliable  functional  connection  (empirical 
law)  has  been  established  between  alcohol  percentage  and  scores 
on  a  line-walking  test,  then  O  values  can  be  estimated  from  scores 
on  the  behavioral  test. 

Other  Varieties  of  Functional  Relations.  The  S-R,  R-R,  and  OR 
relations  discussed  above  are  among  the  most  common  empirical 
functions  obtained  by  the  research  psychologist.  There  are  several 
others,  however,  which,  because  of  the  ways  we  have  chosen  to 
apply  our  labels,  do  not  qualify  precisely  as  S-R,  R-R,  or  OR  func- 
tions. For  instance,  the  familiar  learning  curve  relating  some 
measure  of  performance  to  number  of  trials  has  not  been  cited 
here  as  an  example  of  an  S-R  law,  though  it  is  often  so  regarded, 
since  the  physically  defined  properties  of  the  stimuli  in  the  learn- 
ing situation  are  not  systematically  varied  over  trials  but  are  held 
as  constant  as  possible.  Likewise,  relations  in  which  behavioral 
changes  are  plotted  against  the  passage  of  time,  e.g.,  speed  of 
movement  as  a  function  of  chronological  age  and  sensitivity  to 
light  as  a  function  of  time  in  darkness,  cannot  be  subsumed  easily 
under  any  of  the  types  of  laws  already  considered.  One  could 
readily  invent  new  alphabetical  abbreviations  for  laws  such  as 
these,  but  the  advantages  to  be  gained  therefrom  appear  to  be 
slight. 

Although  in  each  of  the  functions  described  above  a  response 
measure  was  plotted  on  the  ordinate  of  the  graph,  this  is  not  true 
of  all  psychological  laws.  For  example,  the  psychologist  might  be 
interested  in  determining  the  visual  thresholds  of  his  subjects 
under  conditions  where  both  the  duration  and  the  brightness  of 
a  test  light  are  systematically  varied.  The  empirical  function 
resulting  from  such  an  experiment  might  look  like  the  graph 
in  Fig.  1:5.  Here  the  intensity  of  the  test  light  is  plotted  along 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION 
0.03 
0.02 

S  0.01  h 


19 


0.001 


2  4 

Stimulus  intensity 

Fig.  1.5.  An  empirical  relation  in  which  physically  measured  values  of  the 
stimulus  are  plotted  on  both  dimensions.  Each  point  on  the  curve  represents 
a  visual  stimulus  whose  duration  and  intensity  are  such  that  it  is  seen  just 
50  per  cent  of  the  time.  {Adapted  from  Braunstein,  1923.) 


the  abscissa  and  its  duration  on  the  ordinate.  The  empirical 
points  tell  us  which  combinations  of  duration  and  intensity  result 
in  the  subject's  seeing  the  test  light  50  per  cent  of  the  times  on 
which  it  is  presented.  Thus  the  light  will  be  seen  for  half  the  time 
if  it  is  brief  and  bright,  or  for  half  the  time,  even  when  it  is  dim, 
if  it  is  presented  for  a  longer  time.  This  type  of  relation  differs 
from  the  S-R  variety  in  that  physically  measured  quantities  occupy 
both  the  ordinate  and  the  abscissa.  Moreover,  the  plotted  points 
do  not  represent  different  magnitudes  or  frequencies  of  a  response. 
Because  of  these  differences,  this  particular  sort  of  function  might 
best  be  described  as  a  modified  S-R  relation. 

Finally,  it  should  be  noted  that  functions  more  complicated 
than  either  the  simple  S-R  or  OR  laws  can  be  obtained  by  simul- 
taneously varying  both  the  condition  of  the  organism  and  some 
characteristic  of  the  stimulus  situation.  Relations  obtained  under 
such  conditions  might  be  termed  SO-R  laws,  since  the  dependent 
variable  (the  response)  is  a  joint  function  of  both  an  organic 
variable  and  an  environmental  one.  A  hypothetical  example  of 
this  kind  of  relation  is  presented  in  Fig.  1:6.  In  preparing  this 
graph  it  has  been  assumed  that  reaction  time  decreases  as  a 


20 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


Hypothetical 

levels  of 

ascending 

reticular 

system 

activity 


Stimulus  intensity 

Fig.  1:6.  Fictitious  data  depicting  SO-R  relations.  The  dependent  variable 
(reaction  time)  is  shown  as  varying  both  with  stimulus  intensity  and  amount 
of  general  neural  activity  in  the  ascending  reticular  activating  system. 


function  of  increasing  stimulus  intensity  but  that  the  function 
relating  the  two  variables  takes  a  different  form  depending  upon 
the  average  level  of  activity  of  the  brain-stem  reticular  formation. 
In  this  case  stimulus  intensity  is  the  principal  independent  variable, 
and  reticular-system  activity,  though  also  classifiable  as  an  in- 
dependent variable,  would  usually  be  described  as  a  parameter. 
This  combination-type  law  exemplifies  a  phenomenon  which 
statisticians  describe  as  an  interaction.  By  this  they  mean  that  the 
effect  of  stimulus  intensity  upon  reaction  time  depends  upon  the 
particular  level  of  the  third  factor,  reticular-system  discharges.  Al- 
though the  curves  of  Fig.  1:6  have  been  called  an  SO-R  relation, 
three  simple  and  distinct  laws  are  actually  plotted  on  one  graph. 
Each  law,  considered  alone,  is  an  S-R  law  specific  to  the  magnitude 
of  neural  excitation  present  at  the  time  of  its  determination.  Level 
of  reticular  outflow  could,  with  equal  justification,  have  been 
plotted  on  the  base  line  as  the  major  independent  variable,  with 
different  values  of  stimulus  intensity  constituting  the  parameter. 
To  maintain  a  consistent  terminology,  compound  laws  of  this 
latter  type  should  probably  be  termed  OS-R  relations. 

The  reader  should  note  that  if  the  three  values  plotted  vertically 
at  any  point  on  the  abscissa  of  Fig.  1 :6  were  to  be  replotted  as  a 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION  21 

separate  graph,  the  result  would  be  an  OR  law  relating  reaction 
time  to  three  values  of  the  independent  O  variable  (reticular 
activity),  with  stimulus  intensity  held  constant.  Similarly,  a  re- 
plotting  of  the  values  at  any  abscissa  point  on  an  OS-R  relationship 
would  yield  an  S-R  law,  the  value  of  O  being  held  constant.  The 
complexity  of  any  of  these  relationships  could  be  increased  by 
introducing  other  factors  as  additional  parameters.  The  two- 
dimensional  curves  of  Fig.  1 :6  could  be  expanded  into  three-dimen- 
sional surfaces  by  simultaneously  varying  some  other  factor  in 
addition  to  stimulus  intensity  and  reticular  outflow.  The  number 
of  variables  that  might  be  included  is  limited  only  by  the  experi- 
menter's ability  to  control  and  measure  them  and  to  analyze  and 
comprehend  the  results. 

General  Approaches  to  the  Study  of  Behavior 

As  noted  in  our  introductory  paragraphs,  the  psychologist's  fun- 
damental task  is  to  study  and  to  attempt  to  understand  the  be- 
havior of  organisms.  Although  some  progress  toward  this  goal 
might  be  attained  by  a  careful  study  of  historical  and  literary 
writings,  most  students  of  behavior  believe  that  primary  reliance 
should  be  placed  upon  objective  observations  of  the  activities  of 
organisms  and  of  environmental  or  other  factors  that  are  corre- 
lated with  such  actions.  When  the  data  obtained  from  such 
observations  are  collated  and  organized,  the  results  are  empirical 
relations  of  the  several  varieties  we  have  just  described. 

But  no  matter  how  many  functional  relations  are  established 
by  the  psychologist,  he  is  seldom  satisfied  to  cease  his  inquiries  at 
that  point.  He  may  be  pleased  to  learn  that  reaction  time  decreases 
as  a  function  of  increasing  stimulus  intensity,  but  he  is  even  more 
pleased  if  he  can  gain  additional  insights  into  the  factors  that 
determine  this  function.  Hence  he  strives  to  learn  precisely  why 
reaction  time  declines  as  stimulus  intensity  increases.  In  his  efforts 
to  understand  behavior,  therefore,  he  often  finds  it  rewarding  to 
go  beyond  his  initial  empirical  data,  to  speculate  about  relations 
not  yet  discovered,  and  to  search  for  new  facts  and  new  contin- 
gencies. 

Given  a  well-established  empirical  law,  the  psychologist  may 


22  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

follow  two  principal  paths  toward  the  enrichment  of  his  under- 
standing of  the  law.  One  of  these,  which  involves  detailed  analyses 
and  descriptions  of  the  bodily  mechanisms  of  behaving  organisms, 
is  usually  described  as  the  "physiological  approach."  The  second, 
often  characterized  as  the  "behavioral  approach,"  leads  to  further 
study  of  the  range  of  conditions  under  which  the  law  holds  and 
to  the  search  for  "explanatory"  laws  in  which  only  behavioral 
and  experimental  variables  are  contained.  These  two  approaches 
are  not  mutually  exclusive,  and  many  investigators  follow  both, 
but  they  are  suflBciently  different  to  warrant  separate  discussion. 

The  Physiological  Approach.  The  student  of  behavior  who 
adopts  this  general  plan  of  action  tries,  where  possible,  to  interpret 
his  empirical  laws  by  appealing  to  known  facts  concerning  an 
organism's  physical  structure  and  its  functions.  He  endeavors  to 
explain  his  findings  in  terms  of  knowledge  and  concepts  derived 
from  the  work  of  the  physiologist,  the  physiological  psychologist, 
the  anatomist,  the  biochemist,  and  the  biophysicist.  Given  an 
empirical  relation  between  a  response  measure  and  a  stimulus 
variable,  he  may  inquire  into  the  details  of  the  receptor  mechan- 
isms by  which  the  organism  senses  the  stimulus,  or  he  may  try  to 
trace  the  neural  connections  intervening  between  the  receptor 
and  the  final  response.  This  approach  is  primarily  favored  by 
those  who  concentrate  on  the  study  of  the  sensory  processes  of 
vision,  audition,  olfaction,  and  gustation.  Its  value  is  indicated  by 
the  tremendous  strides  toward  the  understanding  of  such  processes 
that  have  been  made  during  the  past  few  decades.  And  the  desir- 
ability of  continued  work  along  these  lines  is  strongly  supported 
by  the  widespread  conviction  among  behavior  scientists  that  living 
organisms,  though  descriptively  unique  and  astonishingly  complex, 
are  nevertheless  physical  systems  or  assemblies  of  such  systems. 
There  are  many  reasons  for  believing,  therefore,  that  in  the  future 
our  explanations  of  complex  human  and  animal  behavior  will  be 
considerably  broadened  by  the  identification  of  the  neurophys- 
iological  and  physicochemical  systems  whose  functions  make  that 
behavior  possible. 

The  Behavioral  Approach.  Investigators  whose  activities  exem- 
plify the  behavioral  approach  typically  do  not  concern  themselves 
with  the  question  of  why  an  empirical  law  is  what  it  is  in  the 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION  23 

light  of  the  structural  characteristics  of  the  behaving  organism. 
They  do  not,  as  a  rule,  apply  the  terms  or  concepts  of  the  physiol- 
ogist or  anatomist  to  the  explication  of  empirical  relations  between 
behavior  and  other  variables  and  seldom  refer  to  such  specific 
bodily  entities  as  muscles,  tendons,  glands,  and  nerve  fibers. 
Instead,  their  attention  is  concentrated  upon  what  they  may 
describe  as  molar  behavior,  meaning  relatively  gross  movements 
or  goal-oriented  actions  of  the  entire  organism.  For  the  psychol- 
ogist who  favors  this  approach  reasonably  satisfactory  explanations 
of  behavior  can  be  wrung  from  a  knowledge  of  the  wide  assort- 
ment of  experimental  variables  that  affect  behavioral  laws,  from 
information  as  to  the  kinds  and  magnitudes  of  these  effects,  and 
from  supraordinate  laws  that  tie  simpler  laws  together  in  a  mean- 
ingful fashion.  Gaps  in  this  network  of  explanatory  laws  are  filled, 
in  part,  by  "guessed-at  laws"  (Spence,  1948)  and  by  the  introduc- 
tion of  "explanatory"  concepts  such  as  intelligence,  personality 
traits,  ego-involvement,  associative  connections,  inherited  reactive 
tendencies,  unconscious  desires,  cognitions,  motives,  and  drives. 
These  terms  refer,  though  often  in  a  relatively  vague  fashion,  to 
properties,  states,  predispositions,  or  characteristics  of  organisms 
that  function  as  determinants  of  behavior.  Their  basic  meanings, 
for  purposes  of  communication  within  the  context  of  the  scientific 
vocabulary,  can  be  given  by  explicit  definitions,  but  failure  to 
provide  such  definitions  is  commonplace.  The  broader  meanings 
of  these  terms,  in  their  roles  as  integrative  or  explanatory  elements 
of  interpretive  networks  or  theories,  derive  from  the  varieties  and 
kinds  of  empirical  and  conceptual  relations  into  which  they  enter 
as  constituents.  In  following  the  behavioral  approach,  therefore, 
one  deals  primarily  with  molar  rather  than  molecular  behavior; 
one  investigates  the  ways  in  which  an  assortment  of  variables 
affects  behavior  and  modifies  the  laws  relating  it  to  other  variables; 
and  in  attempting  to  explain  behavior,  one  tends  to  appeal  to  pos- 
tulated processes  or  intervening  variables  whose  principal  function 
is  that  of  summarization  and  integration.  The  concepts  of  drive 
and  motivation,  to  which  we  now  turn,  are  often  encountered  in 
the  writings  of  those  who  subscribe  to  the  behavioral  approach, 
and  generally  speaking,  occupy  a  position  of  considerable  im- 
portance therein. 


24  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

The  Problem  of  Motivation 

There  is  no  question  but  that  the  idea  of  motivation  or  some 
similar  notion  appears  in  almost  every  systematic  account  of 
behavior.  Contemporary  psychological  theorists  as  well  as  their 
more  philosophically  oriented  predecessors  have  frequently  relied 
upon  some  kind  of  moving,  pushing,  driving,  or  energizing  force 
or  agency.  The  ubiquity  of  the  concept  of  motivation,  in  one 
guise  or  another,  is  nevertheless  surprising  when  we  consider  that 
its  meaning  is  often  scandalously  vague.  It  is  not  our  intention  to 
tabulate  all  of  the  many  motivationlike  terms  that  have  been  used 
or  to  summarize  the  history  and  development  of  the  concept.  Such 
summaries  may  be  found  in  the  writings  of  Troland  (1928), 
Young  (1936),  Gardiner,  Metcalf,  and  Beebe-Center  (1937), 
Lindzey  (1959),  and  Madsen  (1959),  as  well  as  in  widely  scattered 
briefer  discussions.  It  will  be  sufficient  to  note  that,  depending 
upon  the  particular  writer  consulted,  motivation  can  be  conscious 
or  unconscious;  it  can  be  the  same  as,  or  different  from,  drive; 
it  may  or  may  not  guide  behavior;  and  all  motives  can  be  either 
learned  or  instinctive.  Moreover,  arguments  can  be  found  to  sup- 
port the  view  that  motivation  is  both  crucial  to  behavior  and  a 
useless  concept,  that  it  is  simply  the  energy  that  moves  the  body, 
or  that  it  is  identical  with  the  neural  discharges  of  specific  central 
nervous-system  structures.  We  thus  find  ourselves  in  the  position 
of  trying  to  deal  with  an  allegedly  vital  factor  in  the  face  of  violent 
disagreements  as  to  its  origins,  its  essential  nature,  and  its  particu- 
lar roles  as  a  behavior  determinant.  The  evaluation  and  reconcilia- 
tion, where  possible,  of  these  divergent  opinions  and  contradictory 
views  is  of  central  concern  to  the  student  of  motivation  and  is 
a  significant  facet  of  the  problem  of  motivation. 

Within  the  field  of  psychology,  broadly  defined,  factors  or  vari- 
ables known  to  affect  behavior  in  one  way  or  another  are  grouped 
into  a  number  of  loosely  defined  classes,  to  each  of  which,  by 
more  or  less  common  agreement,  a  distinguishing  name  is  assigned. 
These  names  frequently  coincide  with  the  traditional  chapter 
headings  of  our  elementary  texts.  For  instance,  when  behavior  is 
found  to  vary  with  changes  in  sensory  stimulation,  the  psychologist 
says  he  is  concerned  with  the  problems  of  sensation  or  perception. 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION  25 

If  frequency  and  diversity  of  previous  experiences  prove  to  be 
important  variables,  the  area  of  study  may  be  labeled  learning  or 
fatigue  or  adaptation,  depending  on  other  information.  If  verbally 
administered  instructions  influence  behavior,  the  research  is  con- 
cerned with  set  or  expectancy.  In  like  manner,  other  areas  of 
investigation  are  given  names  such  as  conflict,  emotion,  transfer 
of  training,  remembering,  and  of  course,  motivation  or  drive. 

Although  significant  and  relevant  variables  have  been  success- 
fully isolated  and  identified  in  some  of  these  areas,  this  is  less  true 
for  motivation  than  one  might  wish.  Many  of  the  fundamental 
problems  in  this  field  arise  when  serious  inquiries  are  launched 
into  the  nature  of  motivational  variables.  To  bring  order  into 
our  thinking  we  need  criteria  for  deciding  that  a  given  variable 
is  indeed  affecting  behavior  "motivationally";  we  need  to  know 
whether  motivational  variables  can  be  identified  in  terms  of  in- 
trinsic properties  as  well  as  by  means  of  their  effects  on  behavior; 
and  we  need  to  identify  variables  that  may  function  both  motiva- 
tionally  and  nonmotivationally.  The  task  of  obtaining  such  knowl- 
edge is  clearly  relevant  to  the  general  motivational  problem,  and 
much  of  the  remainder  of  this  book  is  concerned  with  this  matter. 

It  is  also  necessary  to  note  that  in  recent  years  more  and  more 
investigators  have  raised  the  serious  question  of  whether  a  concept 
of  motivation  is  really  required  by  a  comprehensive  theory  of 
behavior.  The  student  of  motivation  must  also  devote  a  portion 
of  his  time,  therefore,  to  the  analysis  and  evaluation  of  arguments 
and  evidence  bearing  on  this  issue.  This  means  that  he  must  con- 
cern himself  not  only  with  the  problem  of  motivation  but  also 
with  more  generally  comprehensive  behavior  theories.  The  con- 
struction and  evaluation  of  theories  in  which  motivation  plays 
an  important  role  is  as  much  a  part  of  the  general  problem  of 
motivation  as  the  gathering  of  empirical  data  and  the  identification 
of  significant  variables. 

Summary 

In  this  chapter  we  have  tried  to  set  the  stage  for  our  subsequent 
discussions  of  motivation  by  describing  in  general  terms  some  of 
the  activities,  procedures,  and  goals  of  the  student  of  behavior. 


26  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

The  attainment  of  satisfactory  explanations  of  behavior  is  described 
as  the  psychologist's  principal  aim  and  the  observing  and  recording 
of  the  activities  of  organisms  as  his  initial  task.  The  raw  data  with 
which  he  works  consist  of  tabulations  of  the  frequency  of  occur- 
rence of  certain  actions,  their  magnitude,  their  rate,  or  their  dura- 
tion. These  data  are  unique  in  that  they  are  contingent  upon  the 
presence  of  living  organisms,  but  the  methods  used  in  collecting 
them  are  essentially  identical  with  those  of  the  natural  sciences. 

Since  no  two  responses  are  ever  exactly  alike,  the  investigator, 
in  gathering  his  basic  data,  must  deal  with  classes  or  groups  of 
responses.  The  boundaries  of  the  class  may  be  quite  restricted,  as 
in  the  case  where  the  activity  of  only  a  single  muscle  group  or 
gland  is  recorded,  or  wide  enough  to  encompass  complex  purposive 
and  goal-directed  acts.  The  setting  of  class  limits  is  dictated  solely 
by  individual  preference  and  by  the  scientific  and/or  practical 
utility  of  the  research  findings.  Irrespective  of  where  the  boundaries 
are  set,  however,  lawful  regularities  in  behavior  cannot  be  expected 
unless  the  conditions  of  observation  have  been  specified  precisely 
in  advance. 

Collections  of  raw  facts,  valuable  as  they  are,  do  not  contain  all 
of  the  ingredients  required  for  adequate  scientific  explanations. 
Unelaborated  descriptions  of  a  subject's  behavior  must  be  sup- 
plemented by  accounts  of  environmental  events,  by  records  of 
previous  experiences  and  reactions,  by  observations  of  the  behavior 
of  other  organisms,  and  by  measurements  of  physiologically  de- 
fined states  or  characteristics  of  the  subject.  The  discovery  of 
dependable  empirical  laws  relating  behavior  to  other  variables 
such  as  these  is  a  necessary  step  toward  explanation  and  under- 
standing. Identifying  abbreviations  such  as  S-R,  R-R,  and  O-R  are 
often  applied  to  special  groups  of  these  laws. 

Because  the  component  variables  of  any  empirical  relation  must 
be  independent  of  one  another,  it  is  sometimes  held  that  one 
cannot  legitimately  speak  of  stimulus-response  laws,  since  it  is 
also  alleged  that  responses  and  stimuli  can  be  defined  only  in 
terms  of  one  another.  An  analysis  of  this  matter  leads  to  the 
conclusion  that,  given  precise  criteria  of  observation,  responses 
can  be  identified  and  recorded  reliably  even  when  observers  know 
nothing  of  the  stimuli  that  elicit  the  responses.  Similarly,  the 


PSYCHOLOGIST'S  TASK  AND  PROBLEM  OF  MOTIVATION  27- 

conclusion  is  reached  that  environmental  events  such  as  hghts, 
sounds,  and  odors  can  be  identified  and  measured  by  physical 
procedures,  irrespective  of  whether  these  events  are  correlated  with 
responses.  To  apply  the  term  stimuli  to  events  having  known 
response  contingencies  is  simply  to  reassert  the  facts  of  dependency. 

The  discovery  of  empirical  relations  represents  an  important 
step  toward  scientific  explanation,  but  the  questions  of  why  a 
given  law  holds  or  why  it  takes  a  particular  form  also  demand 
answers.  In  seeking  solutions  some  investigators  find  it  profitable 
to  study  the  physiological  and  neurological  bases  of  behavior  and 
may  be  said  to  follow  the  physiological  approach.  Others,  in  adopt- 
ing a  behavioral  approach,  confine  their  search  for  answers  to  data 
at  the  behavioral  level  of  description.  Their  techniques  involve 
the  discovery  and  evaluation  of  further  related  laws,  the  manipula- 
tion of  additional  variables  to  determine  the  range  of  factors 
crucial  to  the  stability  of  laws,  and  the  introduction  of  summariz- 
ing or  explanatory  concepts  such  as  habit  strength,  personality 
traits,  intelligence,  inhibition,  and  motivation.  The  meanings  of 
these  terms  are  given  both  by  explicit  definitions  within  the  scien- 
tific language  and  by  the  variety  of  useful  relations  into  which 
they  enter  as  constituents. 

Finally,  although  a  concept  of  motivation  or  some  similar  notion 
is  to  be  found  in  nearly  ever}'  theoretical  account  of  behavior,  an 
amazing  divergence  of  opinion  exists  as  to  the  nature  and  function 
of  motivation.  A  significant  portion  of  the  general  problem  of 
motivation  arises,  therefore,  from  the  need  to  clarify,  evaluate, 
and,  wherever  possible,  to  reconcile  these  disparate  conceptions. 
Other  critical  aspects  of  the  problem  are  the  identification,  selec- 
tion, and  manipulation  of  motivational  variables,  the  critical  ap- 
praisal of  the  utility  of  the  concept,  and  the  formulation  of 
adequate  theories. 


CHAPTER 


2 


Intervening  Variables  and 
the  Definition  and 
Measurement  of  Drive 

As  WE  HAVE  SEEN  in  the  previous  chapter,  investigators  who  at- 
tempt to  formulate  systematic  accounts  of  behavior  often  appeal 
to  intermediary  explanatory  factors  such  as  intelligence,  personality, 
field  forces,  associative  strength,  libido,  instinct,  frustration,  and 
drive.  Various  general  names  have  been  suggested  for  these  inter- 
mediaries, e.g.,  symbolic  constructs,  explanatory  concepts,  and 
hypothetical  constructs,  but  the  term  intervening  variables  (Tol- 
man,  1932)  is  perhaps  the  most  common.  The  qualifying  adjective 
"intervening"  is  used  to  convey  the  notion  that  the  postulated 
states,  conditions,  or  processes  intervene  between  behavior  and  its 
observable  correlates  or  antecedents.  Since  these  variables  cannot 
be  observed  directly,  their  meanings  are  provided  by  explicit  defini- 
tions and  by  their  functional  relations  within  the  context  of 
general  theories  of  behavior.  Inasmuch  as  the  introduction  of  such 
conceptions  is  widespread,  and  since  motivation  is  a  prominent 
example,  it  is  desirable  at  this  point  to  consider  the  question  of 
why  students  of  behavior  have  felt  impelled  to  make  venturesome 

28 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE  29 

and  sometimes  unbridled  speculations  about  such  unseen  entities. 
One  rather  obvious  reason  for  the  use  of  intervening  variables, 
even  when  ill  defined  and  loosely  connected  to  a  theory,  is  that 
the  users  regard  them  as  having  real  value  as  summarizing  or 
interpretive  concepts.  The  psychologist  feels  that  he  has  explained 
behavior  in  a  way  that  would  otherwise  have  been  impossible. 
Alternatively,  some  explanatory  concepts  ( and  certainly  motivation 
is  one  of  these)  are  elements  of  the  nonscientific  language  of  the 
layman  and  may  have  been  passed  uncritically  from  one  generation 
of  psychologists  to  another  without  regard  for  their  scientific 
worth.  One  cannot,  unfortunately,  ask  the  psychologists  of  the 
last  fifty  years  why  they  have  felt  the  need  to  incorporate  inter- 
vening variables  into  their  theories.  We  can,  however,  examine 
the  kinds  of  data  with  which  they  have  worked  to  determine 
whether  those  data  or  their  interrelations  have  special  character- 
istics requiring  the  postulation  of  intermediary  concepts.  It  is 
difficult  to  believe  that  the  universality  of  such  notions  as  asso- 
ciative strength,  drive,  and  the  like,  can  be  due  merely  to  chance, 
and  it  is  possible,  therefore,  that  intervening  variables  have,  in  a 
sense,  been  thrust  upon  psychologists  by  the  nature  of  the  em- 
pirical facts  with  which  they  have  dealt. 

Empirical  Relations  Tending  to  Evoke  Motivational 
or  Other  Intermediary  Concepts 

The  Evocation  of  Vigorous  Responses  by  Weak  Stimuli.  Con- 
cepts such  as  drive,  set,  or  expectancy  are  especially  likely  to 
appeal  to  psychologists  when  subjects  exhibit  violent  reactions  to 
weak  stimuli.  The  creaking  of  a  wind-blown  shutter  may  evoke 
intense  reactions  of  fear  or  escape  from  the  timid  explorer  of  an 
abandoned  house;  the  faint  nighttime  stirrings  of  a  sick  child  may 
galvanize  its  mother  into  action;  and  the  smell  of  a  female  dog 
in  heat  may  rouse  the  male  to  excited  and  extensive  exploratory 
action. 

Disproportionalities  of  this  sort  are  common  among  S-R  laws, 
and  though  they  may  assume  a  variety  of  forms,  a  single  example 
will  suffice.  In  this  instance,  the  relation  is  such  that  increases  in 
the  intensity  of  the  stimulus  produce  no  response  whatever  until 


30 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

100 


o)  50  - 


12         3         4         5         6         7         8 

Stimulus  intensity 

Fig.  2:1.  Diagrammatic  representation  of  a  stepwise  disproportion  between 
the  intensity  of  a  stimulus  and  the  strength  of  the  response  it  evokes.  The 
units  on  both  axes  are  fictitious. 


a  certain  level  is  reached,  whereupon  the  reaction  appears  with 
maximum  strength.  Further  increases  in  the  strength  of  the  stimu- 
lus have  no  effect  upon  the  response.  A  stepwise  function  of  this 
type  is  shown  in  Fig.  2:1,  where  the  intensity  of  the  stimulus  has 
been  plotted  on  the  horizontal  axis  (abscissa)  and  the  vigor  of 
reaction  on  the  vertical  axis  (ordinate).  The  units  of  both  scales 
are  fictitious.  A  function  of  this  type  might  be  obtained  in  the 
case  of  verbally  presented  instructions  or  commands.  If  the  instruc- 
tions are  too  faint  to  be  heard,  the  receiving  organism  does  noth- 
ing; but  when  they  become  loud  enough  to  be  clearly  understood, 
the  hearer  reacts  appropriately.  Beyond  the  point  of  intelligibility, 
further  increases  in  the  intensity  of  the  commands  may  have  little 
or  no  effect  on  the  behavior  they  elicit. 

In  dealing  with  a  relation  of  this  sort,  the  psychologist  may 
entertain  the  view  that  the  stimulus  controls  a  separate  source 
of  energy  which  is  released  in  the  response,  and  hence  may  find 
it  desirable  to  introduce  a  motivationlike  concept.  It  must  be 
emphasized,  however,  that  disproportionality,  as  such,  can  also  be 
explained,  perhaps  more  adequately,  by  nonmotivational  concepts 
such  as  set,  expectancy,  or  associative  strength.  Motivation  may  be 
suggested  by  data  such  as  these,  but  it  is  not  required. 

Variability  of  Response  in  the  Presence  of  Constant  Stimulating 
Conditions.  The  observation  that  an  individual's  behavior  varies 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE 


31 


from  time  to  time  in  an  environment  whose  physical  characteristics 
have  not  apparently  changed  is  commonplace  and  provides  strong 
inducement  for  the  use  of  one  or  another  intervening  concept. 
Suppose,  for  example,  that  the  running  speed  of  a  rat  is  measured 
in  the  same  straight  runway  on  three  different  occasions  and  that 
at  each  successive  trial  his  speed  increases.  The  elements  of  this 
situation  are  represented  in  Fig.  2:2,  with  the  large  S  at  the  left 
of  the  diagram  denoting  the  constant  environment  provided  by 
the  alley  and  the  three  Rs  at  the  right,  with  their  respective  sub- 
scripts, indicating  the  running  speeds  as  measured  on  the  three 
trials. 

Presented  with  data  of  this  kind,  the  investigator  may  wonder 
why  the  rat  did  not  run  at  exactly  the  same  speed  on  the  three 
occasions.  Since  the  physical  properties  of  the  runway  were  iden- 
tical throughout  the  experiment  and  the  rat  was  presumably 
handled  in  the  same  way  on  each  occasion,  performance  inequali- 
ties cannot  be  explained  by  appealing  to  variations  in  the  stimulus 
situation.  At  this  point  the  psychologist  might  assume  that  the 
rat  differed  from  trial  to  trial  with  respect  to  some  unknown 
state  or  characteristic,  and  that  this  characteristic  was  responsible 
for  the  recorded  changes  in  running  speed.  As  a  first  step  toward 
accounting  for  his  observations,  therefore,  he  might  postulate  the 
existence  of  a  behavior-determining  fac- 
tor which  he  simply  calls  factor  X.  This 
leads  him  to  modify  the  relations  in  Fig, 
2:2  to  include  three  values  of  X.  This 
alteration  is  shown  in  Fig.  2:3,  where 
the  greatest  amount  or  degree  of  X,  i.e,, 
Xhigh,  is  associated  with  the  highest 
speed  (Rfast),  the  intermediate  level  of 

X  with  Rmoderate,  and  loW  X  with  Rsiow 

From  this,  the  scientist  may  wish  to  as- 
sert that  speed  of  running  depends  upon 
level  or  amount  of  factor  X, 

Not  much  has  been  accomplished,  of 
course,  if  the  interpretive  process  stops 
at  this  point.  A  conception  as  bare  as 
this  must  be  strengthened  and  enriched 


Fig.  2:2.  Schematic  illus- 
tration of  intraindividual 
variation  in  response  de- 
spite a  carefully  maintained 
constancy  of  the  external 
environment  (S).  The  sub- 
scripts to  the  three  capital 
Rs  indicate  the  running 
speeds  of  a  single  rat  when 
tested  on  three  occasions 
in  the  same  straight-alley 
maze. 


32 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


^R. 


Fig.  2:3.  Schematic  diagram  show- 
ing the  postulated  introduction  of 
three  levels  of  a  hypothetical  be- 
havior determinant  (X)  designed 
to  "explain"  differences  in  the  re- 
sponses of  a  single  organism  that 
has  been  tested  under  identical 
stimulating  conditions  (S)  on  three 
occasions. 


by  additional  assumptions  as  to  the  properties  of  factor  X,  the  pre- 
cise ways  in  which  it  functions  to  determine  speed  of  running,  and 
its  relations  to  experimental  variables  and  other  intervening  con- 
cepts. These  are  matters  of  substantial  importance  to  the  behavior 
scientist,  but  their  consideration  must  be  postponed  for  the  pres- 
ent. 

Enlarging  upon  this  example  of  response  variation  in  the  pres- 
ence of  constant  stimulus  conditions,  we  note  that  the  relation, 
in  its  basic  form,  applies  to  differences  between  the  performances 
of  different  individuals  as  well  as  to  intraindividual  variability. 
Thus  if  one  rat  runs  faster  than  a  second,  and  the  second  faster 
than  a  third,  when  all  are  tested  in  the  same  situation,  an  inter- 
vening, performance-determining  variable  can  perhaps  be  profitably 
invoked. 

An  instance  of  what  seems  to  qualify  as  a  special  case  of  response 
variability  in  the  presence  of  constant  stimulation  is  found  in 
the  observation  that,  when  food  is  presented  to  an  animal,  it  some- 
times eats  and  sometimes  does  not;  or,  of  two  supposedly  identical 
animals,  one  may  eat  and  the  other  not.  Skinner  (1938),  in  his 
treatment  of  motivation,  states  that  this  is  the  basic  phenomenon 
giving  rise  to  the  concept  of  drive.  This  particular  behavior  could 
be  represented  by  separate  diagrams  like  those  of  Figs.  2:2  and  2:3, 
but  this  is  not  necessary.  Suppose,  for  example,  that  the  rat  whose 
performance  is  shown  in  Fig.  2:2  instead  of  running  slowly,  simply 
does  not  run  at  all.  His  failure  to  run  might  then  be  attributed  to 
a  complete  lack  of,  or  negligible  strength  of,  factor  X.  If  the 
behavior  is  exhibited,  X  is  postulated  to  be  present;  if  no  behavior 
occurs,  X  is  assumed  to  be  effectively  absent. 

Equality  or  Constancy  of  Behavior  in  the  Presence  of  Normally 
Effective  Changes  in  the  External  Stimulus  Situation.  Under  some 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE  33 

Fig.  2:4.  Three  different  stimulus 
situations,  i.e.,  the  brightnesses  of 
an  alley  on  three  different  occasions, 
are  represented  at  the  left  by  the 
three  Ss.  It  has  been  assumed  that       o        . — >.p    ^    . 

"^bright  ^•"•moderate 

these  unequal  brightnesses  all  lead 
to  equal    (and  moderate)    rates  of 

running    in    three    individual    rats,       Smoderate ^-^  moderate 

even  though  rats  usually  run  faster 
(also  assumed)  under  bright  than 
under  dim  illumination.  Sji,^  ^-Rmoderate 

conditions  subjects  may  behave  alike  even  though  they  are  ex- 
pected to  react  quite  differently,  and  an  individual,  in  situations 
that  typically  lead  to  quite  different  responses,  may  show  behav- 
ioral constancy.  As  in  our  preceding  examples,  empirical  data  of 
this  sort  tend  to  lead  to  the  introduction  of  intervening  variables. 
To  give  a  specific  illustration,  imagine  that,  normally,  the  more 
brightly  an  alley  maze  is  lighted  the  faster  a  rat  will  run.  Suppose 
further  that  an  available  alley  can  be  illuminated  with  three  de- 
grees of  brightness  and  that  three  rats  from  the  same  litter  are 
tested  therein,  one  under  each  level  of  illumination.  If  all  three 
animals  run  at  the  same  speed,  we  would  have  an  instance  of 
response  equality  in  the  presence  of  normally  effective  changes  in 
the  external  situation.  This  is  represented  schematically  in  Fig.  2:4. 

Were  such  results  obtained,  the  psychologist  might  be  tempted 
to  explain  them  by  assuming  that  the  three  rats  differed  with 
respect  to  a  factor  X.  He  might  postulate  that  the  rat  tested  under 
bright  illumination  ran  more  slowly  than  animals  typically  do 
because  its  level  of  X  was  low.  Similarly,  the  rat  tested  under 
dim  illumination  might  have  run  faster  than  expected  because  of 
an  excessive  amount  of  X.  By  assuming  that  differences  in  X  have 
counteracted  the  effects  of  illumination  in  this  way  one  might 
explain  the  failure  to  obtain  the  expected  differences  in  response. 
The  elements  of  this  interpretation  are  represented  diagrammat- 
ically  in  Fig.  2:5. 

In  concluding  this  section,  we  must  note  that  many  additional 
examples  might  be  cited  of  representative  empirical  relations  that 
seem  to  call  for  the  introduction  of  intermediary  constructs.  For 
example,  as  Skinner  (1938),  Hull  (1943),  and  Miller  (1959), 
among  others,  have  observed,  when  several  different  experimental 


34  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

^bright  -^low  ^-"n 


-^Rr 


■^dim  high 


X..„.  ^Rr 


Fig.  2:5.  Showing  how  equahty  of  response  in  spite  of  normally  effective 
variations  in  the  brightness  of  a  stimulus  might  be  explained  by  postulating 
differing  levels  of  an  intervening  variable,  factor  X.  Variations  in  brightness 
and  variations  in  factor  X  are  inversely  related  when  evaluated  with  respect 
to  their  effects  on  speed  of  running. 


variables  are  found  to  affect  behavior  in  the  same  way,  the  postu- 
lation  of  an  intervening  process  common  to  all  of  them  may  prove 
desirable.  Furthermore,  intervening  constructs  should  not  be  re- 
garded as  unique  to  S-R  relations.  Equally  imperative  reasons  for 
the  use  of  such  concepts  may  arise  from  the  study  of  OR,  R-R, 
and  other  relations. 


Circular  Reasoning  in  the  Use  of  intermediary  Concepts 

When  properly  introduced  into  a  psychological  theory,  interven- 
ing variables  often  serve  a  useful  function  as  conceptual  devices. 
When  carelessly  defined  and  irresponsibly  used,  however,  they  not 
only  contribute  nothing  to  our  understanding  but  may  even  be 
gravely  misleading.  In  the  preceding  section,  several  examples 
were  given  of  the  kinds  of  empirical  relations  that  seem  to  give 
rise  to  intermediary  concepts,  and  it  was  observed  that  in  attempt- 
ing to  explain  such  relations  one  might  begin  by  attributing  the 
behavior  to  variations  in  an  unidentified  factor  X.  One  must  go 
well  beyond  this  point,  however,  to  achieve  satisfactory  explana- 
tions. It  is  especially  unfruitful  to  introduce  different  degrees  of 
factor  X  on  the  ground  that  different  responses  are  observed,  and 
then  to  turn  about  and  appeal  to  the  inferred  values  of  X  to  "ex- 
plain" the  variations  in  behavior.  One  may  assume  that  some  ani- 
mals run  faster  than  others  because  they  have  more  of  factor  X, 
but  this  is  trivially  circular  if  the  only  basis  one  has  for  asserting 
they  have  more  X  is  the  fact  that  they  run  more  rapidly.  From 
this  it  becomes  clear  that  the  introduction  of  factor  X  in  the  man- 


V 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE  35 

ner  diagramed  in  Figs.  2:3  and  2:5  has  in  only  the  most  superficial 
sense  explained  the  observed  behavior. 

There  are  many  instances  within  psychology  of  circular  reason- 
ing in  the  use  of  intermediary  constructs.  For  instance,  one  fre- 
quently encounters  the  statement  that  individuals  behave  in  differ- 
ent ways  in  the  same  environment  because  their  perceptions  are 
not  the  same.  This  reasoning  is  typically  circular  since  the  percep- 
tions are  defined  by  the  same  behavior  that  is  allegedly  determined 
by  the  perceptions.  Other  terms  such  as  ability,  constitutional  dif- 
ferences, personality  traits,  and  motivation  are  likewise  often  in- 
troduced and  used  in  this  uncritical  way.  Psychology  is  not  alone, 
however,  in  its  occasional  use  of  circular  arguments.  Social  scien- 
tists, for  example,  have  tried  to  explain  the  gregarious  behavior  of 
sheep  by  postulating  an  instinct  to  be  gregarious  (the  herding 
instinct),  but  the  existence  of  the  instinct  has  usually  been  based 
entirely  upon  the  observed  gregarious  behavior. 

Defining   Intervening  Variables  so  as 
to  Avoid  Circular  Explanations 

As  we  have  seen,  the  introduction  of  intermediary  concepts  into 
one's  theory  must  be  done  in  such  a  fashion  as  to  avoid  circular 
interpretations.  This  can  be  accomplished,  in  principle,  by  making 
certain  that  one's  definition  of  an  intervening  variable  is  com- 
pletely independent  of  the  specific  responses  that  are  assumed  to 
be  determined  by  that  variable.  This  requirement  can  be  met  by 
basing  the  definition  upon  ( 1 )  the  subject's  previous  experiences, 
(2)  the  responses  he  makes  in  other  test  situations,  (3)  one  or 
another  of  his  organic  states,  or  (4)  the  stimuli  impinging  upon 
him.  Each  of  these  ways  of  achieving  independence  in  definition 
is  examined  in  more  detail  in  the  paragraphs  that  follow,  and  in 
every  case  the  intervening  variable  is  simply  called  factor  X.  The 
problem  of  whether  factor  X  should  be  described  as  drive,  habit 
strength,  cognition,  set,  or  whatever,  will  be  discussed  at  a  later 
point  in  this  chapter. 

1.  An  Intervening  Variable  May  Be  Defined  in  Terms  of  Dif- 
ferences in  Experience  Prior  to  the  Test  Situation.  In  essence,  this 
method  of  defining  an  intervening  concept  requires  that  we  have 


36  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

some  knowledge  concerning  an  organism's  life  history.  For  in- 
stance, if  subjects  who  respond  differently  when  tested  in  the  same 
environmental  situation  can  be  shown  to  have  had  different  ex- 
periences or  treatments  prior  to  the  test,  then  those  experiences 
can  be  used  to  define  a  factor  X. 

To  illustrate,  suppose  we  have  carried  out  an  experiment  like 
that  depicted  in  Fig.  2:2,  using  three  rats  rather  than  one,  and 
have  found  that  they  all  run  at  different  speeds  in  the  straight 
runway.  Let  us  suppose  also  that  our  subjects  are  known  to  differ 
with  respect  to  the  amount  of  time  that  has  elapsed  since  they 
were  last  fed.  Perhaps  the  fast  rat  has  not  eaten  for  48  hours,  the 
moderate-speed  rat  for  24  hours,  and  the  slow  rat  for  4  hours.  This 
type  of  information  satisfies  our  need  for  independent  data  upon 
which  to  base  the  definition  of  factor  X.  The  deprivation  histories 
of  the  animals  in  this  case  are  correlated  with,  but  measured  in- 
dependently of,  running  speed.  Different  degrees  of  factor  X  can 
be  inferred  from,  or  defined  by,  measured  differences  in  time  of 
deprivation,  and  differences  in  running  speed  can  be  "explained" 
by  appealing  to  differences  in  factor  X  as  thus  defined.  Figure  2:6 
illustrates  schematically  the  way  in  which  several  values  of  factor 
X  would  be  inferred  from  the  different  deprivation  histories  of  the 
three  animals. 


^R. 


^R. 


^R. 


Frc.  2:6.  A  diagrammatic  representation  of  the  manner  in  which  three  dif- 
ferent antecedent  conditions.  Ads,  AC24,  and  AC4,  which  designate  48,  24, 
and  4  hours  of  food  deprivation,  respectively,  may  serve  as  the  basis  for  de- 
fining high,  medium,  and  low  levels  of  factor  X,  in  turn.  Differences  in  factor 
X  defined  in  this  way  are  assumed  to  be  responsible  for  the  fact  that  an  iden- 
tical stimulus  situation  (S)  elicits  fast,  moderate,  and  slow  rates  of  running 
from  three  otherwise  comparable  animals. 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION   OF   DRIVE  37 

In  this  figure,  which  is  simply  a  modification  of  Fig.  2:3,  AC48 
denotes  the  antecedent  condition  of  being  without  food  for  48 
hours  at  the  time  of  the  running-speed  test,  and  AC24  and  AC4 
refer,  respectively,  to  the  conditions  of  being  without  food  for 
24  and  for  4  hours. 

2.  An  Intervening  Variable  May  Be  Defined  in  Terms  of  Dif- 
ferences in  Performance  on  Some  Task  Other  than  That  Used  in 
the  Test  Situation.  Consider  again  the  laboratory  situation  in 
which  the  responses  of  different  subjects  are  found  to  vary  though 
the  testing  conditions  are  held  constant,  but  suppose  that  we  now 
have  no  way  of  determining  the  past  history  of  our  subjects.  Under 
such  circumstances  it  would  be  impossible  to  base  our  inferences 
about  factor  X  upon  differences  in  the  antecedent  conditions  to 
which  the  organisms  had  been  exposed.  Such  a  situation  is  not 
so  likely  to  occur,  of  course,  in  a  laboratory  where  the  animals  are 
under  constant  supervision,  but  it  often  occurs  with  human  sub- 
jects. In  most  cases  we  simply  do  not  know  what  the  distinctive 
antecedent  events  have  been. 

Whenever  we  are  unable  to  control  a  subject's  previous  history 
or  to  get  an  accurate  estimate  of  it,  we  can  still  achieve  an  inde- 
pendent definition  of  an  intervening  variable  by  measuring  the 
subject's  responses  in  a  second  test  situation.  For  instance,  we 
might  take  three  rats  and  place  them  in  separate  activity  cages 
and  record  the  amount  of  activity  they  exhibit  during  a  standard 
test  period.  Differences  in  amount  of  activity  could  then  be  used 
to  define  levels  of  factor  X,  and  these,  in  turn,  might  be  invoked 
to  explain  differences  in  running  speed  in  the  straight  alley.  This 
method  of  obtaining  an  independent  definition  involves  the  formu- 
lation of  an  R-R  relationship,  and  is  represented  schematically  in 
Fig.  2:7. 

In  this  diagram  S2  represents  the  activity-cage  situation,  and  Si 
represents  the  alley  maze.  R^  R^,  and  R^  indicate  high,  moderate, 
and  low  levels  of  activity,  respectively.  The  dashed  lines  from  R^, 
R^,  and  R^  to  the  three  factor-X  levels  indicate  the  process  of  de- 
fining inequalities  of  this  factor  in  terms  of  the  responses  exhibited 
in  the  activity  cages. 

3.  An  Intervening  Variable  May  Be  Defined  in  Terms  of  Dif- 
ferences in  an  Organic  Variable.  This  way  of  attaining  independ- 


38  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


^Rr 


Fig.  2:7.  A  paradigm  to  represent  the  method  whereby  differences  in  in- 
tensity or  vigor  of  response  (R\  R^,  R")  in  one  testing  situation  (S2)  can 
yield  independent  definitions  of  the  levels  of  an  intervening  variable.  The 
defined  levels  of  factor  X  then  serve  to  "explain"  variations  in  response  to  a 
different  situation  (Si). 


ent  definitions  involves  the  measurement  of  some  physiological 
condition  of  the  organism  (O  variable),  such  as  per  cent  normal 
body  weight,  blood-sugar  level,  stage  of  estral  cycle,  total  neural 
activity  in  the  brain  at  some  point,  or  skin  resistance.  Once  such 
measurements  have  been  obtained,  they  can  be  examined  to  deter- 
mine whether  they  are  stable  indexes  of  inter-  or  intraindividual 
differences.  If  the  three  rats  of  our  previous  example  were  found 
to  differ  reliably  with  respect  to  blood-sugar  level,  such  physiologi- 
cally measured  values  could  be  used  as  the  basis  for  an  independ- 
ent definition  of  factor  X. 

Although  an  O  variable  has  been  described  as  an  organic  state 
or  characteristic  of  an  organism,  numerous  instances  of  such  states 
are  difficult  to  distinguish  from  responses.  To  take  a  single  exam- 
ple, a  subject's  heart  rate  might  remain  relatively  constant  over  a 
period  of  inactivity  and  hence  might  be  termed  an  O  variable.  But 
the  individual  contractions  of  the  heart  are  clearly  consequences 
of,  or  responses  to,  antecedent  neural  impulses.  Similarly,  changes 
in  mean  heart  rate  might  appropriately  be  catalogued  as  responses. 
Were  these  responses  used  to  define  drive  differences,  the  proce- 
dure would  become  an  instance  of  the  second  method  we  have 
just  considered.  In  cases  like  this  the  distinction  between  the  sec- 
ond and  third  methods  tends  to  disappear.  Fortunately,  this  does 
nothing  to  destroy  the  independence  of  either  method. 

4.  An  Intervening  Variable  May  Be  Defined  by  Referring  to 
Differences  in  Stimulus  Conditions.  When  the  characteristics  of 
the  test  situation  are  not  the  same  from  subject  to  subject,  or 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE  39 

from  time  to  time  for  the  same  subject,  these  differences  can  be 
employed  to  obtain  independent  definitions  of  intervening  vari- 
ables. As  an  illustration,  consider  an  experiment  in  which  the  eye- 
blink  response  is  being  conditioned  to  a  faint  light  {CS)  by 
paired  presentations  of  the  light  and  a  puff  of  air  {UCS)  directed 
at  the  cornea.  If  a  strong  puff  is  used  for  one  group  of  subjects  and 
a  weak  puff  for  another,  one  can  assert  that  the  level  of  factor  X 
is  a  function  of  strength  of  puff,  the  strong-puff  group  being  de- 
fined as  having  a  higher  level  of  factor  X  than  the  weak-puff 
group.  Thus  the  definition  of  factor  X  is  independent  of  the  re- 
sulting behavior,  i.e.,  the  frequency  of  conditioned  eyelid  responses 
exhibited  by  the  two  groups. 

The  important  elements  involved  in  this  defining  procedure 
are  summarized  in  Fig.  2:8.  Here  the  upper  line  denotes  the  con- 
ditions for  the  strong-puff  group  and  the  lower  line  those  for  the 
weak-puff  group. 

Thus  far  in  this  chapter  we  have  discussed  some  of  the  reasons 
why  behavior  theorists  tend  to  introduce  intermediary  constructs 
into  their  theories,  the  dangers  of  circular  interpretations  resulting 
from  inappropriate  definitions  of  intermediary  constructs,  and  wavs 
of  structuring  definitions  so  as  to  avoid  such  circularity.  In  the 


CS 


GROUP  I 

■w      f^Ty 

■'^  high 

r-    f^ix  frequent 

/ 
/ 

GROUP  n 

■V 

■ta    fT' 

.-'^low 

"    ^"infrequent 

/ 
/ 

/ 

CS 


Fig.  2:8.  Elements  involved  in  defining  factor  X  in  terms  of  differences  in 
the  intensity  of  the  unconditioned  stimulus  in  an  eyelid-conditioning  experi- 
ment. The  greater  frequency  of  conditioned  responses  (CRfrequent)  exhibited 
by  Group  I  is  attributed  to  the  higher  level  of  factor  X  resulting  from  the 
use  of  a  more  intense  unconditioned  stimulus  ( UCSg trong). 


40  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

specific  examples  given,  we  have  purposely  refrained  from  sub- 
stituting a  specific  label  such  as  motivation  for  the  colorless  sym- 
bol, factor  X.  Our  next  task,  therefore,  is  to  consider  the  problem 
of  how  one  decides  whether,  and  under  what  conditions,  partic- 
ular names,  such  as  habit  strength,  expectancy,  drive,  or  moti- 
vation, might  be  substituted  for  factor  X. 

Naming  Intervening  Variables 

Although  meaningful  names,  instead  of  abstract  symbols,  are 
typically  applied  to  intervening  variables  in  theories  of  behavior, 
the  use  of  such  names  is  not  necessary,  and  may  sometimes  be 
dangerous.  The  meaning  of  a  factor  X  is  given  by  explicit  defini- 
tion within  the  scientific  vocabulary  and  by  the  nature  and  variety 
of  laws  of  which  it  is  a  part.  Moreover,  the  scientific  meaning  of 
any  other  term  that  might  be  substituted  for  factor  X  is  given  in 
precisely  the  same  ways.  Thus  to  say  that  factor  X  is  "really"  drive 
adds  nothing  to  our  understanding  unless  drive  has  already  been 
more  specifically  defined  or  has  acquired  more  significant  second- 
ary meanings  within  the  broader  context  of  behavior  theory.  It  is 
possible,  of  course,  that  the  use  of  a  meaningful  term  in  place 
of  a  svmbol  may  facilitate  communication  among  investigators, 
but  it  may  also  lead  to  misunderstanding  because  of  different  pre- 
conceptions as  to  what  is  meant  by  the  "meaningful"  term.  It  is 
also  likely  that  in  the  present  state  of  psychology  words  must  be 
used  because  we  lack  so  much  in  the  way  of  quantification.  Not 
until  extensive  and  interrelated  equations  and  functional  relations 
have  been  established  do  symbols  become  predominant. 

If  one  does  set  about  providing  a  name  for  factor  X,  the  name 
must  be  secondary  to,  and  contingent  upon,  the  naming  of  experi- 
mental variables.  To  make  this  point  concrete,  let  us  consider 
again  the  hypothetical  experiment  in  which  three  rats  are  found 
to  run  at  different  speeds  when  tested  in  the  same  straight  alley. 
When  the  experiment  is  performed,  if  we  have  no  information 
about  our  subjects  save  that  provided  by  the  animals'  behavior,  we 
can  neither  define  factor  X  appropriately  nor  rename  it.  But  should 
we  discover  that  the  three  subjects  have  been  given  different 
amounts  of  practice  in  running  through  the  alley,  then  practice 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE  41 

becomes  a  manipulated  variable  capable  of  providing  an  independ- 
ent definition  of  factor  X.  And  since  practice,  by  convention,  is 
said  to  affect  learning,  factor  X  might  then  be  called  a  learning  or 
habit  factor.  In  like  manner,  if  we  were  to  discover  that  our  sub- 
jects differ  with  respect  to  hours  of  food  deprivation,  factor  X 
might  be  defined  in  terms  of  this  variable,  as  in  our  first  example 
of  independent  definitions,  and  might  be  renamed  drive.  Generally 
speaking,  therefore,  the  particular  name  one  applies  to  any  factor 
X  stems  from  the  variables  used  in  its  definition  and  from  our 
customary  ways  of  naming  the  effects  of  those  variables  on  per- 
formance. To  describe  factor  X  as  a  motivational  factor  implies 
that  it  has  been  defined  in  terms  of  certain  variables,  which,  by 
common  agreement,  are  said  to  have  motivational  effects.  But 
agreements  are  not  as  common  as  one  might  wish,  and  we  must 
turn,  therefore,  to  the  task  of  specifying  possible  criteria  for  the 
identification  of  motivational  variables. 

Criteria  for  the  Identification  of  Motivational  Variables 

At  the  end  of  Chapter  1  it  was  observed  that  the  numerous  vari- 
ables or  conditions  affecting  behavior  are  customarily  classified 
into  several  broad  groups.  In  elementary  textbooks,  chapters  on 
sensation  and  perception  treat,  in  the  main,  of  the  effects  on  be- 
havior of  stimulus  variables;  chapters  on  instincts  and  develop- 
ment tend  to  stress  genetic  variables;  and  chapters  on  learning, 
transfer  of  training,  and  memory  elevate  the  variables  of  practice 
and  experience  to  a  place  of  primary  importance.  Questions  often 
arise  as  to  whether  certain  variables  belong  in  one  or  another  of 
these  groups,  but  apparently  fewer  differences  of  opinion  exist  as 
to  the  limits  of  group  membership  than  as  to  the  limits  of  the 
class  of  motivational  variables.  Attempts  to  identify  motivational 
variables  lead  to  considerable  controversy,  and  widely  accepted 
criteria  for  making  decisions  in  case  of  doubt  are  nonexistent.  The 
specific  criteria  listed  below  cannot,  therefore,  be  regarded  as  either 
definitive  or  exhaustive,  or  as  representative  of  all  possible  views. 

1 .  A  Variable  Is  Often  Said  to  Be  Motivational  if  It  Facilitates 
or  Energizes  a  Wide  Variety  of  Responses.  This  criterion,  which 
is  probably  more  widely  accepted  than  any  other,  stresses  the  fact 


42  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

that  the  presence  of  certain  variables  may  alter  the  frequency, 
latency,  or  vigor  of  a  number  of  responses.  For  example,  a  mod- 
erate degree  of  muscular  tension,  produced  by  squeezing  a  hand 
dynamometer,  is  considered  motivational  because  it  facilitates 
verbal  learning,  mental  arithmetic,  the  knee  jerk,  and  a  variety  of 
other  responses  (Courts,  1942).  Similarly,  food  deprivation  appears 
to  be  motivating,  especially  in  animals,  since  it  often  intensifies 
reactions  of  running,  sniffing,  exploring,  clawing,  biting,  whimper- 
ing, and  even  drinking.  Thus  it  is  the  nonspecific,  broadly  gen- 
eralized effects  of  certain  variables  that  seem  to  mark  them  oflF  as 
motivational  rather  than  something  else. 

2.  A  Variable  Is  Commonly  Said  to  Be  Motivating  if  the  Learn- 
ing of  New  Responses  Seems  to  Depend  upon  Appropriate  Ma- 
nipulations of  That  Variable.  This  criterion  involves  the  assump- 
tion that  a  reduction  in  the  drive  state  associated  with  the  variable 
is  rewarding  and  that  responses  followed  by  such  a  reduction  will 
tend  to  be  learned.  If  a  period  of  stimulation  by  an  intense  light 
is  terminated  as  soon  as  an  albino  rat  presses  a  lever,  the  probabil- 
ity of  his  making  the  same  response  on  a  future  occasion  may  be 
increased.  The  variable  of  intense  light  is  then  a  motivator  because 
its  offset  brings  about  or  is  correlated  with  the  acquisition  of  a 
new  response. 

3.  A  Variable  Is  Sometimes  Regarded  as  Motivational  if 
Changes  in  That  Variable  Lead  to  the  Weakening  of  Certain  Re- 
sponses. Strong  stimuli  tending  to  elicit  aversive  or  avoidant  be- 
havior are  clear  examples  of  variables  that  meet  this  criterion.  A 
child  may  have  a  strong  tendency  to  reach  out  to  touch  a  brightly 
burning  match,  but  the  reaching  response  is  likely  to  be  aban- 
doned if  it  is  followed  by  a  painful  burn.  This,  of  course,  is  the 
phenomenon  typically  subsumed  under  the  heading  of  punish- 
ment, and  the  hot  flame  is  treated  as  a  motivational  variable  be- 
cause of  its  efficacy  in  leading  to  the  weakening  of  the  reaching 
reaction. 

4.  A  Variable  Is  Occasionally  Labeled  Motivational  Simply 
Because  No  Other  Designation  Seems  Suitable.  If  the  results  of 
certain  experimental  treatments  cannot  be  explained  by  appealing 
to  principles  of  learning,  perception,  genetics,  or  whatever,  one 
may  be  tempted  to  assert  that  the  treatments  have  led  to  changes 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION   OF  DRIVE  43 

in  level  of  drive.  For  instance,  altering  a  variable  such  as  depriva- 
tion time  may  result  in  relatively  immediate  and  precipitous 
changes  in  performance.  If  these  changes  are  more  abrupt  than 
we  might  predict  from  the  suppositions  that  learning  or  inhibitory 
processes  are  involved,  we  may  wish  to  assume  that  the  variable 
is  functioning  motivationally.  This  criterion  is  perhaps  the  least 
satisfactory  of  all,  however,  since  the  variable  is  named  by  exclu- 
sion. By  this  standard  a  variable  is  motivational  if  it  is  not  affect- 
ing behavior  as  we  would  expect  it  to  be  affected  by  other 
variables  for  which  we  already  have  meaningful  names.  For  this 
criterion  to  be  of  real  utility,  we  would  have  to  have  much  clearer 
notions  than  we  now  have  of  what  each  of  the  many  nonmotiva- 
tional  variables  is  and  of  how  it  functions  as  a  determinant  of 
behavior. 

It  has  been  asserted  in  the  previous  section  that,  generally  speak- 
ing, variables  are  regarded  as  motivational  if  they  aflfect  behavior 
in  ways  that  are  commonly  said  to  be  motivational.  The  four 
criteria  listed  above  may  be  regarded  as  a  tentative  summary  of 
some  of  the  "motivational  ways"  in  which  behavior  may  be  al- 
tered by  variables.  At  the  present  stage  of  our  knowledge,  of 
course,  it  would  be  foolhardy  to  maintain  that  all  students  of  be- 
havior would  approve  of  this  list  or  that  any  one  of  its  loosely  struc- 
tured criteria  is  entirely  adequate. 

Before  leaving  this  topic  we  should  note  that  certain  criteria  for 
the  identification  of  motivational  variables  are  clearly  not  satis- 
factory. For  example,  an  increase  in  the  probability  or  vigor  of  a 
single  reaction  following  the  manipulation  of  a  variable  is  not 
suitable  since  the  same  behavioral  effect  might  be  ascribed,  per- 
haps with  equal  reason,  to  learning,  expectancy,  perception,  or 
whatever.  Improvement  in  performance,  as  such,  does  not  point 
unerringly  to  motivation  as  the  only  responsible  variable.  It  is  also 
clear  that  the  intrinsic  properties  of  a  variable  do  not  suffice  to 
distinguish  it  as  motivational.  An  allegedly  motivating  electric 
shock  may  be  identical  in  its  physical  properties  to  a  shock  used 
in  studying  tactual  sensitivity.  In  like  manner,  one  cannot  rely 
upon  the  descriptive  properties  of  behavior  alone  for  clear  guidance 
as  to  what  is  motivational.  The  appearance  of  an  emotional  tan- 
trum in  a  frustrating  situation  may  mean  either  heightened  motiva- 


44  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

tion  or  simply  the  transfer  to  that  situation  of  a  previously  well- 
learned  mode  of  adjustment  to  frustration. 

One  is  under  no  obligation,  of  course,  in  doing  research,  to 
specify  whether  a  variable  is  or  is  not  motivational.  One  can,  for 
instance,  study  the  effect  of  failure  instructions  upon  the  per- 
formance of  human  subjects  even  when  one  is  uncertain  as  to 
how  the  variable  should  be  classified.  Such  instructions  could 
operate  as  stimuli  to  elicit  habits  or  sets;  they  could  change  the 
subjects'  attitudes;  or  they  could  alter  motivation.  The  theoretical 
implications  of  the  research  would  perhaps  be  enriched  if  one 
could  decide  among  these  alternatives,  but  the  empirical  results 
would  be  valuable  even  if  a  decision  were  never  made. 

Operational  and  Significant  Definitions  of  Drive 

Operational  Definitions.  In  an  earlier  section  of  this  chapter, 
mention  was  made  of  several  techniques  for  introducing  constructs 
such  as  drive  into  one's  theory  without  having  to  refer,  in  the  defi- 
nition itself,  to  the  behavior  to  be  explained  by  the  construct.  In 
exemplifying  these  methods  the  definitions  were  never  formally 
presented,  but  each  could  have  been  stated  in  such  a  way  as  to 
qualify  as  an  operational  definition.  The  need  for  operational  defi- 
nitions of  concepts  and  terms  has  been  heavily  emphasized  in  recent 
years  by  psychologists  seeking  a  maximum  degree  of  precision  and 
rigor.  While  the  phrase  operational  definition  may  sound  formida- 
ble, it  is  essentially  nothing  more  than  a  clear  definition.  It  is  a 
definition  in  which  the  conditions  under  which  the  concept  is  to 
be  used  have  been  clearly  and  unambiguously  stated  in  terms  of 
operations  or  activities  of  observing  and  recording  that  can  be 
made  by  any  competent  observer.  Thus  the  statement,  "Degree  of 
drive  in  the  rat  is  defined  in  terms  of  the  time  during  which  the 
rat  has  been  without  food,"  is  a  good  (operational)  definition.  It 
states  precisely  what  operations,  i.e.,  measuring  and  recording  the 
time  during  which  a  rat  does  not  eat,  must  be  carried  out  to  satisfy 
the  definition.  Presumably,  all  observers  who  have  stop  watches  or 
other  time-measuring  devices  can  agree  as  to  how  much  time  has 
elapsed  since  the  rat  has  been  fed.  From  the  definition,  therefore, 
they  can  agree  that  rat  X  has  a  higher  drive  than  rat  Y  if  rat  X 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND   DEFINITION   OF   DRIVE  45 

has  been  without  food  for  a  longer  time  than  rat  Y.  When  a  con- 
cept is  defined  operationally,  therefore,  it  is  defined  in  terms  of 
communicable,  repeatable  manipulations  and  observations  that 
can  be  performed  by  any  reasonably  competent  observer.  It  is  a 
definition  whose  meaning  within  the  scientific  vocabulary  is  clear 
because  the  meanings  of  its  constituent  words  and  symbols  can  be 
given  in  terms  of  observable  properties  of  physical  objects  and  the 
relations  among  them.  Many  of  the  definitions  of  drive  that  have 
been  seriously  proposed  in  the  past  fail  to  meet  the  test  of  opera- 
tional precision,  but  allusions  to  them  still  appear  frequently  in 
psychological  literature.  Taken  seriously  and  uncritically,  nonopera- 
tional  definitions  lead  to  little  but  confusing  and  interminable 
arguments. 

Although  an  operational  definition  of  drive  in  terms  of  hours  of 
food  deprivation  may  seem  sensible  on  intuitive  grounds,  many 
other  possible  definitions,  though  less  obviously  reasonable,  are 
equally  acceptable  as  to  their  operational  bases.  For  example,  there 
is  no  a  priori  reason  why  the  strength  of  a  man's  drive  cannot 
be  defined  in  terms  of  the  length  of  his  nose  as  measured  under 
certain  carefully  prescribed  conditions.  To  assert  that  men  with 
long  noses  have  a  strong  drive  and  those  with  short  noses  a  weak 
drive  is  a  perfectly  clear  operational  definition.  It  is  operationally 
adequate  because  it  specifies  the  conditions  under  which  the  terms 
strong  drive  and  weak  drive  are  to  be  used.  Any  person  with  a 
suitable  ruler  and  a  little  patience  can  presumably  measure  the 
noses  of  a  number  of  individuals,  and  the  data  he  obtains  will 
correlate  positively  with  those  obtained  by  other  nose  measurers. 
If  the  measurement  conditions  of  the  definition  are  carefully  met, 
all  members  of  a  subject  population  can,  with  a  high  degree  of 
agreement  among  observers,  be  separated  into  relatively  long-  and 
short-nosed  groups.  And  the  observers  can  then  agree  that,  by 
definition,  one  group  of  subjects  has  a  strong  drive  and  the  other 
a  weak  drive.  In  a  similar  manner,  one  could  formulate  opera- 
tionally precise  definitions  of  drive  in  terms  of  the  color  of  a 
rat's  fur,  in  terms  of  the  ratio  of  its  weight  to  the  amount  of  curva- 
ture of  its  nose,  in  terms  of  the  length  of  steps  it  takes  while  run- 
ning, or,  in  fact,  in  terms  of  any  conceivable  quantities  one  could 
measure.  As  long  as  the  measurements,  discriminations,  or  other 


46  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

activities  that  must  be  performed  by  an  observer  are  specified 
precisely  by  the  definition,  and  those  activities  can  indeed  be 
executed  in  the  same  way  and  with  the  same  outcome  by  independ- 
ent competent  observers,  the  definition  satisfies  the  requirement 
that  it  be  operational. 

Significant  Definitions.  The  mere  fact  that  a  definition  is  indeed 
operational  does  not  guarantee  that  the  construct  thus  defined 
will  be  generally  useful  or  theoretically  significant.  Drive  can  be 
operationally  defined  in  terms  of  the  length  of  a  man's  nose,  and 
nose  length  can  be  measured  with  reasonable  precision.  But  it 
would  be  foolish  to  use  such  a  definition  for  very  long  if  one  could 
not  show  that  nose  length  meets  one  or  more  of  the  criteria  of 
motivational  variables  or  is  meaningfully  related  to  other  variables. 
Thus,  nose  length  provides  a  useless  definition  of  drive  unless  it 
can  be  shown  that  long-nosed  subjects  behave  as  though  they  were 
more  highly  motivated  than  short-nosed  subjects.  Irrespective  of 
the  elegance  of  our  operational  definitions,  they  are  of  little  value 
until  the  defined  concepts  have  been  shown  to  have  sensible,  clari- 
fying relations  to  other  concepts  and  to  other  facts.  A  definition 
is  useful  or  significant  when  the  laws  of  which  the  defined  concept 
is  a  component  fit  meaningfully  into  a  broader  theoretical  struc- 
ture and  serve  to  illuminate  a  variety  of  lower-order  laws  or  func- 
tions. Nonoperationally  defined  constructs  can  probably  never  be 
scientifically  significant;  but  a  construct  can  be  immaculately  opera- 
tional without  being  helpful  in  any  way. 

A  distinction  is  thus  drawn  between  (1)  the  basic  scientific- 
vocabulary  meaning  of  a  concept,  as  the  result  of  its  having  been 
defined  in  specific  operational  terms,  and  (2)  the  additional, 
more  significant  meanings  it  may  acquire  if  it  proves  to  be  useful 
or  helpful.  A  clear  understanding  of  these  two  kinds  of  meanings 
(Bergmann,  1944;  Spence,  1948)  helps  to  eliminate  confusion  in 
dealing  with  psychological  problems,  and  we  shall  have  occasions 
throughout  the  remainder  of  this  text  to  refer  to  them  again. 

Since  drive  or  any  other  construct  can  be  defined  operationally 
in  many  different  ways,  decisions  as  to  which  definition  will  be 
used  must  rest  upon  the  utility  of  the  concept.  Of  several  opera- 
tional definitions,  the  one  that  is  most  useful  or  significant  is 
clearly  to  be  preferred.  And  whenever  utility  can  be  enhanced  by 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE  A7 

altering  a  definition,  then  such  remedial  measures  are  clearly  in- 
dicated. Unfortunately,  we  cannot  state  in  precise  language  what 
is  meant  by  maximum  utility  or  significance,  and  hence  cannot 
point  to  any  single  definition  of  drive  as  the  one  that  is  most  use- 
ful. The  process  of  evaluating  significance  and  of  refining  defini- 
tions is  an  ever-continuing  one,  and  widely  satisfying  answers  can 
probably  not  be  expected  for  many  years.  It  is  even  possible  that 
no  definition  of  drive  will  ever  turn  out  to  be  useful  and  that  the 
concept  will  disappear  entirely  from  our  scientific  vocabulary. 

The  Problem  of  Drive  Quantification 

General  Considerations.  The  problems  involved  in  attempting 
to  quantify  or  to  measure  the  strength  of  a  drive  or  motive  are 
extremely  complex,  and  any  comprehensive  discussion  of  them 
would  take  us  far  beyond  the  intended  scope  of  this  book.  But 
the  "measurement  issue"  is  repeatedly  raised  in  discussions  of 
motivation,  and  since  it  is  closely  allied  to  the  definitional  matters 
we  have  just  considered,  it  seems  desirable  to  examine  it  briefly 
at  this  point. 

The  bases  of  our  concern  with  measurement,  both  in  the  affairs 
of  our  daily  lives  and  in  our  scientific  pursuits,  have  been  discussed 
quite  frequently  and  need  only  to  be  touched  upon  here.  We  are 
constantly  making  judgments  about  the  properties  or  qualities  of 
objects  and  situations,  and  our  behavior  is  often  guided  by  the 
outcome  of  these  judgments.  A  room  may  be  judged  to  be  "too 
warm,"  so  we  remove  our  jackets;  an  automobile  is  seen  to  be 
approaching  the  intersection  "too  rapidly,"  so  we  step  back  until 
it  has  passed;  our  friends  may  be  judged  to  be  "too  angry"  at  the 
moment,  so  we  may  defer  a  request  for  a  favor.  In  many  instances, 
judgments  of  this  kind,  in  which  we  simply  affirm  or  deny  the 
presence  of  qualitative  characteristics,  provide  adequate  support 
for  the  normal  activities  of  living.  In  other  circumstances,  however, 
and  especially  in  the  pursuit  of  scientific  knowledge,  we  find  it 
necessary  to  ascertain,  if  possible,  the  precise  degree  of  the  prop- 
erty or  characteristic  about  which  judgments  are  made.  Thus  we 
may  need  to  know,  not  just  that  a  rat  has  become  heavier  when 
fed  certain  foods,  but  whether  it  has  gained  10  grams  or  50  grams; 


48  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

we  may  need  to  know  whether  a  subject's  skin  resistance  has 
changed  by  100  or  1,000  ohms;  whether  one  subject  is  more  highly 
motivated  than  another,  and  if  so,  by  how  much. 

In  the  case  of  motivation  or  drive,  as  in  many  other  instances, 
answers  to  such  questions  as  "how  much,"  or  "how  intense,"  are 
fundamental  to  an  increase  in  the  accuracy  of  our  judgments  about 
motivation  and  to  the  discovery  of  comprehensive  explanatory 
principles.  Not  until  these  answers  can  be  given  shall  we  be  in  a 
position  to  formulate  principles  or  theories  capable  of  being  un- 
ambiguously confirmed  or  refuted  (Cohen  and  Nagel,  1934). 
When  we  can  say  that  an  individual  has  a  certain  amount  or 
strength  of  drive  we  have  substituted  quantitative  distinctions  for 
qualitative  ones  and  have  made  an  important  first  step  toward 
the  measurement  of  the  attribute  or  property  of  drive. 

Acknowledged  authorities  on  the  topic  of  measurement,  though 
they  differ  with  respect  to  a  number  of  issues,  hold  comparable 
views  as  to  what  constitutes  the  essence  of  measurement.  Broadly 
conceived,  measurement  is  the  process  of  assigning  numerals  to 
events,  objects,  or  the  properties  of  objects,  in  accordance  with 
clearly  specified  rules  and  procedures.  It  is  a  process  through  which 
experimentally  demonstrable  properties  or  relations  of  objects  or 
systems  are  juxtaposed  against  a  numerical  system  having  corre- 
sponding properties  and/or  relationships.  As  Stevens  (1951)  has 
so  aptly  phrased  it,  when  we  measure  ".  .  .  we  deputize  the  nu- 
merals to  serve  as  representatives  for  a  state  of  affairs  in  nature 
.  .  ."  (p.  23). 

From  these  general  statements  about  measurement,  it  follows, 
for  example,  that  the  heights  of  a  number  of  discernibly  different 
individuals  have  been  measured  when  we  have  applied  yardsticks 
or  other  length-measuring  devices  to  these  individuals  in  certain 
agreed-upon  ways,  and  when,  as  a  consequence  of  these  experi- 
mental operations,  we  have  allocated  one  numeral  to  each  individ- 
ual. By  the  same  token,  it  would  be  permissible  to  say  that  we 
have  measured  the  strength  of  a  drive  or  motive  when,  by  fol- 
lowing certain  operational  procedures  or  rules,  we  have  been  able 
to  assign  numerals  to  different  organisms  that  are  presumed  to 
possess  different  degrees  of  drive. 

In  actual  practice,  however,  any  of  several  different  rules  and 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE  49 

procedures  might  be  followed  in  attempting  to  assign  numerals  to 
objects  or  individuals  possessing  a  certain  property.  As  a  conse- 
quence, one  cannot  speak  simply  of  just  one  kind  or  variety  of 
measurement.  Typically,  at  least  two,  and  sometimes  four,  types  of 
measurement  are  described,  depending  on  the  kinds  of  operations 
that  can  be  performed  with  the  property  being  measured,  on  the 
existence  of  related  numerical  laws,  and  on  the  types  of  mathe- 
matical transformations  that  can  be  applied  to  the  measured  data. 

Let  us  now  consider  several  of  these  kinds  of  measurement  as 
they  might  relate  to  the  problem  of  quantifying  drive  or  motiva- 
tion. 

Counting.  Perhaps  the  simplest  example  of  what  some  writers 
describe  as  a  crude  sort  of  "measurement"  is  that  in  which  in- 
stances of  the  phenomenon  under  study  are  counted  or  enumer- 
ated. By  the  use  of  a  standard  set  of  ordered  symbols,  such  as  the 
series  of  numerals  1,  2,  3,  etc.,  we  can,  by  pairing  off  one  instance 
of  the  phenomenon  against  each  numeral,  determine  whether 
there  are  more  instances  of  the  event  in  one  situation  or  under  one 
set  of  conditions  than  in  another.  Thus  we  determine  whether 
there  are  more  students  in  classroom  A  than  in  classroom  B  by  the 
simple  expedient  of  counting  the  students  in  each  room.  Counting 
satisfies  the  broad  criteria  of  measurement  because  it  involves 
assigning  the  numeral  1  to  a  particular  student,  the  numeral  2  to 
another,  and  so  on,  until  all  of  the  students  have  been  given  a 
number.  If  the  last  numeral  assigned  to  classroom  A  stands  higher 
in  the  series  of  numerals  than  the  one  last  assigned  to  classroom 
B,  we  can  conclude  that  A  contains  more  students  than  B.  This 
procedure  will  not  be  successful,  of  course,  unless  we  have  some 
means  of  unequivocally  identifying  the  individual  students  so  that 
no  two  students  will  be  assigned  the  same  numeral  and  no  student 
fails  to  get  a  numeral. 

This  elementary  method  of  measurement  might  be  applied  to 
the  quantification  of  drive  in  the  following  manner.  Since  count- 
ing cannot  be  successful  unless  we  can  recognize  the  things  or 
properties  to  be  counted,  our  initial  step  must  be  to  set  up  definite 
criteria  for  determining  whether  an  individual  is  motivated.  For 
this  purpose  we  might  choose  a  simple  operational  definition  such 
as  "an  animal  is  motivated  (has  some  degree  of  drive)   if  it  is 


50  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

awake  and  walking  about,  but  not  if  it  is  asleep."  Since  we  can 
readily  observe  whether  an  animal  is  active  and  awake  or  asleep, 
we  can  apply  the  definition  to  each  and  every  animal  in  a  group. 
Thus  we  can  recognize  the  presence  or  absence  of  the  phe- 
nomenon we  wish  to  measure  and  can  go  on  to  count  the  num- 
ber of  animals  in  the  group  that  are,  by  the  terms  of  the  defini- 
tion, possessed  of  drive.  Should  we  be  interested,  we  could  then 
note  whether  colony  A  contains  more  motivated  animals  than 
colony  B,  whether  the  count  of  motivated  animals  is  higher  under 
one  diet  than  another,  and  the  like.  Moreover,  if  it  seemed  ex- 
pedient to  do  so,  we  could  alter  our  initial  operational  definition 
of  drive  or  choose  a  completely  different  one.  By  means  of  new 
counts  we  could  then  determine  whether  the  use  of  the  alternate 
definition  yields  more  significant  or  more  meaningful  relations 
than  did  the  original  one. 

The  application  of  operational  definitions  and  counting  proce- 
dures in  this  suggested  manner  does  not,  of  course,  provide  us 
with  information  as  to  the  relative  drive  strengths  of  different  ani- 
mals or  of  different  colonies.  But  the  fact  that  we  have  been  able 
to  divide  our  animals  into  "driven"  and  "nondriven"  groups  and 
to  enumerate  the  constituents  of  each  group  does  mean  that  we 
have  achieved  one  kind  of  drive  quantification. 

Ranking.  The  operational  definition  employed  in  the  previous 
section,  that  an  animal  is  motivated  if  it  is  awake  and  moving 
about,  is  an  all-or-none  type  of  definition.  By  applying  it  we  can 
decide  whether  any  one  individual  is  motivated  or  not.  But  the 
definition  does  not  provide  us  with  a  method  for  determining 
which  of  two  motivated  individuals  is  the  more  highly  motivated. 
Assertions  about  the  relative  drive  strengths  of  different  individ- 
uals imply  a  different  sort  of  measurement  than  that  achieved  by 
counting  and  involve  different  kinds  of  definitions  and  procedures. 
The  outcome  of  such  procedures  is  an  ordinal  or  rank-order  scale 
by  means  of  which  numerals  may  be  assigned  to  individuals  hav- 
ing varying  degrees  of  the  property  or  dimension  of  drive. 

The  first  requirement  to  be  met  in  constructing  an  ordinal 
drive  scale  is  to  develop  standardized  laboratory  operations  for 
arranging  individuals  in  order  with  respect  to  strength  of  drive. 
We  must,  that  is,  find  empirical  methods  to  support  decisions 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE  51 

such  as  "A  has  more  drive  than  B,"  "B  has  less  drive  than  C," 
and  so  forth.  But  since  drive  is  an  intermediary  construct,  it  again 
becomes  necessary  at  this  point  to  introduce  an  operational  defini- 
tion. Perhaps  we  might  choose  a  definition  such  as  the  following: 
if  two  food-deprived  rats  are  permitted  simultaneously  to  run 
down  adjacent  straight  alleys  for  food,  then  the  rat  that  first 
reaches  its  goal  has  the  higher  drive.  In  principle,  at  least,  the 
procedures  specified  in  this  definition  can  be  carried  out  in  the 
laboratory,  and  from  the  outcome  it  can  be  asserted  that,  with 
respect  to  any  two  rats,  the  drive  of  one  is  either  greater  than, 
less  than,  or  equal  to  that  of  the  other,  by  definition.  The  defini- 
tion states  that  the  rats  are  to  be  run  simultaneously,  and  it  is  im- 
plied that  the  observer  simply  judges  which  rat  is  the  "winner." 
However,  the  rats  could  be  run  individually,  provided  their  com- 
parative running  speeds  are  evaluated  through  the  use  of  stop 
watches  or  other  timing  devices.  The  two  methods  would  yield 
identical  estimates  of  relative  running  proficiency,  and  hence  of 
relative  drive  strength,  unless  social  or  other  factors  were  differen- 
tially involved  in  the  two  situations.  Incidentally,  other  operational 
definitions  than  the  above  (e.g.,  definitions  involving  differences 
in  antecedent  conditions,  organic  states,  or  stimulus  conditions) 
could  be  used  with  equal  justification  as  the  basis  for  the  rank 
ordering  of  subjects  according  to  drive  level. 

The  logical  requirements  for  quantifying  any  physical  property 
or  quality  have  been  clearly  stated  by  such  writers  as  Campbell 
(1921),  Cohen  and  Nagel  (1934),  and  Reese  (1943).  Cohen  and 
Nagel  have  listed  the  minimum  requirements  to  be  met  in  con- 
structing an  ordinal  scale.  In  the  following  paragraphs  each  of 
these  requirements  is  examined  in  relation  to  the  problem  of 
developing  an  ordinal  scale  of  drive. 

Given  a  group  of  individuals,  A,  B,  C,  etc.,  we  must  be  able  to 
arrange  them  serially  with  respect  to  the  property  (drive)  so  that 
between  any  two  individuals,  A  and  B,  one  and  only  one  of  the 
following  relations  holds:  (a)  A  has  more  drive  than  B;  {b)  A 
has  less  drive  than  B;  (c)  A's  drive  equals  B's.  It  must  also  be 
possible  to  show  by  physical  operations  that  the  relationship 
"greater  than"  and  its  converse  "less  than"  (symbolized  by  >  and 
< )  are  asymmetrical  and  transitive.  The  requirement  for  asym- 


52  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

metry  is  satisfied  by  demonstrating  that  if  A  >  B,  then  B  >  A 
(where  >  means  "not  greater  than").  Transitivity  can  be  demon- 
strated by  showing  that  if  A  >  B,  and  B  >  C,  then  A  >  C. 
Satisfying  these  requirements  at  the  empirical  laboratory  level,  by 
comparing  running  times,  for  example,  comprises  the  first  steps  to- 
ward constructing  an  ordinal  scale  of  drive. 

The  actual  task  of  scale  construction  is  a  relatively  simple  matter 
once  we  have  found  satisfactory  physical  operations  for  establish- 
ing the  fundamental  relationships  listed  above.  To  do  so  we  must 
assign  numerals  to  the  individuals  of  the  group  in  accordance 
with  certain  rules.  If  we  have  determined,  by  laboratory  tests,  that 
individual  A  has  more  drive  than  B,  we  must  assign  to  A  a  nu- 
meral standing  higher  in  the  series  of  numerals  than  the  numeral 
assigned  to  B.  Conversely,  if  B  has  less  drive  than  A,  the  numeral 
assigned  to  B  must  be  less  (lower  in  the  series)  than  the  numeral 
assigned  to  A.  If  A  and  B  are  equal  with  respect  to  drive,  as  ex- 
perimentally determined,  then  the  numeral  assigned  to  one  must 
be  the  same  as  the  numeral  assigned  to  the  other.  The  numeral 
series  is,  by  convention,  an  ordered  series  that  exhibits  transitive 
and  asymmetrical  relations.  But  until  we  have  shown  empirically 
that  the  relations  among  individuals  with  different  drive  strengths 
are  also  transitive  and  asymmetrical  we  cannot  profitably  use  the 
numeral  series  to  represent  the  rank  orders  of  the  individuals' 
drives. 

Incidentally,  although  our  operations  may  tell  us  that  A  has 
more  drive  than  B  there  is  nothing  in  these  operations  to  indicate 
what  specific  numerals  should  be  assigned  to  A  and  B.  The  rule 
merely  states  that  the  numeral  assigned  to  A  must  be  greater  than 
that  assigned  to  B.  Any  two  numerals  will  do:  1  and  2,  10  and  20, 
or  37  and  99,  so  long  as  the  second  is  the  larger  of  the  two.  As 
Reese  (1943)  has  pointed  out,  at  this  stage  we  have  no  operations 
for  determining  how  much  more  drive  A  has  than  B,  and  hence 
the  numerals  we  assign  cannot  mirror  a  relation  that  has  not  been 
determined.  The  ordinal  scale  we  would  obtain  from  assigning 
numerals  in  compliance  with  these  rules  would  tell  us  nothing 
about  the  size  of  the  interval  separating  any  two  individuals  on  the 
scale,  nor  would  it  yield  any  information  as  to  the  absolute  amount 
of  drive  at  any  point.  We  can  assign  the  numerals  2  and  1  to  A 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE  53 

and  B,  respectively,  if  we  wish,  but  we  cannot  maintain  that  A 
has  twice  as  much  drive  as  B,  since  the  relation  "twice  as  much 
as"  has  not  been  empirically  demonstrated. 

Once  a  rank-order  ( ordinal )  scale  of  drive  has  been  established, 
we  can  use  it  in  a  number  of  different  ways  even  though  no  mean- 
ing can  be  attached  to  the  statement  that  the  drive  of  one  individ- 
ual is  twice  (or  n  times)  the  drive  of  another.  For  instance,  any 
new  individual  can  be  assigned  a  position  on  the  scale  with  respect 
to  the  original  group  used  in  constructing  the  scale.  We  can 
also  use  the  scale  to  study  the  effects  of  any  new  variables  upon 
relative  scale  position.  Or  we  can  relate  position  on  the  scale  to 
level  of  performance  on  some  new  and  different  task.  Thus,  we 
can,  from  the  scale,  select  groups  of  organisms  with  different 
drive  levels  and  subject  them  to  a  learning  task  to  discover  whether 
their  speed-of-learning  scores  stand  in  the  same  rank  order  as  do 
their  drive  levels.  A  great  many  of  the  "qualities"  of  individuals 
that  are  "measured"  by  the  psychologist,  such  as  intelligence, 
honesty,  and  aptitude,  etc.,  are  measured  only  in  the  limited  sense 
that  different  degrees  of  the  quality  can  be  arrayed  in  serial  order. 
But  it  is  also  true  that  certain  properties  of  purely  physical  systems, 
such  as  density  and  hardness,  are  also  restricted  to  measurement 
of  this  kind.  All  of  these  qualities  are  commonly  described  as 
intensive,  and  when,  for  a  given  quality,  physical  operations  have 
been  worked  out  which  satisfy  the  criteria  listed  above,  one  speaks 
of  an  intensive  dimension. 

In  concluding  this  discussion,  we  must  note  that  the  major  prob- 
lem in  constructing  an  ordinal  scale  of  drive  is  to  find  satisfactory 
empirical  methods  upon  which  to  base  the  assertion  that  individ- 
ual A  has  more  drive  than  individual  B,  or  that  individual  A  has 
more  drive  at  one  time  than  at  another.  The  method  used  in  our 
illustration,  of  defining  drive  operationally  in  terms  of  relative 
running  speeds,  would  probably  not  be  entirely  satisfactory  to 
most  investigators.  In  principle,  one  can  construct  an  ordinal  scale 
of  drive,  but  it  will  be  of  limited  interest  until  a  genuinely  sig- 
nificant definition  of  drive  can  be  formulated  as  the  basis  for  the 
empirical  process  of  rank-ordering  subjects  with  respect  to  drive. 

Extensive  Properties  and  Fundamental  Measurement.  The  ordi- 
nal type  of  measurement  as  applied  to  the  problem  of  drive  quan- 


54  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

tification  can  never  tell  us  how  much  more  drive  one  subject  has 
than  another.  To  obtain  this  information  it  would  be  necessary  to 
demonstrate  that  drive  intensity  is  an  extensive  dim.ension  and 
susceptible,  therefore,  to  what  the  physicist  calls  fundamental  meas- 
urement. According  to  Campbell  (1921),  an  extensive  dimension 
is  like  an  intensive  one  in  that  the  characteristics  of  asymmetry 
and  transitivity  can  be  shown  to  hold  among  events  having  the 
extensive  property.  The  two  differ,  however,  in  that  a  quality  that 
is  extensive  possesses  also  the  attribute  of  additivity.  The  prop- 
erty of  objects  which  we  call  their  length  is  extensive  because  ex- 
perimental operations  have  been  found  by  which  one  length  can 
be  added  to  another  to  produce  more  of  the  same  property  of 
length.  It  is  because  length  is  additive,  primarily,  that  it  is  said  to 
be  extensive  and  to  permit  fundamental  measurement. 

At  present  there  seems  to  be  little  reason  for  supposing  that  a 
property  such  as  drive  can  ever  be  measured  in  this  fundamental 
sense,  since  experimental  operations  for  demonstrating  additivity 
may  never  be  found.  It  is  conceivable,  however,  that  satisfactory 
quantitative  estimates  of  drive  can  eventually  be  obtained  by  what 
is  termed  derived  measurement.  We  cannot  pause  to  describe  this 
method  in  detail  here  but  it  is  applied  by  the  physicist  to  dimen- 
sions such  as  density  that  do  not  exhibit  the  property  of  additivity. 

Summary 

The  discussions  in  Chapter  2  have  dealt  with  the  general  ques- 
tions of  why  intervening  variables  such  as  drive  are  used  in  be- 
havior theories,  how  such  impalpable  entities  can  be  defined  by 
reference  to  observable  variables,  how  one  might  decide  that  a 
given  intermediary  variable  is  motivational  rather  than  something 
else,  and  how  such  variables  might,  in  principle,  be  measured. 

In  the  first  part  of  the  chapter  it  was  noted  that  intermediary 
variables  or  constructs  are  usually  proposed  in  the  hope  that  they 
will  add  to  our  understanding  of  obscure  relations  between  be- 
havior and  other  variables  both  inside  and  outside  of  the  organism. 
Typical  relations  of  this  kind  were  cited  with  special  emphasis 
being  placed  upon  disproportions  between  the  vigor  of  a  response 
and  the  intensity  of  a  stimulus,  upon  behavioral  variability  in  the 


INTERVENING  VARIABLES  AND  DEFINITION  OF  DRIVE  55 

presence  of  constant  environmental  conditions,  and  on  invariant 
behavior  in  the  face  of  normally  effective  changes  in  the  environ- 
ment. 

Intervening  variables  are  sometimes  defined  in  terms  of  the 
particular  responses  that  are  supposed  to  be  explained  by  such 
variables.  This  practice  leads  to  circular  explanatory  reasoning  of 
an  undesirable  kind,  as  when  a  herding  instinct,  defined  in  terms 
of  gregarious  behavior,  is  alleged  to  be  the  cause  of  such  behavior. 
To  avoid  such  circularity  an  intervening  variable  can  be  defined 
in  terms  of  variations  in  the  organism's  life  history,  in  terms  of 
other  responses  recorded  in  different  testing  situations,  or  in  terms 
of  organic  variables  and  contemporary  environmental  conditions. 

The  scientific  meanings  of  an  intervening  variable  are  provided 
by  explicit  definitions  as  to  how  the  term  shall  be  used  in  the 
scientific  vocabulary  and  by  the  diversity  and  kinds  of  laws  into 
which  the  variable  enters.  It  is  not  necessary,  therefore,  that  the 
constructed  variable  be  given  a  name  that  is  also  meaningful  to 
laymen.  Usually,  in  such  an  attempt,  the  choice  of  a  particular 
name  seems  to  depend  primarily  upon  the  independent  variables 
used  in  defining  the  construct  and  upon  traditional  ways  of  nam- 
ing the  effects  of  such  variables  upon  performance. 

Although  opinions  differ  as  to  the  nature  of  motivational  vari- 
ables, several  criteria  for  their  identification  are  suggested  in 
this  chapter.  Thus  a  specific  variable  tends  to  be  regarded  as  mo- 
tivational ( 1 )  if  it  tends  to  facilitate  or  energize  several  different 
responses,  (2)  if  its  termination  or  removal  following  a  new  re- 
sponse leads  to  the  learning  of  that  response,  (3)  if  sudden  in- 
creases in  the  strength  of  the  variable  lead  to  the  abandonment  of 
responses,  and  (4)  if  its  effects  on  behavior  cannot  be  attributed 
to  other  processes  such  as  learning,  sensation,  innate  capacities, 
and  sets. 

In  later  sections  of  the  chapter  we  have  pointed  out  that  inter- 
mediary constructs,  including  drive  or  motivation,  must  be  defined 
with  sufficient  clarity  so  that  investigators  with  comparable  train- 
ing can  understand  what  the  terms  mean.  This  goal  can  be  at- 
tained if  construct-names  are  defined  either  in  terms  of  directly 
observable  things,  or  in  terms  of  words  that  have  been  so  defined. 
Definitions  of  this  kind  are  said  to  be  operational,  and  the  scientific- 


56  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

vocabulan^  meaning  of  the  construct  is  thus  given  by  the  opera- 
tions or  manipulations  used  in  its  definition.  A  construct  may  be 
clearly  defined,  however,  and  yet  have  no  value  as  an  element  of 
a  theor}^  of  behavior.  The  student  of  motivation,  therefore,  must 
face  the  problem  of  how  to  formulate  a  conception  of  motivation 
that  is  both  operationally  immaculate  and  generally  useful.  When 
functioning  as  an  integral  component  of  a  behavior  theor}^, 
a  construct  acquires,  from  its  interrelations  with  different 
constructs  and  laws,  other  meanings  than  those  provided  by  its 
operational  definition.  A  construct  can  have  operationally  clear 
meanings  without  these  secondary  meanings,  but  not  the  reverse, 
save  perhaps  in  highly  developed  physical  theories. 

Some  elements  of  the  problem  of  drive  measurement  are  re- 
viewed in  the  final  section.  There  it  is  observed  that  measurement, 
in  essence,  is  the  assignment  of  numbers  to  objects  and  events  in 
accordance  with  certain  rules  and  conventions.  Counting  is  one 
way  of  assigning  numbers,  and  if  operations  for  detecting  the  pres- 
ence of  drive  can  be  devised,  then  the  frequency  with  which 
"driven"  subjects  appear  in  a  given  population  can  be  determined. 
At  a  more  advanced  level,  an  ordinal  scale  of  drive  can  be  devised, 
provided  one  can  find  physical  operations  for  arranging  individuals 
in  rank  order  with  respect  to  drive  strength.  No  procedures  have 
yet  been  devised  by  means  of  which  drive  may  be  measured  in 
the  fundamental  sense  that  length  and  weight  are  measured,  but 
the  quantification  of  drive  by  what  is  termed  derived  measure- 
ment may  eventually  prove  to  be  feasible. 


CHAPTER 


3 


Primary  Sources  of  Drive 

In  this  chapter  we  shall  deal  primarily  with  experimental  studies 
of  the  effects  of  certain  alleged  motivational  variables  upon  the 
performance  of  animals  in  a  variety  of  situations.  The  variables  to 
be  considered  are  those  that  are  commonly  said  to  be  responsible 
for  the  arousal  of  the  "primary  drives."  For  reasons  presented  be- 
low, however,  we  have  chosen  to  depart  somewhat  from  conven- 
tional terminology  and  to  speak,  not  of  "drives,"  but  of  "primary 
sources  of  drive."  Since  these  and  other  terms  to  be  used  hereafter 
require  clarification,  we  begin  with  a  brief  terminological  discus- 
sion. 

Some  Terminological  Distinctions 

Motivating  and  Steering  Variables.  With  few  exceptions,  con- 
temporary theorists  make  a  distinction  between  independent  vari- 
ables that  seem  to  have  motivational  effects  upon  behavior  and 
those  that  direct  or  guide  behavior  (e.g.,  Tolman,  1932;  Lewin, 
1938;  Hull,  1943;  Spence,  1956).  Moreover,  two  kinds  of  interme- 

57 


58 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


diary  constructs  are  introduced  that  correspond  with  these  two 
groups  of  variables.  Thus,  drives,  motivations,  conations,  emotions, 
and  hbidos  function  as  the  activating  agents;  while  cognitive  maps, 
associative  tendencies,  and  habit  strengths  serve,  in  conjunction 
with  external  and  internal  stimuli,  to  determine  the  direction  be- 
havior will  take. 

In  some  instances,  however,  difficulties  arise  in  attempting  to 
maintain  these  distinctions.  Specifically,  there  are  certain  manip- 
ulatable  variables  that  appear  to  exert  both  a  motivating  and  a 
guiding  influence  upon  behavior  and  hence  cannot  be  put  into 
a  single  classification.  Peripheral  shock  is  a  good  example,  since 
it  has  sensory  consequences  in  addition  to  its  presumed  drive- 
arousing  effects. 

Two  solutions  to  this  difficulty  merit  consideration.  First,  one 
might  assume  that  a  variable  such  as  electric  shock  affects  only 
drive,  but  that  drive  can  function  as  both  an  activator  and  a 
director.  This  conceptual  arrangement  is  represented  in  the  upper 
half  of  Fig.  3:1.  Unfortunately  this  solution  seems  unsatisfactory, 
since  the  directive  function  it  ascribes  to  drive  is  precisely  the  same 
function  traditionally  reserved  for  cognitions  or  associative  tend- 
encies (lower  half  of  Fig.  3:1).  If  both  drive  and  habit  are  to  be 


Motivational 

variable     

(e.g.  shock) 

>■  Drive  <C^ 

Environmental 
variables 

Sensory 
'    effects 

Nonmotivational 

variable 

(e.g.  practice  in  a 

learning  situation) 

Associative 
tendencies 

Directive 
function 


Motivating 
function 


Directive 
function 


Fig.  3:1.  The  upper  half  of  this  figure  represents  one  hypothesis  as  to  how 
a  motivational  variable  such  as  electric  shock  might  have  both  directive  and 
motivating  effects  upon  behavior.  For  purposes  of  comparison,  the  directive 
effects  of  environmental  variables  and  of  practice  in  a  learning  situation,  as 
mediated  by  associative  tendencies,  are  included  in  the  bottom  half  of  the 
figure. 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE 


59 


included  in  our  theories,  then  the  two  should  affect  behavior  in 
different  ways;  otherwise  only  one  construct  seems  to  be  required. 
In  the  scheme  of  Fig.  3:1,  habits  (associative  tendencies)  operate 
as  behavior  directors  but  not  as  activators,  whereas  drive  exhibits 
both  properties.  This  interpretation  thus  seems  to  add  little  to  the 
clarity  of  our  understanding,  but  several  theorists  (McClelland, 
1951;  Young,  1955;  Seward,  1956;  Marx,  1956)  use  the  term 
motive  in  essentially  the  way  that  drive  has  been  used  here. 

A  second  solution  that  promises  to  be  more  useful  is  represented 
in  Fig.  3:2.  Here  the  dual-purpose  variable  (shock)  is  assumed  to 
have  two  distinguishable  consequents  rather  than  one.  It  provides 
sensory  stimuli  which,  in  conjunction  with  associative  predisposi- 
tions, can  impart  direction  to  behavior,  and  in  addition  it  affects 
drive,  to  which  only  the  single  function  of  motivation  is  assigned. 
This  answer  has  the  advantage  of  preserving  unique  functions  for 
drive  as  well  as  for  habit  strength.  On  this  view,  which  is  tenta- 
tively adopted  throughout  the  remainder  of  this  book,  the  con- 
struct denoted  by  the  words  drive  or  motivation — these  terms  are 
used  as  synonyms  here  and  elsewhere — is  assumed  to  have  no 
function  as  a  behavior  guide  or  director.  Certain  variables  may 
thus  be  seen  to  have  dual  consequences,  but  drive  is  assumed  to 
have  only  motivational  effects  and  habit  strength  only  directive 
functions. 


Motivational 

variable     - 
(e.g.  shock) 


->-  Drive 


Motivating 
function 


Environmental 
variables 


Nonmotivational 

variable 
(e.g.  practice  in  a" 
learning  situation) 


^  Sensory 
effects 


Associative 


tendencies 


Directive 
function 


Fig.  3:2.  Components  of  a  second  interpretation  of  the  dual  behavioral  ef- 
fects of  a  motivational  variable.  Here  electric  shock  is  assumed  to  affect  drive, 
which  serves  as  the  sole  motivating  agent,  and  also  to  lead  to  sensory  effects. 
These  effects  are  essentially  identical  with  those  arising  from  other  aspects 
of  the  physical  environment  and  are  presumed  to  function  in  conjunction 
with  associative  predispositions  to  direct  behavior. 


60  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

It  should  be  clearly  understood,  however,  that  an  adequate 
theory  of  directed  behavior  may  not  require  both  an  activating  and 
a  steering  agency.  As  we  shall  see  in  the  next  chapter,  some  the- 
orists feel  that  a  construct  having  an  activating  function  can  be 
dispensed  with  entirely,  the  assorted  effects  of  the  so-called  motiva- 
tional variables  being  explained  by  appeal  simply  to  changes  in 
stimuli  and  in  associative  strengths. 

Drives  or  Drive?  In  current  discussions  of  motivation  it  is  com- 
monplace to  encounter  the  word  "drives."  For  certain  writers,  this 
term  apparently  conveys  the  idea  of  multiple  directedness.  The 
hunger  drive  is  said  to  be  directed  or  to  direct  behavior  toward 
food,  the  thirst  drive  toward  water,  and  so  on.  But  this  terminology 
is  confusing  if,  as  we  have  argued,  it  is  desirable  to  limit  the 
function  of  a  drive  to  that  of  an  activator  or  motivator.  If  this 
latter  position  is  adopted,  drive  can  never  be  directed  toward  any 
specific  goal,  nor  can  it  selectively  activate  one  type  of  associative 
tendency  to  the  exclusion  of  others,  since  this  would  indirectly 
involve  a  directive  function.  To  speak  of  "drives"  implies  that  the 
constructs  so  designated  are  alike,  yet  different.  If  they  are  exactly 
alike  when  functioning  as  motivators,  then  identical  processes 
must  be  involved  in  all  cases,  and  all  drives,  as  activators,  become 
one.  If  they  are  not  alike  as  motivators,  then  each  must  be  motivat- 
ing but  in  a  unique  way.  Just  what  these  different  yet  comparable 
ways  might  be  is  difficult  for  one  to  imagine.  One  might  sup- 
pose, of  course,  that  drives  are  all  alike  save  that  each  is  the  result 
of  its  own  distinctive  motivational  variable.  But  if  this  is  the  case, 
then  we  no  longer  have  different  drives,  as  behavior  determinants, 
but  only  different  sources  of  drive.  It  is  this  line  of  reasoning  that 
has  led  us  to  entitle  this  chapter  "Primary  Sources  of  Drive"  rather 
than  "Primary  Drives." 

The  conclusions  reached  above,  that  a  sharp  distinction  should 
be  drawn,  whenever  possible,  between  the  driving  and  steering 
determinants  of  action,  and  that  drive,  as  an  intermediary  con- 
struct, should  be  unitary  rather  than  multiple  are  clearly  coordinate 
with  a  theory  proposed  by  Hull  (1943)  in  his  Principles  of  Be- 
havior. According  to  Hull,  behavior  is  determined,  in  large  meas- 
ure, by  two  intermediaries,  drive  (D)  and  habit  strength  (H). 
Drive,  for  him,  is  a  broadly  acting,  nondirective  factor  that  func- 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  61 

tions  exclusively  to  facilitate  associative  tendencies  whether  learned 
or  unlearned.  Drive  results  from  the  manipulation  of  certain  vari- 
ables, such  as  strong  stimuli  and  the  withholding  of  food  or  water. 
Furthermore,  its  capacity  to  facilitate  all  behavior  is  assumed  to  be 
independent  of  the  particular  antecedent  condition  of  which  it 
may,  at  the  moment,  be  a  function.  For  example,  drive  due  to  in- 
tense stimulation  is  indistinguishable,  as  an  energizer,  from  drive 
due  to  food  deprivation.  At  the  theoretical  level,  drive  is  simply 
a  numerical  quantity  multiplying  associative  quantities  (habit 
strengths)  to  yield  a  further  quantity,  excitatory  potential  (E). 
This  latter  quantity,  further  altered  by  other  factors,  is  in  turn  re- 
lated by  one  or  another  postulated  mathematical  law  to  overt 
behavior. 

The  behavior-directing  function  is  performed  within  Hull's  sys- 
tem by  the  hypothetical  associative  tendencies,  whether  learned 
or  instinctive,  functioning  in  combination  with  both  internal  and 
external  stimuli.  An  animal  in  a  discrimination  situation  is  steered 
or  directed  toward  one  stimulus  object  and  away  from  another  by 
its  learned  associative  predispositions.  But  drive,  being  nondirec- 
tive,  is  presumed  to  facilitate  both  movements  of  approach  to 
the  positive  cue  and  movements  away  from  the  negative  cue. 
Whichever  reactive  tendency  is  dominant  at  the  moment  is 
catalyzed  into  overt  action  by  drive. 

Primary  and  Secondary  Sources  of  Drive.  Although  mention  has 
been  made  of  primary  sources  of  drive,  we  have  neither  explained 
the  meaning  of  the  adjective  "primary"  nor  contrasted  such  sources 
with  those  that  are  called  "secondary."  Broadly  speaking,  primary 
motivational  variables  are  those  that  produce  their  effects  through 
the  action  of  inherited  bodily  mechanisms.  When  environmental 
conditions  are  altered  in  any  of  a  variety  of  ways,  the  physiological 
mechanisms  of  an  organism,  even  in  the  absence  of  opportunities 
to  learn,  tend  to  react  in  a  corrective  manner.  At  such  times  the 
organism  is  likely  to  behave  as  though  motivated.  The  environ- 
mental changes  or  variables  leading  to  these  effects  are  called  pri- 
mary because  they  appear  early  in  the  developmental  and  phylo- 
genetic  sequences,  not  because  they  are  necessarily  more  important 
than  those  labeled  secondary.  Such  terms  as  homeostatic  drives, 
biogenic  drives,  and  physiogenic  drives  have  been  used  as  synonyms 


62  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

for  what  we  are  calling  primary  sources  of  drive.  These  terms  serve 
further  to  emphasize  the  regulatory  mechanisms  involved  and 
their  relations  to  the  genetic  constitution  of  the  organism.  Ex- 
amples of  variables  typically  described  as  having  primary  motiva- 
tional effects  are  the  withholding  of  such  commodities  as  food, 
water,  or  air  for  breathing.  The  removal  of  a  mother's  offspring — 
in  some  species  only — is  also  described  as  a  primary  variable,  as 
are  deviations  from  optimal  levels  of  environmental  temperature 
and  humidity,  and  pressures  produced  by  the  accumulation  of 
bodily  wastes.  Any  stimulus  to  which  the  organism  is  receptive 
may  have  motivational  effects  if  it  is  intense  enough.  Electric 
shocks,  bright  lights,  loud  noises,  pin  pricks,  and  the  like,  are  com- 
mon instances.  In  the  opinion  of  some  authors,  the  withholding 
of  opportunities  to  play,  to  be  active,  or  to  explore,  also  qualify  as 
primary  motivational  variables. 

The  secondary  drives,  or,  as  we  shall  describe  them,  the  second- 
'ary  sources  of  drive,  differ  from  their  primary  counterparts  in  that 
their  efficacy  as  motivators  rests  largely  upon  learning.  Specifically, 
if  an  individual  has  acquired  a  tendency  to  make  a  certain  response 
to  a  particular  environmental  situation,  the  elicitation  of  that  re- 
sponse may  have  motivational  consequences;  consequences,  that  is, 
resembling  those  stemming  from  primary  sources  of  drive  and  con- 
sistent with  one  or  more  motivational  criteria.  Because  human  be- 
havior is  often  said  to  be  largely  motivated  by  secondary  or  ac- 
quired sources  of  drive,  these  have  come  to  occupy  the  attention 
of  psychologists  to  an  increasing  degree.  All  of  Chapter  5  is 
devoted  to  their  analysis. 

The  remainder  of  the  present  chapter  is  concerned  with  a  dis- 
cussion of  certain  primary  sources  of  drive  and  their  effects  upon 
behavior.  Since  hunger  and  thirst  are  the  most  frequently  studied 
sources  and  since  their  strength  is  often  believed  to  be  reflected 
rather  directly  in  the  amount  of  consummatory  behavior,  we 
begin  with  the  question  of  how  such  behavior  is  regulated. 

The  Regulation  of  Consummatory  Behavior 

Students  concerned  with  the  ways  in  which  biological  needs  may 
serve  as  primary  sources  of  -drive  have  dealt  extensively  with  the 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  63 

effects  of  such  needs  on  performance  in  problem  solving,  discrimi- 
nation, and  conditioning  tasks.  In  addition,  considerable  effort 
has  been  devoted  to  the  study  of  the  physiological  mechanisms 
controlling  consummatory  behavior.  Most  of  the  relevant  research 
in  this  latter  area  lies  more  properly  within  the  field  of  physiology 
rather  than  in  that  of  psychology;  hence  we  shall  consider  it  only 
briefly  and  in  broad  outline.  For  more  detailed  information  the 
reader  may  wish  to  consult  such  sources  as  Morgan  and  Stellar 
(1950),  Stellar  (1954),  Miner  (1955),  and  Morgan  (1957). 

The  Local  Theory  of  Hunger  and  Thirst.  When  psychologists 
and  physiologists  first  became  concerned  with  the  nature  of  hunger 
and  thirst,  they  tended  in  large  part  to  approach  the  problems 
from  the  basic  position  of  the  introspectionists.  Looked  at  in  this 
way,  hunger  and  thirst  were  sensations  experienced  by  the  self- 
observing  scientist,  and  the  proper  way  to  study  therh  was  to  seek 
for  meaningful  relations  between  these  sensations  and  other  con- 
ditions such  as  time  since  eating  or  drinking  and  organic  activities.^ 
Such  an  approach  to  the  study  of  these  needs  is  well  illustrated  by 
the  work  of  the  physiologist  Cannon  (1929).  Over  a  period  of 
many  years.  Cannon's  research  was  directed  toward  discovering  the 
physiological  correlates  of  these  sensations  and  toward  elaborating 
and  justifying  his  "local  theory"  of  their  origin.  The  essence  of 
this  theory  was  that  thirst,  or  at  least  the  sensation  of  thirst,  was 
a  consequence  of  a  dryness  of  the  mouth  and  throat  caused  by  th^ 
body's  need  for  water.  Similarly,  hunger  was  identified  with  sen- 
sory impulses  arising  from  vigorous  contractions  of  the  empty 
stomach.  The  label  "local  theory"  has  been  applied  to  this  view 
because  of  its  emphasis  upon  the  peripheral,  localized  origins  of 
the  hunger  and  thirst  sensations. 

The  evidence  presented  by  Cannon  and  others  to  support  his 
views  was  extensive  and  persuasive.  If  dryness  of  the  buccal  cavity 
is  alleviated  by  rinsing  the  mouth  with  water,  the  sensation  of 
thirst  is  also  reduced,  at  least  temporarily,  even  though  no  water 
passes  into  the  body.  And  any  one  of  a  wide  variety  of  events,  such 
as  tightening  one's  belt,  smoking,  or  becoming  frightened,  may 
temporarily  reduce  or  eliminate  hunger  contractions  and  thereby 
also  alleviate  the  subjective  pangs  of  intense  hunger.  Moreover, 
objective  records  of  gastric  contractions  obtained  from  subjects 


64  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

who  swallowed  special  recording  devices  (Cannon,  1929)  were 
found  to  coincide  with  subjective  reports  of  hunger  pangs.  Hunger 
also  appeared  to  be  related  to  level  of  overt  activity,  since  the 
movements  of  sleeping  subjects  occurred  at  about  the  time  of 
vigorous  stomach  activity. 

The  local  theory  of  hunger  and  thirst  thus  seemed  adequate 
to  explain  the  origins  of  the  sensations  consequent  to  food  and 
water  deprivation.  But  with  the  growth  of  interest  in  the  broader 
consequences  of  deprivation,  especially  in  animals,  it  soon  became 
clear  that  the  local  theory  could  not  encompass  all  of  the  impor- 
tant motivational  phenomena  of  hunger  and  thirst.  Its  inade- 
quacy was  due,  in  part,  to  the  fact  that  introspective  methods 
could  not  be  used  with  animals,  but  more  importantly  to  the  find- 
ing that  laws  obtained  when  hunger  and  thirst  were  defined  as 
sensations  were  different  from,  and  apparently  not  as  useful  as, 
those  obtained  when  hunger  and  thirst  were  defined  in  terms  of 
consummatory  behavior.  For  example,  thirsty  subjects  do  not  cease 
drinking  immediately  after  the  first  mouthful,  even  though  only 
a  small  quantity  of  water  is  needed  to  moisten  the  mucous  mem- 
branes of  the  mouth  and  throat  and  thus  eliminate  the  sensations 
of  thirst.  Nor  do  subjects  stop  eating  after  their  first  few  bites,  in 
spite  of  the  fact  that  their  hunger  contractions  have  doubtless 
ceased  and  their  hunger  sensations  have  been  allayed.  Hunger  and 
thirst  as  sensations  thus  turned  out  to  be  different  from  hunger 
and  thirst  as  regulators  or  motivators  of  eating  and  drinking. 

Physiological  Mechanisms  Governing  Consummatory  Behavior. 
Amount  or  rate  of  consummatory  activity  has  been  used  as  the 
principal  basis  for  estimating  biological  needs  in  a  great  many 
physiologically  oriented  investigations  of  basic  mechanisms.  A  de- 
tailed review  of  factors  responsible  for  the  control  of  consumma- 
tory activity  would  take  us  far  beyond  the  intended  scope  of  this 
book  (see,  for  example.  Miner,  1955)  but  a  brief  summary  of  some 
of  the  major  trends  appears  justified. 

Concerning  the  factors  that  function  to  produce  cessation  of 
eating,  Grossman  (1955)  has  concluded  that  they  may  be  divided, 
for  purposes  of  analysis,  into  four  components:  (1)  oropharyngeal 
factors,  (2)  gastrointestinal  factors,  (3)  circulating  nutrients  in 
the  blood,  and  (4)  stored  nutrients  in  the  tissues. 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  65 

The  oropharyngeal  component  refers  to  the  stimulation  of  sen- 
sory receptors  in  the  mouth  and  pharynx  produced  by  food  in  the 
mouth  and  by  the  subsequent  movements  of  chewing  and  swal- 
lowing. Available  evidence  points  to  the  conclusion  that  stimula- 
tion of  these  head  receptors  tends  to  produce  cessation  of  eating, 
apparently  through  the  mediating  action  of  the  medial  portion  of 
the  hypothalamus.  The  neural  impulses  function,  it  would  seem, 
as  a  kind  of  signal  that,  in  cooperation  with  many  other  kinds  of 
signals,  tells  the  brain  to  shut  off  the  mechanisms  that  initiate  and 
maintain  consummatory  activity.  The  oropharyngeal  control  func- 
tion, Grossman  points  out,  is  most  effective  when  supplemented 
by  the  entry  of  food  into  the  stomach.  His  studies  indicate  that 
neither  factor  operating  alone  will  produce  satiety.  For  example, 
if  a  portion  of  a  dog's  daily  ration  is  placed  directly  into  its 
stomach  through  a  fistula,  just  before  food  is  given  ad  libitum, 
voluntary  intake  is  reduced,  but  the  dog  will  still  eat.  This  it  would 
not  do,  clearly,  if  stomach  distention  provided  sufficient  inhibitory 
stimulation.  However,  the  quantity  of  food  ingested  during  the 
subsequent  ad-lib  feeding  period  is  greater  than  if  the  pre-ad-lib 
portion  is  eaten  in  the  normal  manner.  Thus  the  suppression  of 
oral  intake  is  greater  when  the  head  receptors  are  stimulated  dur- 
ing the  normal  processes  of  eating  and,  in  addition,  the  stomach 
is  distended.  Experimental  studies  by  Berkun,  Kessen,  and  Miller 
(1952)  and  by  Miller,  Sampliner,  and  Woodrow  (1957)  have  also 
shown  that  consummatory  behavior  is  reduced  more  when  a  given 
amount  of  food  or  water  is  ingested  orally  than  when  it  is  slowly 
injected  directly  into  the  stomach.  When  milk  is  very  rapidly  in- 
jected, however,  the  opposite  effect  is  obtained  (Smith,  Pool,  and 
Weinberg,  1959),  suggesting  that  rate  of  injection  may  be  a  sig- 
nificant variable. 

In  some  studies,  involving  the  use  of  esophageal  fistulas,  food 
consumed  orally  is  not  permitted  to  reach  the  stomach.  Animals 
that  are  given  sham  feeding  in  this  manner  generally  eat  more 
than  their  normal  daily  rations  before  stopping.  This  increase  in 
intake,  when  the  oropharyngeal  cues  are  functioning  in  isolation, 
points  to  the  need  for  supplementary  control  by  gastrointestinal 
factors;  but  the  fact  that  eating  ceases  even  temporarily  when 
stomach  distention  does  not  occur  suggests  that  hunger  drive,  re- 


66  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

garded  as  a  determinant  of  eating,  has  suffered  abatement.  Gross- 
man summarizes  the  situation  as  follows:  "From  these  observa- 
tions, we  may  hypothesize  that  stimulation  of  head  receptors  by 
smelling,  tasting,  chewing,  and  swallowing,  during  eating,  plays 
an  important  role  in  bringing  about  satiety  and  suppression  of 
further  eating,  but  that  this  factor  is  relatively  ineffective  when 
it  is  not  associated  with  entry  of  food  into  the  stomach"  (1955,  p. 
86).  On  the  basis  of  these  and  other  studies  it  appears  probable 
that  hunger,  defined  in  terms  of  eating  behavior,  can  be  controlled 
by  appropriate  stimulation  and  its  resulting  neural  activity. 

Apparently,  knowledge  as  to  the  precise  neural  mechanisms 
through  which  stimulation  of  the  head  receptors  can  reduce  the 
tendency  to  eat  is  not  yet  available.  Experimental  evidence  (Anand 
and  Brobeck,  1951)  is  at  hand,  however,  to  support  the  view 
that  stimulation  of  the  hypothalamus  may  lead  either  to  hy- 
perphagia  (overeating)  or  to  aphagia  (undereating).  Brobeck 
(1955),  in  reviewing  the  evidence  for  neural  regulation  of  hunger 
and  appetite,  has  hypothesized  that  the  lateral  hypothalamus  may 
be  the  facilitative  and  the  medial  hypothalamus  the  inhibitory 
mechanism.  On  this  view,  when  food  is  eaten,  certain  changes 
occur  within  the  body  which  either  directly  or  indirectly  affect  the 
hypothalamus.  "These  changes  serve  as  signals  to  the  brain,  tend- 
ing to  suppress  the  activity  of  the  lateral  hypothalamus  and  thus 
to  decrease  appetite,  while  they  stimulate  the  medial  or  inhibitory 
portion  of  the  mechanism  and  thus  promote  satiety"  (Brobeck, 
1955,  p.  48).  As  the  food  becomes  absorbed  into  the  body,  the 
situation  tends  to  reverse;  the  lateral  hypothalamus  becomes  more 
active  and  the  medial  portion  more  inhibited.  Under  these  con- 
ditions the  animal's  locomotor  activity  increases,  and  eventually 
eating  begins  again  if  food  is  available. 

Concerning  the  role  played  by  nutrients  in  the  blood  and  in 
the  tissues  in  regulating  consummatory  activity,  we  need  only 
note  that  physiologists  have  not  yet  agreed  on  the  extent  to  which 
either  of  these  factors  governs  consummatory  activity.  Moreover, 
the  mechanisms  of  the  alleged  effects  remain  obscure  (cf.  Gross- 
man, 1955). 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  67 

Needs  and  Drive  Distinguished 

An  interesting  problem,  arising  in  part  out  of  these  studies  of 
the  regulation  of  consummatory  behavior,  is  that  of  the  relation 
of  physiological  needs  to  drive.  The  term  need,  as  it  is  usually 
used,  refers  to  a  bodily  imbalance  or  departure  from  normality 
produced  by  any  one  of  a  variety  of  conditions.  If  food  is  with- 
held for  a  sufficient  period  of  time,  the  chemical  structure  of  the 
body  is  altered,  and  a  need  for  food  is  said  to  exist  because  the 
ingestion  of  food  is  the  necessary  condition  for  the  restoration  of 
the  original  state.  Other  variables  such  as  water  deprivation, 
hormonal  imbalances,  extreme  temperatures,  and  even  noxious 
stimuli  can  be  thought  of  as  generating  needs  for  conditions 
conducive  to  the  restoration  of  equilibrium.  When  vari- 
ables such  as  these  are  manipulated,  behavior  is  often  affected  in 
ways  that  are  consistent  with  one  or  another  motivational  crite- 
rion, and  it  is  common,  therefore,  to  identify  these  needs  with 
drive.  Moreover,  it  is  often  implicitly  assumed  that  drive  fluctuates 
concomitantly  with  needs  as  the  latter  are  modified  by  the  manip- 
ulation of  appropriate  variables. 

Over  restricted  ranges  of  variation  and  for  a  limited  number  of 
needs,  the  identification  of  need  with  drive  can  perhaps  be  de- 
fended. But  as  many  bits  of  evidence  show,  the  two  concepts 
must  be  distinguished  under  certain  conditions.  Consider,  for 
example,  the  case  of  the  rat  from  which  all  food  is  withheld  until 
death  occurs.  If  this  animal's  need  for  food  is  defined  by  reference 
to  loss  of  body  weight,  then  its  need  increases  progressively  up  to 
the  moment  of  death.  But  if,  as  is  sometimes  done,  drive  is  inde- 
pendently defined  in  terms  of  the  number  of  times  the  animal 
crosses  an  electrified  grid  to  reach  food,  drive  increases  at  first  and 
then  decreases.  Decreases  in  number  of  grid  crossings  with  pro- 
longed starvation  are  usually  ascribed,  of  course,  to  muscular  weak- 
ness attending  inanition.  Nevertheless,  the  two  quantities,  need 
and  drive,  when  defined  in  these  two  different  ways,  are  not 
covariant  save  perhaps  for  the  first  two  or  three  days  of  the  depriva- 
tion period. 

It  is  also  obvious  that  the  body  may,  as  a  consequence  of  im- 
proper diet,  develop  a  physiological  need  for  a  specific  chemical 


68  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

substance  such  as  a  vitamin.  But  an  organism  with  a  deficiency  of 
this  sort  may  not  exhibit  increased  activity  or  other  behavioral 
characteristics  typical  of  increased  level  of  drive  (behavioral  defini- 
tion).  The  body's  need  for  the  vitamin  may  increase  as  a  function 
of  time,  but  drive,  as  estimated  from  changes  in  overt  behavior, 
remains  constant. 

Other  evidence  to  support  the  assertion  that  need  and  drive 
are  not  always  covariant  and  hence  should  be  differentiated  comes 
from  a  variety  of  observations.  It  is  generally  accepted,  for  exam- 
ple, that  the  need  for  sexual  gratification  depends  primarily  upon 
the  presence  of  hormones  in  the  blood  (Morgan,  1957).  The  satis- 
factory completion  of  the  sex  act,  however,  does  not  produce  a 
direct  or  immediate  reduction  in  hormonal  concentration.  Never- 
theless, strength  of  sex  drive,  conceived  as  a  general  motivating 
tendency,  is  clearly  reduced  by  copulation. 

Studies  of  sham  drinking  and  of  sham  eating  such  as  those  of 
Adolph  (1943)  and  Janowitz  and  Grossman  (1949)  also  point  to 
the  noncorrespondence  of  need  and  drive.  Here  the  important 
fact  is  that  an  esophageal  animal  will  temporarily  stop  drinking 
or  eating  even  though  no  water  or  food  is  permitted  to  enter  its 
stomach.  For  a  brief  period  following  sham  ingestion,  the  ani- 
mal's thirst  or  hunger  drive,  defined  in  terms  of  its  willingness  to 
engage  in  the  consummatory  act,  is  nonexistent.  Yet  the  body's 
need,  as  measured  by  loss  of  weight,  tissue  conditions,  or  hours 
of  deprivation,  does  not  decline,  and  may  even  increase.  Ap- 
parently, consummatory  activity  itself  may  be  drive  reducing  even 
though  need  is  not  thereby  altered. 

These  examples  should  suffice  to  support  our  contention  that  a 
need,  as  estimated  from  one  set  of  observations,  may  vary  inde- 
pendently of  drive,  when  the  latter  is  defined  by  appeal  to  a  differ- 
ent set  of  data.  Similar  lacks  of  covariation  may  be  found,  of 
course,  between  two  definitions  of  a  need  or  two  definitions  of  a 
drive,  whenever  the  members  of  the  pair  are  defined  by  reference 
to  conditions  of  observation  that  are  quite  different.  Thus  tissue- 
condition-defined  need  does  not  correspond  perfectly  to  drinking- 
behavior-defined  need;  and  deprivation-estimated  drive  may  not 
covary  with  activity-wheel  estimates  of  drive.  This  failure  of  dif- 
ferent definitions  to  coincide  is  one  of  the  persisting  problems 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF   DRIVE  69 

facing  the  student  of  motivation.  Its  solution,  as  we  have  aheady 
suggested  in  our  chapter  on  the  definition  and  measurement  of 
drive,  probably  hinges  upon  the  formulation  of  definitions  that 
are  useful  and  significant  as  w^ell  as  operational. 

We  conclude  this  section  with  the  observation  that  a  tendency 
indiscriminately  to  identify  need  with  drive  is  frequent  among 
those  who  seek  to  disprove  the  hypothesis  that  drive  reduction 
is  a  necessary  condition  for  learning.  Arguments  against  the  drive- 
reduction  concept  are  sometimes  based  on  evidence  of  the  follow- 
ing sort:  Rats  rewarded  with  a  nonnutrient  solution  of  saccharin 
and  water  will  learn  a  simple  instrumental  response  more  readily 
than  rats  rewarded  with  plain  water.  Empirically,  therefore,  the 
sweet-tasting  solution  is  more  reinforcing  than  the  plain  water 
in  spite  of  the  fact  that  the  former  is  no  more  effective  in  reducing 
the  body's  need  for  water  and  has  no  food  value.  From  this  it  is 
reasoned,  assuming  that  the  water  needs*  of  both  groups  have 
been  equally  satisfied  and  that  their  drives  have  therefore  been 
equally  reduced,  that  drive  reduction  is  unnecessary  for  the  growth 
of  learned  associations. 

The  suggestion  that  needs  and  drive  should  be  differentiated 
provides  one  plausible  answer  to  this  type  of  argument.  Thus 
saccharin-rewarded  rats  and  water-rewarded  rats  might  differ  with 
respect  to  drive  reduction,  even  though  their  need  reduction  was 
the  same.  The  sweet-tasting  saccharin  solution  would  be  expected 
to  provide  a  greater  amount  or  intensity  of  oropharyngeal  stimula- 
tion than  would  plain  water.  And  this,  in  terms  of  the  neural 
inhibitory  mechanisms  described  by  Brobeck,  could  readily  be 
followed  by  decreased  appetite  and  increased  satiety.  Whether 
this  is  the  drive-reduction  mechanism  of  reinforcement  we  cannot 
say.  But  this  analysis  suggests  that  at  least  one  kind  of  drive- 
reduction  mechanism  could  be  excited  by  saccharin  even  though 
need  for  water  is  not  differentially  affected.  A  recent  observation 
by  Smith  and  Capretta  (1956),  though  nonsystematic,  supports 
this  interpretation.  According  to  these  authors,  after  rats  have  been 
injected  with  sufficient  insulin  to  produce  insulin  shock,  they  are 
less  likely  to  manifest  severe  shock  symptoms  if  they  are  allowed 
to  consume  saccharin.  Apparently  the  neural  consequences  of  the 
sweet-tasting  substance  set  into  motion  the  same  kind  of  com- 


70  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

pensatory  machinery  normally  excited  only  by  the  ingestion  of 
sugar. 

Along  this  same  line  of  thought,  the  mere  sight  or  smell  of  food 
(stimuli  usually  described  as  secondary  reinforcers)  may  be  effec- 
tive as  rewards  for  new  learning  simply  because  they  do  lead  to  a 
reduction  in  drive.  Because  of  the  individual's  repeated  oppor- 
tunities to  see  and  smell  food  Just  prior  to  its  ingestion,  associa- 
tions could  be  formed  having  the  capacity  to  produce  a  temporary 
and  partial  decline  of  drive.  Perhaps  the  cues  provided  by  food 
come  to  evoke  a  competing  reaction  that  interferes  with  events 
in  the  hypothalamus  normally  responsible  for  hunger-drive  be- 
havior. Direct  experimental  evidence  to  support  this  notion  is 
lacking,  but  several  writers  (Mowrer,  1951;  Osgood,  1953;  Farber, 
1954cz;  Brown,  1955)  have  hypothesized  that  such  a  relationship 
might  exist.  Even  Tolman  (1949),  who  seldom  advocated  the 
drive-reduction  view  under  any  conditions,  maintained  that  sub- 
goals  antedating  the  final  goal  might,  to  a  degree,  be  drive  reduc- 
ing. Moreover,  Morgan  (1957),  who  for  reasons  similar  to  those 
given  above  also  maintains  that  drive  and  need  should  be  distin- 
guished, contends  that  a  strong  argument  can  be  presented  for  the 
view  that  sensory  stimulation  can  reduce  drive.  Neurophysiological 
evidence  to  support  this  position  is  also  available  and  is  discussed 
briefly  in  Chapter  9. 

Performance  as  a  Function  of  Variations 
in  Primary  Sources  of  Drive 

Some  students  of  behavior,  as  we  noted  earlier,  are  not  vitally 
interested  in  the  details  of  the  physiological  processes  resulting 
from  manipulations  of  primary  sources  of  drive.  Instead  they  are 
concerned  with  the  observable  effects  of  such  manipulations  on 
the  behavior  of  their  subjects  in  a  variety  of  situations.  Such 
research  workers  seek  to  determine  the  empirical  laws  relating 
the  dependent  behavior  variables  to  independent  motivational 
variables.  Although  few  of  these  laws  are  as  firmly  established  as 
might  be  desired,  a  considerable  number  of  experiments  have  been 
directed  toward  their  clarification  and  understanding.  It  is  to  the 
presentation  and  discussion  of  selected  examples  of  these  types 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  71 

of  experiments  that  the  remainder  of  this  chapter  is  devoted. 

The  Effect  of  Deprivation  Time  on  Consummatory  Behavior. 
One  of  the  basic  research  problems  in  the  field  of  motivation  is 
that  of  determining  the  relation  between  time  of  deprivation  and 
consummatory  behavior.  For  example,  if  an  animal  is  deprived  of 
food  for  varying  periods  of  time  before  being  allowed  to  eat  ad 
libitum,  what  is  the  function  relating  duration  of  deprivation  to 
rate  of  eating  or  some  other  index  of  voracity?  Though  such  a 
problem  is  obvious  and  is  perhaps  logically  an  antecedent  to  other 
problems,  few  experiments  have  been  directed  toward  its  solution, 
and  the  precise  nature  of  the  laws  for  different  species,  different 
kinds  of  deprivation,  and  the  like,  remain  to  be  determined  in 
future  experiments. 

From  available  experiments,  two  may  be  cited  as  illustrations. 
The  first,  by  Siegel  (1947),  seems  to  be  among  the  earliest  sys- 
tematic studies  of  water  consumption  as  a  function  of  hours  of 
privation.  In  his  experiment,  60  male  albino  rats  were  used  as 
subjects.  They  were  housed  in  a  thermostatically  regulated  environ- 
ment marked  by  small  temperature  and  humidity  changes.  On  the 
first  evening  all  animals  were  weighed  and  their  intake  of  water 
was  measured  over  a  five-minute  period.  Since  they  had  been 
maintained  on  an  ad-lib  drinking  and  eating  regimen  since  wean- 
ing, the  values  obtained  from  these  first  measurements  provided 
estimates  of  water  ingestion  following  zero  hours  of  water  depriva- 
tion. The  body-weight  data  were  then  used  as  the  basis  for  dividing 
the  animals  into  four  groups  of  approximately  equal  weight.  On 
the  second  and  third  days  the  animals  were  given  an  additional 
test  to  see  how  much  water  they  would  drink  in  five  minutes. 
At  the  time  of  these  tests,  the  four  groups  had  been  deprived  of 
water  for  different  lengths  of  time.  These  times  were  6,  12,  24, 
and  48  hours.  The  results  of  these  tests  are  summarized  in  Fig. 
3:3,  where  mean  water  intake  in  milliliters  (cubic  centimeters) 
has  been  plotted  against  hours  of  deprivation. 

It  is  clear  from  this  figure  that  rate  of  drinking  is  for  the  most 
part  an  increasing,  negatively  accelerated  function  of  time  of 
privation  for  periods  up  to  48  hours.  The  initial  portion  of  the 
curve  exhibits  a  slight  positive  acceleration,  but,  as  Siegel  observes, 
this  may  well  be  due  to  chance.  The  fact  that  rate  of  drinking  is 


72 


THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 


12  24 

Number  of  hours  of  water  privation 


48 


Fig.  3:3.  Amount  of  water  (in  milliliters)  drunk  during  5  minutes  by  rats 
as  a  function  of  the  number  of  hours  since  drinking  was  last  permitted.  (From 
Siegel,  1947.) 

higher  at  the  48-hour  than  at  the  24-hour  point  is  of  interest 
because  earher  studies  by  Warden  (1931),  using  the  Columbia 
obstruction  box,  had  implied  that  thirst  decreased  after  24  hours. 
There  are  various  plausible  reasons  for  the  poorer  performance 
of  Warner's  48-hour  animals,  such  as  inanition  or  increased  sen- 
sitivity to  electric  shock.  Nevertheless,  the  fact  remains  that  we 
have  here  another  instance  of  noncorrespondence  between  two 
measures  or  definitions  of  drive. 

A  subsidiary  finding  of  Siegel's  also  deserves  mention.  Just  be- 
fore testing  his  animals  on  the  second  and  third  days,  he  weighed 
them  carefully  to  find  out  how  much  weight  the  groups  had  lost 
during  their  respective  deprivation  periods.  From  these  data  and 
from  measures  of  drinking  he  was  able  to  plot  per  cent  of  body 
weight  drunk  in  five  minutes  against  percentage  of  body- 
weight  loss.  This  is  shown  in  Fig.  3:4.  In  its  general  form  this 
curve  resembles  one  previously  reported  by  Adolph  (1941)  relat- 
ing sham  drinking  to  body-weight  deficit  in  dogs.  It  provides 
further  confirmation  of  the  observation  that  animals  tend  to 
adjust  their  intake  of  water  to  match  the  body's  need  for  fluid. 
And  incidentally  the  curve  provides  an  excellent  example  of  what 
was  described  in  Chapter  1  as  an  OR  law,  since  body-weight  loss 
reflects  an  organic  state  (O)  and  drinking  is  clearly  a  response  (R). 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE 


73 


-15  -10  -5 

Percentage  body  weight  loss 

Fig.  3:4.  A  functional  relation  between  an  organic  variable  (loss  in  body 
weight)  and  a  response  variable  (amount  of  water  ingested).  {From  Siegel, 
1947.) 


Our  second  experiment  illustrating  the  effects  of  privation  on 
consummatory  behavior  is  one  by  Horenstein  (1951 ) .  In  her  study, 
the  subjects  were  10  female  rats  that  had  been  used  in  a  previous 
investigation  of  the  relation  of  drive  to  response  latency.  At  the 
outset,  the  23.5-hour  feeding  rhythm  on  which  they  had  previously 
been  maintained  was  reestablished.  Then  the  animals  were  satiated 
on  wet  mash  and  returned  to  their  home  cages  for  the  duration 
of  the  deprivation  interval.  At  the  end  of  that  interval,  the  sub- 
jects were  weighed,  permitted  to  eat  freely  of  mash  for  20  minutes, 
and  were  finally  weighed  again.  The  quantity  of  food  consumed 
was  computed  from  the  difference  between  these  initial  and  final 
weights.  The  deprivation  intervals  were:  0,  0.5,  1,  2,  6,  12,  and  23.5 
hours.  All  of  the  animals  were  tested  under  each  of  the  various 
deprivation  conditions  in  a  random  order  to  balance  out  the 
influence  of  systematic  factors  such  as  learning,  aging,  etc.  The 
results  of  these  manipulations  are  summarized  in  Fig.  3:5. 

As  the  curve  of  Fig.  3 : 5  clearly  shows,  mean  food  intake  during 
the  20-minute  test  period  was  an  increasing  monotonic  function 
of  hours  of  deprivation.  In  contrast  to  Siegel's  water-drinking  data, 
the  food  ingestion  curve  of  Horenstein's  exhibits  a  rapid  initial 
rise  from  zero  to  two  hours  of  deprivation.  This  effect  is  apparently 


74 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


^13 

V) 

^^ 

•|  20 

^^ 

o 

^^'^ 

eg 

^^'^ 

c 

^^»'^^ 

'Z,  15 

.^'''^^^ 

E 

^^"^^ 

bO 

^^x*"'^ 

c 

^.X"*^ 

i^io 

f""^ 

(0 

_*c 

1 

T3 

f 

O 

O       „ 

•^     5 

-      1 

c 

J 

nj 

<u 

S 

0 

1      1     1                      1                                 1                                                                1 

0  1  2 


6  12 

Number  of  hours  of  food  deprivation 


23.5 


Fig.  3:5.  Amount  of  food  ingested  during  a  20-niinute  period  by  rats  de- 
prived of  food  for  varying  lengths  of  time.  {Yrom  Horenstein,  19 SI.) 


not  specific  to  consummatory  behavior  since  Horenstein  obtained 
a  similar  result  in  her  studies  of  the  effects  of  deprivation  time 
upon  latency  and  resistance  to  extinction  of  a  simple  instrumental 
response.  Moreover,  the  phenomenon  had  previously  been  reported 
by  Koch  and  Daniel  (1945)  and  by  Saltzman  and  Koch  (1948). 
Several  possible  reasons  for  this  sharp  increase  in  response  strength 
during  the  first  two  hours  are  discussed  by  Horenstein,  among 
them  being  cyclic  factors  and  digestive  mechanisms  of  the  rat. 

Concerning  these  consummatory-response  studies  of  Siegel  and 
Horenstein,  two  explanatory  comments  are  indicated.  First,  no 
vigorous  instrumental  responses  such  as  crossing  a  charged  grid 
or  pushing  a  bar,  over  and  beyond  those  necessary  for  eating  and 
drinking,  were  required  of  the  animals.  Since  the  performance  of 
such  nonconsummatory  responses  involves  additional  energy  out- 
put, estimates  of  hunger  or  thirst  requiring  their  performance 
might  yield  spuriously  low  values,  especially  at  longer  deprivation 
times,  when  the  animal  may  be  somewhat  debilitated.  Moreover, 
in  Horenstein's  experiment,  the  animals  were  allowed  to  eat  wet 
mash  instead  of  hard  pellets,  a  substitution  which  would  minimize 
the  effort  involved  even  in  eating.  Consequently  the  animals'  per- 
formance level  was  probably  not  appreciably  reduced  by  inanition. 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  75 

The  second  comment  on  these  studies  has  to  do  with  their 
potential  utihty  as  estimates  of  drive  (D)  in  Hull's  sense  of  the 
term.  If  drive,  as  Hull  assumed,  serves  to  energize  into  overt  action 
all  reactive  tendencies,  whether  learned  or  unlearned,  then  eating 
and  drinking  curves  reflect  the  strength  of  D  in  a  relatively  direct 
manner,  provided  that  the  strengths  of  the  habits  to  eat  and  drink 
are  equal  at  the  different  deprivation  intervals.  Stimulus  similarity 
is  one  of  the  variables  believed  to  determine  habit  strength,  but 
in  order  to  explain  how  this  variable  might  have  affected  Horen- 
stein's  results,  we  must  digress  briefly  to  discuss  deprivation-induced 
stimuli. 

Within  Hull's  system,  deprivation,  like  electric  shock  (cf.  Fig. 
3:2),  is  assumed  to  generate  not  only  D,  the  nondirective  catalyst, 
but  also,  in  most  cases,  distinctive  internal  stimuli.  These  stimuli 
are  consequences,  for  example,  of  stomach  contractions  attending 
hunger  and  of  dryness  of  the  throat  during  thirst.  These  internal 
events  have  sensory  components  and,  unlike  D,  can  have  a  direc- 
tive influence  on  behavior  since  associative  connections  can  be 
formed  between  them  and  overt  (as  well  as  implicit)  reactions. 
Hull  used  the  term  drive  stimuli  for  these  internal  cues  and  sym- 
bolized them  by  the  notation  So-  This  designation  is  somewhat 
misleading,  however,  since  the  internal  stimuli  neither  originate 
in  nor  bear  any  direct  relation  to  drive  (D)  as  such.  It  would  be 
more  appropriate,  though  less  succinct,  to  call  them  motivation- 
variable  stimuli  (Smvs),  since  they,  like  drive,  result  from  manipu- 
lations of  so-called  motivating  variables. 

Now  in  Horenstein's  experiment,  though  not  in  Siegel's,  the 
animals  had  been  maintained  for  a  good  many  days  on  a  fixed 
dietary  regimen,  being  fed  every  23.5  hours.  Because  of  this  regu- 
larity, as  Horenstein  suggests,  the  tendency  to  eat  may  have 
become  more  strongly  associated  with  internal  stimuli  characteristic 
of  a  23.5-hour  deprivation  period  than  with  cues  arising  from 
shorter  privation  times.  Thus  the  fact  that  Horenstein's  curve  was 
highest  at  the  23.5-hour  point  and  lower  at  increasingly  shorter 
deprivation  intervals  might  be  due,  in  part,  to  differences  in  asso- 
ciative strengths.  This  would  follow  if  as  the  privation  periods 
became  shorter  and  shorter,  the  internal  cues  became  increasingly 
different  from  those  of  the  23.5-hour  training  interval,  and  if. 


76  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

with  increasing  disparity,  there  was  a  decrease  in  the  associative 
tendency  to  eat.  This  sort  of  nonmotivational  interpretation  of 
data  deserves  serious  consideration,  and  in  the  next  chapter  we 
shall  discuss  the  matter  at  greater  length.  The  important  conclu- 
sion to  be  reached  here,  however,  is  that  changes  in  performance 
following  the  manipulation  of  a  motivational  variable  cannot  be 
ascribed  solely  to  changes  in  drive  unless  there  is  reason  to  believe 
that  associative  strengths  have  remained  constant.  In  this  respect 
Siegel's  results  come  closer  to  providing  a  "pure"  estimate  of 
drive,  since  his  animals  were  not  habituated  to  an  externally  im- 
posed drinking  schedule  prior  to  the  experiment,  and  the  drinking 
responses,  therefore,  could  hardly  have  become  associated  with 
only  one  specific  value  of  thirst-stimulus  intensity.  The  ad-lib 
drinking  schedule  under  which  Siegel's  rats  were  reared  might 
have  led,  however,  to  the  growth  of  associations  between  drinking 
responses  and  various  low-intensity  thirst  stimuli.  The  presence 
of  such  tendencies  would  tend  to  encourage  drinking  at  short-term 
privation  test  periods  relative  to  long-term  periods. 

Estimates  of  drive  strength  based  upon  consummatory  behavior 
may  also  be  affected  by  the  number  of  previous  experiences  the 
organism  has  had  with  deprivation  and  with  the  removal  of 
deficits  by  eating  or  drinking.  As  Ghent  (1957)  has  clearly  shown, 
when  rats  are  permitted  to  eat  or  drink  after  their  first  deprivation 
experiences,  they  do  not  immediately  go  to  a  familiar  food  dish  or 
to  a  familiar  water  spout.  But  with  repeated  privations,  eating  and 
drinking  latencies  decrease  markedly,  and  time  spent  in  consuming 
food  and  water  increases.  Corroborative  evidence  to  support  this 
view  that  prior  experience  with  deprivation  affects  consummatory 
responses  has  been  reported  by  Young  (1949),  Baker  (1955),  and 
Lawrence  and  Mason  (1955). 

Instrumental  Behavior  as  a  Function  of  Deprivation.  The  two 
experiments  we  have  just  examined  were  chosen  to  illustrate  the 
effects  of  deprivation  upon  behavior  which,  though  probably 
learned  in  part,  appears  quite  early  in  the  organism's  life  and 
under  conditions  seldom  controlled  by  the  experimenter.  In  this 
section  we  shall  review  experiments  in  which  the  indicant  reactions 
are  instrumental  to  the  obtaining  of  food  or  water  and  have  been 
learned  under  the  supervision  of  the  experimenter.  Thus  we  shall 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF   DRIVE  77 

be  dealing  with  the  effects  of  motivational  variables  upon  such 
responses  as  running,  swimming,  and  lever  pressing,  which  must 
be  performed  by  the  subject  to  obtain  a  reward.  As  in  the  pre- 
ceding section,  we  shall  make  no  attempt  to  review  existing 
studies  in  toto,  but  will  concentrate  on  a  few  of  the  more  recent 
and  more  adequately  controlled  experiments. 

One  problem  of  central  importance  in  this  area  is  that  of  the 
effects  of  different  levels  of  a  motivational  variable  upon  the  rate 
of  acquisition  of  an  instrumental  response  and  upon  terminal 
levels  of  proficiency.  In  principle,  the  experimental  design  required 
for  this  problem  is  extremely  simple:  different  groups  of  subjects 
are  taught  the  to-be-learned  reaction  under  different  levels  of  the 
motivational  variable,  and  their  performance  during  acquisition 
is  observed  and  recorded.  Unfortunately,  our  psychological  litera- 
ture contains  few  studies  of  this  simple,  straightforward  type. 

An  experiment  by  Fredenburg  (1956),  designed  in  essentially 
this  way,  yields  evidence  as  to  the  effects  of  different  deprivation 
levels  upon  the  performance  of  a  simple  instrumental  response.  In 
her  study  two  groups  of  rats  were  trained  to  run  down  a  4-foot 
alley  for  food.  One  group  received  this  training  after  3  hours  of 
food  deprivation,  the  other  after  22  hours  of  deprivation.  Two 
additional  groups,  also  under  3-  and  22-hour  deprivation  condi- 
tions, respectively,  were  trained  in  an  II -foot  alley.  Four  trials 
per  day  were  given  to  each  rat  for  a  period  of  12  days.  By  means 
of  photoelectric  devices  it  was  possible  to  measure  both  starting 
and  running  time  on  every  trial.  Starting  time  was  defined  as  the 
interval  between  the  opening  of  the  starting-box  door  and  the 
instant  the  rat  had  moved  a  distance  of  I  foot  out  into  the  alley. 
Running  time  was  the  time  taken  to  traverse  the  second,  foot- 
long  segment  of  the  alley. 

Acquisition  curves  for  the  two  groups  trained  in  the  4-foot  alley 
are  reproduced  in  Figs.  3:6  and  3:7.  These  speed  curves  were 
obtained  from  the  starting  and  running  times  by  converting  each 
individual  subject's  time  scores  into  reciprocals  (by  dividing  each 
score  into  1)  and  then  averaging  these  reciprocals.  As  the  curves 
in  these  figures  show,  the  performance  of  the  22-hour  deprivation 
group  was  superior  to  that  of  the  3-hour  group  in  both  starting 
and  running  speed.  Comparable  results  favoring  a  long-  over  a 


78  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

4 


•e  2 


22  hours  privation 
(JV=12) 


3  hours  privation 
(N=12) 


3       4       5       6        7       8       9 
Successive  four -trial  blocks 


10     11      12 


Fig.  3:6.  Mean  starting  speeds  over  successive  blocks  of  four  trials  of  rats 
that  had  been  deprived  of  food  for  22  and  for  3  hours.  {Adapted  from 
Fredenburg,  19  S  6.) 

short-deprivation  group  were  also  obtained  in  the  case  of  additional 
animals  that  Fredenburg  trained  in  the  11-foot  alley. 

The  conclusion  to  which  these  data  point  is  amply  supported 
by  other  experimental  evidence.  For  example,  Loess  (1952)  found 
performance  level  during  learning,  as  measured  by  speed  of  re- 
sponse, to  be  higher  for  a  22-hour  group  than  for  a  3-hour  group. 
In  his  experiment  the  response  was  one  of  running  from  a  starting 
compartment  into  a  choice  compartment  to  touch  a  small  bar 
projecting  from  the  back  wall.  Kimble  (1951),  Ramond  (1954), 
Davenport  (1956),  and  Bass  (1958)  have  also  shown  that  acquisi- 
tion curves  obtained  after  long  deprivation  intervals  tend  to  reach 
higher  final  asymptotic  levels  than  curves  obtained  following  brief 
periods  of  deprivation.  Moreover,  performance  of  an  instrumental 
running  response  is  better  under  high  than  under  low  drive  even 
when  these  conditions  are  induced  in  the  same  subjects  on  alter- 
nate days  (Bass).  We  may  take  it  as  reasonably  well  established, 
therefore,  that  the  heights  of  curves  depicting  the  acquisition  of  a 
simple  instrumental  response  vary  directly  with  level  of  food 
deprivation  over  a  limited  range. 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE 


79 


22  hours  privation 
(iV=12) 


3  hours  privation 
(iV-12) 


3       4        5       6       7       8 
Successive  four-trial  blocks 


10      11      12 


Fig.  3:7.  Mean  running  speeds  of  rats  in  a  short  straight  alley  as  joint  func- 
tions of  number  of  rewarded  learning  trials  and  of  length  of  food  deprivation. 
{Adapted  from  Fredenburg,  J  956.) 

In  attempting  to  interpret  the  results  of  studies  such  as  these 
one  must  proceed  with  caution.  Performance  may  be  better  when 
a  response  is  learned  following  long  deprivation,  but  this  may 
or  may  not  mean  that  the  manipulated  variable  (deprivation  time) 
is  functioning  "motivationally."  Actually,  stronger  associations 
or  habits  might  be  formed  when  an  animal  is  hungry  than  when 
it  is  not,  and  if  behavior  is  assumed  to  be  a  joint  function  of 
habits  and  drives,  the  observed  disparities  in  performance  might 
be  due  to  habit-strength  differences,  not  to  drive  differences.  Alter- 
natively, such  results  could  be  due  to  inequalities  in  both  drives 
and  habits  or  in  drive  level  alone. 

While  few  experimenters  have  studied  the  effects  of  a  motiva- 
tional variable  upon  the  acquisition  of  instrumental  responses,  a 
great  many  studies  have  been  performed  in  which  such  variables 
were  manipulated  during  the  extinction  of  a  response.  Tlie  prob- 
lem under  investigation  in  these  experiments  is  that  of  how  differ- 
ent drive  levels  affect  resistance  to  extinction  resulting  from  non- 
reward. 

Experimental  designs  evolved  to  shed  light  on  this  problem  have 
assumed  a  variety  of  forms.  In  a  number  of  these,  all  subjects  are 
given  their  initial  training  under  the  same  motivational  conditions. 


80  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Then,  when  their  performance  has  reached  or  approached  a  stable 
level,  they  are  divided  into  two  or  more  subgroups  that  are  given 
extinction  trials  under  different  motivational  levels.  In  general, 
studies  employing  this  design  (Heathers  and  Arakelian,  1941; 
Perin,  1942;  Saltzman  and  Koch,  1948;  Horenstein,  1951)  have 
found  that  resistance  to  the  extinguishing  effects  of  nonreward 
varies  directly  with  deprivation  time.  With  this  design,  however, 
it  is  difficult  to  draw  clear-cut  conclusions  about  the  relative  roles 
of  habits  and  drive.  This  is  because  some  of  the  groups  are  extin- 
guished under  the  same  deprivation  conditions  as  those  obtaining 
during  learning,  whereas  others  are  extinguished  under  different 
deprivation  regimens.  Thus  for  some  groups  the  intensity  or  quality 
of  the  internal  stimuli  (S^s  or  Smvs)  would  be  the  same  during 
acquisition  and  extinction,  whereas  for  others  marked  changes 
might  be  expected.  Altering  the  nature  of  these  internal  cues 
would  affect  performance  if  the  response  under  study  had  become 
associated  with  those  cues.  If  all  animals  were  trained  under  a 
high  level  of  deprivation  and  separate  subgroups  were  extinguished 
under  that  and  lower  levels,  an  observed  decrease  in  resistance  to 
extinction  with  declining  motivation  could  be  explained  as  an 
instance  of  weakened  internal  cues.  Such  an  interpretation  would 
qualify  as  associative  rather  than  motivational. 

The  difficulties  attending  this  design  might  be  overcome  by 
giving  all  subjects  extensive  preliminary  training  under  all  the 
levels  of  deprivation  to  be  used  during  extinction.  Provided  that 
habit  strength  does  not  depend  on  drive,  such  diversified  training 
should  result  in  the  instrumental  response's  becoming  conditioned 
equally  to  the  several  intensities  or  kinds  of  internal  deprivation- 
produced  cues.  Response  strength  manifested  by  subgroups  extin- 
guished at  different  privation  levels  would  then  not  be  distorted 
by  uncontrolled  variations  in  associative  strength.  To  the  best  of 
our  knowledge,  no  one  has  performed  an  experiment  in  precisely 
this  way.  The  nearest  approximation  is  a  study  by  Cotton  (1953). 
His  subjects  (rats)  were  first  given  preliminary  training  in  a 
straight  runway  under  a  22-hour  deprivation  schedule.  This  was 
followed  by  extensive  training  under  deprivation  times  of  0,  6,  16, 
and  22  hours,  administered  in  a  random  order  within  each  four-day 
period.  When  running-speed  asymptotes  had  been  reached,  further 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  81 

tests  were  carried  out  under  the  four  different  privation  schedules. 
The  measure  of  response  strength  was  running  speed  on  rewarded 
trials  rather  than  resistance  to  extinction.  When  all  test  trials 
were  counted,  running  time  was  found  to  decrease  as  a  linear 
function  of  deprivation  time.  Quite  a  different  function  was  ob- 
tained, however,  when  the  trials  on  which  animals  made  compet- 
ing responses,  such  as  stopping  to  sniff,  were  excluded.  Under 
these  conditions  performance  was  but  little  affected  by  deprivation, 
a  result  that  underscores  the  importance  of  the  particular  measure 
used  in  studies  of  this  kind. 

Some  of  the  difficulties  inherent  in  shifting  from  one  motiva- 
tional level  during  acquisition  to  another  during  extinction  can 
also  be  overcome  by  the  kind  of  design  used  by  Yamaguchi  ( 1951 ) . 
He  employed  five  different  deprivation  times  (3,  12,  24,  48,  and  72 
hours),  one  group  of  animals  being  both  trained  and  extinguished 
at  each  of  these  levels.  Thus  for  each  group,  the  motivation- 
variable-produced  stimuli  (Sj/i-s)  would  be  the  same  during  both 
learning  and  extinction.  The  response  was  that  of  pressing  a  lever 
in  a  modified  Skinner  box,  and  the  basic  measure  was  the  number 
of  responses  made  during  a  series  of  extinction  trials  to  a  criterion 
of  no  responses  in  two  minutes.  As  in  previous  studies,  Yamaguchi 
found  that  the  mean  number  of  responses  in  extinction  increased 
progressiveh"  as  the  period  of  privation  was  lengthened.  He  ob- 
tained means  of  14.9,  15.8,  24.4,  32.2,  and  40.0  responses  for  3, 
12,  24,  48,  and  72  hours  of  hunger,  respectively.  Considerable 
confidence  can  probably  be  placed  in  the  stability  of  these  results, 
since  the  number  of  subjects  in  each  of  the  five  groups  was  quite 
large,  ranging  from  36  to  66.  The  possibility  still  remains,  however, 
that  associative  strength  depends,  to  a  degree,  upon  level  of  motiva- 
tion, and  this  would  operate  artificially  to  enhance  the  apparent 
energizing  effects  of  extended  deprivation  times.  Moreover,  differ- 
ent results  might  have  been  obtained  had  the  distribution  of 
extinction  trials  been  the  same  as  that  of  the  acquisition  trials. 
In  Yamaguchi's  study  extinction  trials  were  massed,  whereas  the 
learning  trials  were  given  in  a  quasi-distributed  manner:  four  trials 
per  session,  one  session  every  five  days. 

As  we  have  seen  in  our  discussion  of  behavior  strength  as  a 
function  of  time  of  deprivation,  difficult  problems  arise  in  design- 


82  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

ing  experiments  on  motivational  variables,  and  since  known  inves- 
tigations differ  so  widely  with  respect  to  subjects,  responses,  and 
procedures,  no  single  function  can  be  held  to  be  uniquely  repre- 
sentative of  the  relation  between  response  strength  and  deprivation 
time.  Nevertheless,  three  conclusions  for  which  there  is  reasonable 
support  may  be  tentatively  stated.  First,  consummatory  activities, 
as  well  as  the  speed  and  resistance  to  extinction  of  responses 
instrumental  to  consummation,  tend  to  be  enhanced  by  privation. 
The  effect  of  any  specific  deprivation  period  is  also  a  function, 
however,  of  such  variables  as  the  number  of  deprivation  cycles 
preceding  the  test,  the  animal's  body  weight,  and  the  relative 
familiarity  of  the  testing  environment.  Second,  curves  depicting 
the  course  of  acquisition  of  instrumental  responses  as  a  function 
of  different  deprivation  levels  tend  to  diverge  during  early  learning 
trials  and  to  maintain  a  constant  separation  with  extended  practice. 
Third,  when  performance  is  measured  at  its  asymptote,  behavior 
strength  is  found  to  rise  rapidly  after  satiation  (or  shortly  there- 
after) up  to  privation  times  of  about  two  hours  and  then  to 
increase  at  a  slower  rate  to  periods  of  about  48  to  72  hours.  With 
intervals  longer  than  this,  behavior  strength  declines,  presumably 
as  a  consequence  of  inanition. 

Instrumental  Behavior  and  Level  of  Noxious  Stimulation.  While 
food  and  water  deprivation  are  the  most  commonly  manipulated 
motivational  variables,  our  treatment  of  primary  sources  of  drive 
would  be  incomplete  without  some  mention  of  the  ways  in  which 
intense  stimuli  may  motivate  instrumental  responses. 

In  experimental  work  with  animals,  electric  shock,  because  of 
the  relative  ease  with  which  it  can  be  applied  and  controlled,  has 
been  used  more  frequently  than  any  other  noxious  stimulus.  Ex- 
periments have  also  been  reported,  however,  in  which  loud  sounds, 
bright  lights,  intense  olfactory  and  gustatory  stimuli,  and  exces- 
sively hot  or  cold  environments  have  been  employed  as  motivators. 

As  the  student  of  learning  is  well  aware,  noxious  stimuli  are 
used  as  unconditioned  stimuli  (UCSs)  in  studies  of  classical 
(Pavlovian)  aversive  conditioning  with  both  human  and  animal 
subjects.  Unfortunately,  UCS  intensity  has  seldom  been  system- 
atically varied  in  animal  experiments,  and  it  is  necessary,  therefore, 
to  rely  upon  instrumental  conditioning  studies  for  information  as 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  83 

to  the  motivational  consequences  of  this  variable.  In  Chapter  1, 
the  role  of  \]CS>  intensity  in  classical  aversive  conditioning  with 
human  subjects  will  be  discussed. 

In  research  on  noxious  stimuli  as  motivators  of  instrumental 
actions,  the  situation  is  commonly  arranged  so  that  the  subject, 
by  performing  either  a  previously  established  response  or  by  learn- 
ing a  new  one,  can  escape  from  or  terminate  the  noxious  stimulus. 
Proficiency  in  the  performance  of  the  designated  response  is  then 
measured  at  different  levels  of  the  noxious  stimulus.  Experiments 
by  Amsel  (1950cz)  and  by  Campbell  and  Kraeling  (1953)  serve 
as  examples  of  this  general  procedure. 

In  AmseFs  study,  two  groups  of  hooded  rats  were  given  practice 
in  escaping  from  a  section  of  a  straight  alley  with  an  electrified 
floor  into  a  wooden-floored  goal  box.  The  two  groups  were  satiated 
with  food  and  water  at  the  time  of  these  trials  and,  save  for  the 
fact  that  one  group  was  given  weak  shocks  and  the  other  strong, 
were  treated  identically.  The  performance  of  the  two  groups  was 
evaluated  by  measuring  the  time  they  took  to  traverse  the  middle 
4-foot  section  of  the  60-inch  alley.  Figure  3:8  presents  the  median 
running  times  for  the  strong-shock  and  weak-shock  groups  as  a 
function  of  10  successive  training  trials  administered  during  a 
single  day. 

From  the  data  in  Fig.  3:8  it  appears  that  although  the  animals 
were  not  motivated  by  either  hunger  or  thirst,  the  shock  provided 
a  strong  drive  to  activate  running,  and  its  cessation  following 
escape  from  the  alley  functioned  as  a  reinforcing  agent.  More- 
over, although  both  groups  quickly  acquired  the  new  skill  of 
running  to  escape  shock,  the  strong-shock  group  maintained  a 
consistently  higher  performance  level  (shorter  running  times) 
than  did  the  weak-shock  group,  Amsel  tried  to  prevent  the  rats 
from  becoming  negatively  adapted  to  the  shock  by  gradually 
increasing  its  strength,  but  the  tendency  for  both  curves  to  rise 
toward  the  end  of  a  second  day  of  training  (not  shown  in  Fig. 
3:8)  may  indicate  the  occurrence  of  such  adaptation. 

The  experiment  of  Campbell  and  Kraeling  (1953)  also  shows 
that  the  performance  of  rats  in  an  escape  situation  is  facilitated 
by  increasingly  strong  electric  shock.  Acquisition  curves  obtained 
from  three  groups  of  animals  that  were  escaping  from  different 


84 


THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 


12        3        4        5        6 
Trials 


10 


Fig.  3:8.  Median  running  times  over  trials  for  two  groups  of  rats  (N  =  28 
per  group)  given  weak  and  strong  shocks  in  a  short  straight-alley  maze. 
{Adapted  from  Amsel,  19S0a.) 


levels  of  shock  into  a  neutral  goal  box  are  reproduced  in  Fig.  3:9. 
As  these  data  indicate,  the  strong  shock  provided  a  more  power- 
ful drive  for  running,  even  on  early  trials,  than  did  the  weaker 
shocks.  In  commenting  on  these  and  other  groups  run  in  their 
investigation,  Campbell  and  Kraeling  state  that  on  the  initial  trials 
most  of  their  subjects  ran  at  a  speed  proportional  to  the  intensity 
of  the  shock.  Nevertheless,  the  performance  level  of  the  three 
groups  differed  but  little  by  the  time  training  was  terminated. 
On  the  basis  of  statistical  analyses  of  these  data,  Campbell  and 
Kraeling  concluded  that  rate  of  acquisition  varied  significantly 
with  amount  of  shock  reduction  but  that  final  running  speed  did 
not.  They  suggest  that  differences  in  response  strength  might 
have  been  observed  if  a  different  measure  had  been  used.  If  all 
animals  were  running  at  or  near  their  maximum  speeds  by  the 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE 


85 


80  - 


70  - 


60  - 


£  50 


40  - 


30  - 


20 


400  volts\          ^o °^ 

^^^         ^  -^^-^——H 

- 

0 

-"-^.--^      f 

.^       i 

^^"^300           / 

A'^        volts 

/ 

-    n 

A 

/ 

/^200  volts 

/ 

.A 

.y^ 

.^ 

D^ 

1 

1                          I                         1                          1 

2-3 


4-6  7-9 

Trials 


10-12 


13-15 


Fig.  3:9.  These  curves  show  the  effects  of  different  intensities  of  electric 
shock  on  the  speeds  with  which  rats  run  to  escape  shock.  Speeds  for  trial  1 
are  plotted  separately  to  indicate  the  effect  of  shock  on  running  speed  prior 
to  the  first  successful  escape  experience.  {From  Campbell  and  Kraeling,  J 953.) 

end  of  practice,  an  artificial  ceiling  would  be  imposed  on  mag- 
nitude of  response. 

To  the  writer's  knowledge,  the  only  investigation  in  which  a 
functional  relation  has  been  obtained  between  time  of  air  depriva- 
tion and  performance  is  one  by  Broadhurst  (1957).  Since  there 
seems  to  be  little  question  of  the  noxious  nature  of  stimulation 
resulting  from  interference  with  breathing,  studies  of  its  motiva- 
tional properties  quite  properly  deserve  mention  at  this  point.  The 
curve  of  Fig.  3:10  reproduced  from  Broadhurst's  paper  is,  in  large 
measure,  self-explanatory.  It  shows  that  the  speed  with  which  rats 
swam  under  water  through  a  short  straight  alley  increased 
progressively  as  the  period  of  air  deprivation  prior  to  their  release 
was  increased.  Broadhurst  used  20  rats  in  this  portion  of  his  ex- 
periment, all  of  them  being  tested  at  each  of  the  several  air- 
deprivation  intervals.  The  subjects  had  had  preliminary  practice 
in  underwater  swimming  before  these  tests,  and  it  seems  likely. 


86 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


therefore,  that  this  curve  provides  a  reasonably  accurate  picture 
of  the  effects  of  air  deprivation  upon  performance  level  at  or  near 
the  learning  asymptote.  The  slight  drop  of  the  curve  from  the 
20-  to  the  25-second  point  may  be,  as  Broadhurst  suggests,  a  con- 
sequence of  anoxia  at  the  longest  deprivation  interval. 

Incidentally,  a  stimulus  such  as  electric  shock  may  function  as 
a  primary  source  of  drive  for  the  learning  of  new  responses  even 
when  applied  directly  to  the  brain  rather  than  to  peripheral 
sensory  surfaces.  For  example,  in  a  study  by  Cohen,  Brown,  and 
Brown  (1957)  stimulation  of  the  hypothalamus  in  cats  served  to 
motivate  the  learning  of  both  instrumental  escape  and  anticipatory 
(conditioned)  avoidance  responses.  Central  stimulation  thus  ex- 
hibits functional  similarities  to  the  traditional  grid-shock  UCS,  a 
finding  confirmed  by  Bower  and  Miller  (1958),  and  by  Roberts 
(1958),  among  others.  The  two  methods  of  shock  administration 
differ,  however,  in  that  central  shock  seems  to  lead  directly  to  a 
motivating  emotional  state  without  arousing  the  pain  that  grid 
shock  produces.  Intracranial  shock  may  thus  be  an  instance  of  a 
motivational  variable  having  minimal  directive  (stimulus)  conse- 
quences and  maximal  motivating  effects.  This  has  important  im- 
phcations  for  the  interpretation  of  experiments  in  which  the  onset 


0.42 


0  5  10  15  20 

Seconds  of  air  deprivation  prior  to  test 

Fig.  3:10.  The  speed  with  which  rats  swim  through  an  underwater  maze 
as  a  function  of  the  length  of  an  immediately  preceding  period  during  which 
they  have  been  deprived  of  air.  The  ordinal  values  are  reciprocals  of  swim- 
ming times  in  seconds.  {Adapted  from  Broadhurst,  1957.) 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  87 

of  central  shock  proves  to  be  reinforcing  rather  than  punishing, 
but  v^^e  shall  postpone  our  discussion  of  this  topic  until  Chapter  9. 

It  seems  justified,  from  these  and  other  studies  (e.g.,  Miller 
and  Dollard,  1941;  Kaplan,  1952;  Ketchell,  1955;  Spence,  1956), 
to  conclude  that  under  certain  conditions  intense  stimuli  can 
serve  as  a  primary  source  of  drive  to  motivate  the  performance 
of  instrumental  acts.  Moreover,  responses  followed  by  the  cessation 
of  such  stimuli  tend  to  be  learned,  and  the  stronger  the  stimulus, 
within  limits,  the  better  the  performance.  Nevertheless,  it  is  well 
to  remember  that  the  motivating  and  rewarding  function  of 
strong  external  stimuli  is  always  complicated  by  their  capacity  to 
elicit  specific  responses.  These  reactions  may  be  the  correct  ones 
in  a  given  experimental  situation,  or  they  may  be  wrong  and  in 
competition  with  the  correct  ones,  and  their  relative  strengths 
may  vary  with  stimulus  intensity.  As  an  example,  if  weak  grid 
shock  elicits  responses  of  jumping  and  running  in  rats,  oriented 
escape  reactions  will  perhaps  be  readily  learned.  But  with  intense 
shock,  crouching  may  become  prepotent  over  running,  and  the 
process  of  learning  to  escape  may  be  retarded  even  though  level 
of  motivation  may  be  higher  than  before.  Clearly,  any  conclusions 
as  to  the  motivating  function  of  strong  stimuli  should,  in  principle, 
include  some  reference  to  the  associative  (response-eliciting)  prop- 
erties of  those  stimuli. 

Up  to  this  point,  our  discussion  of  the  effects  of  primary  sources 
of  drive  has  dealt  only  with  relatively  simple  situations  and  simple 
responses.  To  round  out  the  picture  we  turn  now  to  the  exam- 
ination of  a  few  selected  investigations  in  which  primary  sources 
of  drive  have  been  varied  in  choice  and  discrimination  situations. 

Behavior  in  Spatial  Choice  Situations  as  a  Function  of  Primary 
Motivational  Variables.  The  simple  T  maze  is  one  of  the  most 
frequently  used  experimental  situations  in  which  animals  must 
learn  to  choose  between  two  alternative  goals  or  response  se- 
quences. Since  the  response  to  be  learned  is  simply  to  turn  toward 
and  approach  a  goal  on  either  the  left  or  right,  the  T  maze  is 
sometimes  described  as  a  two-choice  spatial  situation.  It  is  usually 
distinguished,  therefore,  from  a  discrimination  situation  in  which 
the  animal  must  approach  a  specific  stimulus,  such  as  a  white 
card,  regardless  of  its  spatial  position. 


88 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


Choice  of  the  correct  side  of  the  T  maze  may  be  induced  in  a 
number  of  ways.  The  animal  may  be  rewarded  on  one  side  but 
not  on  the  other;  he  may  be  given  more  frequent  rewarded  trials 
or  larger  rewards  on  one  side;  or  he  may  be  rewarded  on  one  side 
and  punished  on  the  other.  Sometimes  animals  are  permitted  to 
correct  an  error  that  has  led  to  punishment  or  nonreward  (cor- 
rection method),  and  sometimes  they  are  simply  removed  from 
the  maze  (noncorrection  method).  In  all  cases  efficiency  of  per- 
formance is  evaluated  by  counting  the  number  of  choices  of  the 
correct  side  during  the  course  of  learning,  these  data  being  sup- 
plemented occasionally  by  measurements  of  running  speed  in  the 
stem  or  to  the  correct  and  incorrect  sides. 

Another  practical  device  for  studying  the  learning  of  choice  reac- 
tions is  the  apparatus  described  by  Logan  (1952).  The  schematic 
drawing  in  Fig.  3:11  shows  that  the  principal  features  of  the 
apparatus  are  a  starting  box  and  a  choice  compartment.  When  the 
guillotine  doors  are  opened,  the  rat  must  leave  the  starting  box, 
enter  the  choice  compartment,  and  touch  one  of  the  two  small 
bars  projecting  out  into  the  compartment  from  the  back  wall. 
When  the  correct  bar  is  touched,  a  small  pellet  of  food  drops 


Opaque  barrier 


Scale  of  inches 


Glass  door 


Metal  door 


Starting  box 


Fig.  3:11.  Floor  plan  of  apparatus 
used  to  investigate  choice  behavior 
in  rats.  At  the  experimenter's  dis- 
cretion, either  or  both  sides  of  the 
choice  compartment  can  be  made 
distinctive  by  svi'itching  on  lights 
above  each  of  the  bars.  Response 
speed  is  obtained  by  measuring  the 
time  that  elapses  between  the  open- 
ing of  the  glass  door  and  the  mo- 
ment at  which  the  rat  touches  a 
bar.  {Adapted  from  Logan,  1952.) 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  89 

into  the  food  cup  below  the  bar  and  the  bar  is  withdrawn  from 
sight.  As  in  the  T  maze,  performance  may  be  evaluated  either 
from  number  of  correct  choices  or  from  response  speed.  Speed 
is  determined  by  measuring  the  time  between  the  opening  of 
the  doors  and  the  touching  of  the  bar.  While  the  T  maze  and  the 
two-bar  choice  box  differ  in  many  respects,  the  same  principles 
of  learning  and  motivation  may  be  applicable  to  both.  Certainly 
the  problem  of  immediate  concern  with  both  is  whether  proficiency 
in  the  execution  of  choice  reactions  is  meaningfully  and  lawfully 
related  to  variations  in  the  strengths  of  primary  sources  of  drive. 

Systematic  experimental  studies  of  choice  behavior  as  a  function 
of  drive  are  relatively  scarce,  but  the  weight  of  evidence  points 
to  the  conclusion  that  selection  of  the  correct  side  is  unrelated  to 
time  of  food  deprivation.  This  generalization  seems  to  be  restricted, 
however,  to  experiments  in  which  the  animals  are  not  permitted 
to  rectify  their  errors  (noncorrection  method)  and  in  which  they 
are  forced  to  go  to  the  incorrect  (nonrewarding)  side  as  often  as 
they  are  permitted  to  go  to  the  correct  side. 

The  study  we  use  to  illustrate  this  conclusion  is  one  whose 
different  aspects  have  been  reported  by  Teel  and  Webb  (1951) 
and  by  Teel  (1952).  Four  groups  of  albino  rats,  21  per  group, 
were  trained  in  a  single-unit  T  maze  under  food-deprivation 
periods  of  1,  7,  15,  and  22  hours,  respectively.  Of  the  four  trials 
given  each  subject  on  each  of  14  days,  two  were  free-choice  trials 
and  two  were  forced.  On  free  trials  both  choice-point  doors  were 
open,  whereas  on  forced  trials  only  one  was  open  and  access  to 
only  one  arm  of  the  T  was  permitted.  This  procedure  was  used 
to  equate  the  number  of  reinforced  and  nonreinforced  runs  for 
all  animals.  The  arbitrary  criterion  of  learning  was  eight  correct 
choices  in  succession. 

Analyses  of  the  data  revealed  that  the  mean  number  of  trials 
required  by  the  four  groups  to  reach  the  criterion  of  learning  did 
not  decrease  with  increasing  time  of  food  deprivation.  In  fact,  a 
small  but  consistent  trend  in  the  opposite  direction  was  obtained. 
It  was  also  found,  as  reported  in  the  Teel  and  Webb  paper,  that 
when  trials  were  administered  under  near-satiation  conditions,  level 
of  performance  was  not  significantly  reduced.  Again,  this  indicates 
that  performance  in  a  choice  situation,  as  estimated  by  correct 


90  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

reactions,  is  unrelated  to  deprivation  time.  Data  tending  to  corrob- 
orate those  of  Teel  and  Webb  have  been  reported  by  Loess 
(1952),  who  used  the  two-bar  choice  box;  by  Champion  (1954), 
who  employed  a  T  maze;  and  by  Carlton  (1955),  who  trained  his 
subjects  on  an  elevated  Y-like  maze. 

These  studies  are  consistent  in  finding  choice  proficiency  to  be 
unrelated  to  level  of  deprivation,  but  other  experiments  in  which 
different  procedures  were  followed  have  produced  positive  results. 
For  example,  Ramond  (1954)  found,  with  the  two-bar  choice 
box,  that  rats  under  22  hours  of  food  deprivation  performed 
significantly  better  than  others  under  4  hours  of  deprivation.  His 
subjects,  however,  were  given  twice  as  many  reinforced  trials  to  one 
bar  as  to  the  other,  and  his  performance  measure  was  the  per- 
centage of  times  the  more  frequently  rewarded  bar  was  chosen. 
Thus,  frequencies  of  left-  and  right-bar  choices  were  unequal, 
which  was  not  the  case  in  studies  with  negative  findings. 

Additional  evidence  for  a  positive  relation  between  strength 
of  motivation  and  behavior  in  simple  and  multiple  choice  situa- 
tions may  be  found  in  the  investigations  of  Siegel  (1943),  Tolman 
and  Gleitman  (1949),  Miller  (1948ib),  and  Davenport  (1956).  In 
all  of  these  studies,  however,  as  in  Ramond's,  the  procedures  were 
such  that  the  number  of  responses  made  to  the  correct  and  incor- 
rect sides  of  the  apparatus  were  either  purposely  made  unequal 
or  were  permitted  to  become  unequal  during  the  course  of  learn- 
ing. As  Spence  (1956)  and  Ramond  (1954)  have  pointed  out, 
one  would  not  expect  a  variation  in  drive  to  affect  choice  behavior 
unless  the  training  methods  produce  differences  in  the  strengths 
of  the  habits  corresponding  to  the  two  reactions.  If  the  habits  are 
kept  equal  by  the  use  of  forced  trials,  drive  differences  arising 
from  changes  in  deprivation  should  not  affect  percentage  choice. 
The  explication  of  the  details  of  this  prediction  is  rather  lengthy, 
and  hence  it  will  be  postponed  to  the  next  chapter,  where  we 
shall  be  concerned  more  directly  with  such  matters. 

Behavior  in  Discrimination  Situations  as  a  Function  of  Primary 
Motivational  Variables.  As  we  have  noted,  it  is  customary  to  apply 
the  term  discrimination  learning  to  situations  in  which  an  animal 
must  acquire  a  specific  response  to  an  environmental  cue  having 
no  fixed  spatial  location.  For  instance,  in  a  black-white  discrimina- 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  91 

tion  the  positive  stimulus  is  usually  presented  equally  often  in  the 
right  and  left  positions  in  the  apparatus.  Hence,  success  in  the 
performance  of  the  discrimination  cannot  be  achieved  unless 
tendencies  to  prefer  one  side  or  the  other  are  overcome.  It  is  in 
this  principal  respect  that  discrimination  situations  differ  from  the 
spatial-choice  problems  we  have  just  examined. 

It  is  somewhat  regrettable,  from  the  point  of  view  of  under- 
standing phenomena  in  this  area,  that  investigations  of  the  role 
of  motivation  in  discrimination  learning  are  even  less  plentiful 
than  those  concerned  with  simple  choice  reactions.  Perhaps  the 
earliest  relevant  study  is  one  by  Yerkes  and  Dodson  (1908),  who 
examined  the  relation  of  shock  intensity  to  performance  on  visual- 
discrimination  problems  of  varying  levels  of  difficulty.  One  of  the 
principal  findings  of  this  investigation  was  that  performance  on 
easy  discriminations  tended  to  improve  progressively  with  shock 
intensity.  But  on  difficult  problems  performance  was  poorer  with 
weak  and  with  strong  shocks  than  with  shocks  of  intermediate 
strength.  This  latter  finding  led  them  to  propose  a  general  prin- 
ciple, since  known  as  the  Yerkes-Dodson  law,  to  the  effect  that 
there  is  an  optimal  motivational  level  for  learning,  which  tends 
to  decrease  as  problem  difficulty  increases.  Subsequently,  Dodson 
(1917)  performed  a  follow-up  experiment,  in  which  rats  were 
taught  a  light-dark  discrimination  under  several  intensities  of 
hunger.  The  results  obtained  were  coordinate  with  those  of  the 
first  study,  since  performance  improved  for  values  of  food  depriva- 
tion up  to  41  hours  but  became  worse  when  the  period  was  ex- 
tended to  48  hours.  Shock  was  also  used  for  some  animals  in  the 
second  study  and  was  found  to  be  most  efficacious  when  neither 
too  strong  nor  too  weak. 

More  recent  studies  of  the  relation  of  hunger  to  performance 
in  a  discrimination  situation  are  those  by  Dinsmoor  (1952),  by 
Eisman  (1956),  and  by  Eisman,  Asimow,  and  Maltzman  (1956). 
In  Dinsmoor's  investigation,  rats  were  trained  initially  to  press  a 
bar  while  starved  down  to  85  per  cent  of  their  normal  body  weight. 
Then  they  were  given  further  training  in  making  the  discrimina- 
tory response  of  pressing  the  bar  in  the  presence  of  a  light  and  not 
pressing  it  in  the  dark.  Final  tests  were  carried  out  with  satiated 
animals  and  with  animals  maintained  at  100,  95,  90,  85,  80,  and  75 


92 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


per  cent  of  normal  weight.  The  tests  with  percentage  weights  of 
80  and  75  represent  a  greater  food  need  than  that  in  effect  during 
original  training,  and  the  weights  of  90,  95,  and  100,  as  well  as  the 
satiated  condition,  constitute  weaker  need  values.  The  results  of 
the  study  are  presented  in  Fig.  3:12.  Of  principal  interest  here  is 
the  finding  that  the  difference  between  the  number  of  responses 
to  the  positive  stimulus  (light)  and  negative  stimulus  (no  light) 
increased  as  hunger  was  heightened  above  the  level  used  in  train- 
ing. Thus  an  increase  in  hunger,  even  after  fairly  extensive  training 
has  been  carried  out,  seems  to  lead  to  improved  proficiency  in 
responding  differentially  to  the  positive  and  negative  cues.  Dins- 
moor's  data  also  indicate  that  differences  between  responses  to 
the  two  cues  decrease  as  hunger  is  reduced,  with  the  total  number 
of  responses  declining  also.  Dinsmoor's  animals  were  trained,  as 
has  been  pointed  out,  at  only  a  single  level  of  deprivation,  a 
procedure  that  may  have  permitted  associative  (habit)  as  well  as 
motivational  (drive)  variables  to  affect  his  results.  As  we  shall  see 
in  the  next  chapter,  associative  factors  provide  a  reasonable  basis 
for  explaining  the  convergence  of  the  curves  as  drive  level  is  re- 
duced but  not  their  divergence  as  drive  is  increased.  Dinsmoor's 


Positive- 
stimulus 

y^ 

^  1000 

c 
o 

CL 
I/) 
<U 

O 

0) 

1    500 

y^ 

<,-——^ 

, Negative 
/stimulus 

^ 

n 

1          1          1 

1 

Sat. 


100      95       90       85       80       75 
Per  cent  normal  body  weight 


Fig.  3:12.  Data  obtained  in  a  study  of  the  effects  of  varying  degrees  of 
hunger  on  behavior  in  a  discrimination  situation.  The  ordinate  shows  the 
number  of  lever-pressing  responses  made  to  the  positive  stimulus  (light) 
and  negative  stimulus  (no  light)  during  a  90-minute  test  period.  The  initial 
points  of  the  curves  were  obtained  following  a  period  of  continuous  feeding 
(satiation).  {From  Dinsmoor,  1952.) 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  93 

experiment,  therefore,  seems  to  support  the  earher  conclusion  of 
Dodson  that  the  performance  of  a  (simple)  discrimination  task 
is  facilitated  increasingly  by  heightened  hunger. 

The  remaining  two  experiments  of  Eisman,  Asimow,  and  Maltz- 
man  and  of  Eisman  provide  further  evidence  for  a  positive  relation 
between  discrimination-task  performance  and  level  of  motivation. 
In  the  first  of  these  experiments,  rats  run  in  a  black-white,  Y-type 
discrimination  apparatus  under  46  hours  of  food  deprivation  made 
fewer  errors  and  required  fewer  trials  and  reinforcements  to  reach 
a  learning  criterion  than  did  rats  trained  under  22  hours  or  4 
hours  of  deprivation.  The  4-hour  and  22-hour  groups  did  not,  how- 
ever, differ  significantly  with  respect  to  any  of  the  three  measures. 
This  rather  unexpected  finding  was  interpreted  by  supposing  that 
the  rat's  stomach  takes  about  four  hours  to  empty  following  eating, 
and  that  after  this  further  deprivation  has  no  effect  upon  drive. 
On  these  assumptions,  the  drive  levels  of  the  4-  and  22-hour  groups 
should  have  been  identical. 

But  the  fact  that  the  46-hour  group  was  superior  to  both  of  the 
others  could  not  be  explained  without  additional  assumptions. 
As  a  consequence,  Eisman  (1956)  suggested  that  drive  level  also 
depends  upon  the  general  severity  of  the  deprivation  schedule 
under  which  the  animal  has  been  maintained.  This  variable  which 
he  termed  "hours  of  deprivation  during  a  unit  of  time"  is  believed 
to  operate  jointly  with  the  more  conventional  factor  of  "time 
since  eating."  Thus  one  is  led  to  the  expectation  that  if  two  groups 
have  been  fed,  say,  22  hours  previously,  but  if  one  of  them  has 
been  maintained  on  a  46-hour  deprivation  schedule,  it  will  have  a 
higher  drive  level  than  one  maintained  on  a  22-hour  schedule. 
Eisman's  experiment,  designed  specifically  to  test  this  hypothesis, 
yielded  clear  confirmatory  results.  More  directly  related  to  the 
topic  under  discussion,  however,  was  Eisman's  finding  that  high- 
drive  groups,  defined  by  reference  to  the  severity  of  the  mainte- 
nance schedule,  performed  more  efficiently  on  a  black-white  dis- 
crimination problem  than  did  low-drive  subjects. 

It  might  seem  justifiable,  in  the  light  of  the  evidence  provided 
by  these  studies,  to  conclude  that,  in  general,  performance  in  the 
learning  of  a  discrimination  reaction  improves  as  a  function  of 
heightened  motivation.  But  exceptions  to  this  conclusion  are  to 


94  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

be  found  in  the  performance  of  the  4-  and  22-hour  groups  of  the 
Eisman-Asimow-Maltzman  study  and  in  an  unpubHshed  study  by 
Myers  (1952).  This  latter  investigator  found  no  relationship  be- 
tween drive  differences  due  to  4  and  21  hours  of  food  deprivation 
and  performance  in  a  T-shaped  brightness-discrimination  appara- 
tus. Meyer  (1951)  has  likewise  found  that  in  experiments  with 
monkeys  rather  large  differences  in  time  of  deprivation  do  not 
affect  performance  in  a  discrimination-reversal  situation.  Until 
these  negative  findings  have  been  satisfactorily  accounted  for,  the 
wisest  course  of  action  is  to  withhold  final  judgment.  Further 
studies  of  the  relations  of  changes  in  primary  sources  of  drive  to 
discrimination  learning  and  of  the  conditions  determining  specific 
outcomes  are  urgently  needed. 

Summary 

The  first  sections  of  this  chapter  were  concerned  primarily  with 
the  elucidation  of  various  terms  frequently  encountered  in  discus- 
sions of  motivation.  Initially  it  was  observed  that  a  distinction  is 
commonly  made  by  theorists  between  motivating  or  activating 
variables  and  variables  that  function  to  guide  or  direct  behavior. 
The  terms  drive,  conations,  emotions,  and  motivation  have  been 
used  in  conjunction  with  members  of  the  first  class,  and  cognitions, 
associative  bonds,  and  habit  strengths  with  the  second  class.  Cer- 
tain variables,  however,  are  diflBcult  to  classify  because  they  appear 
to  function  both  as  directive  cues  that  elicit  specific  responses  and 
as  relatively  nonspecific  motivators.  To  reduce  confusion  it  was 
suggested  that  such  variables  be  conceptualized  as  leading  to  two 
intermediary  processes  having  the  nonoverlapping  functions  of 
behavior  direction  and  of  motivation,  respectively. 

As  a  further  step  toward  terminological  clarity,  it  was  proposed 
that  the  use  of  the  plural  word  "drives"  be  dropped  in  favor  of 
the  singular  form.  This  suggestion  was  supported  primarily  by  the 
contention  that  the  so-called  drives  can  be  differentiated  with 
respect  to  their  individual  antecedent  variables,  but  not  in  terms 
of  their  postulated  effects  upon  behavior.  The  phrase  "multiple 
sources  of  drive"  is  proposed  in  place  of  the  word  drives. 

In  accordance  with  current  practice,  a  distinction  was  also  made 


PRIMARY  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  95 

between  sources  of  drive  that  achieve  their  motivating  effects 
through  the  operation  of  inherited  homeostatic  mechanisms  and 
those  whose  effects  are  largely  contingent  on  prior  learning.  Tlie 
former  are  here  termed  "primary  sources  of  drive"  and  the  latter 
"secondary  sources  of  drive." 

The  variables  of  food  and  of  water  deprivation  have  been  studied 
more  extensively  than  any  others  by  students  of  primary  sources 
of  drive.  And  since  intakes  of  food  and  water  have  often  been  used 
as  indexes  of  the  resulting  drive,  the  problem  of  how  such  intakes 
are  regulated  becomes  of  considerable  significance.  Contemporary 
thinking  in  this  area  places  primary  emphasis  upon  two  factors: 
oropharyngeal  stimulation  produced  by  chewing  and  swallowing, 
and  stomach  distention.  Each  of  these  processes  exercise  some  con- 
trol over  ingestion  when  operating  separately,  but  neither  is 
alone  sufficient  to  account  for  all  consummatory  behavior.  Thus 
stimulation  of  receptors  in  the  mouth  and  throat  serves  as  a  signal 
tending  to  produce  cessation  of  eating  or  drinking,  but  unless 
aided  by  additional  signals  from  the  stomach,  the  control  of  in- 
gestion is  incomplete.  Circulating  nutrients  in  the  blood  and 
stored  nutrients  in  the  tissues  probably  also  play  a  role,  but  the 
specific  mechanisms  involved  have  not  been  clearly  detailed. 

In  the  context  of  our  discussion  of  factors  controlling  ingestion, 
it  was  observed  that  a  distinction  can  be  profitably  made  between 
need  and  drive.  This  is  because  drive  can  apparently  be  reduced 
by  variables  that  cannot  possibly  modify  a  physiological  need  and 
because  a  need  arising  from  deprivation  may  continue  to  increase 
until  death,  whereas  the  resulting  drive  increases  and  decreases 
with  time.  It  was  also  noted  that  the  maintenance  of  this  distinc- 
tion may  clarify  the  interpretation  of  experiments  directed  against 
the  drive-reduction  hypothesis  of  learning. 

The  major  portion  of  the  chapter  dealt  with  studies  of  the 
effects  of  primary  sources  of  drive  upon  consummatory  behavior, 
upon  instrumental  responses,  and  upon  performance  in  discrimi- 
nation situations.  Concerning  the  relation  of  deprivation  to  oral 
intake,  available  data  indicate  that  consummatory  activity  in- 
creases as  a  monotonic  function  of  hours  of  deprivation  up  to 
periods  of  the  order  of  two  or  three  days.  Beyond  these  limits 
ingestive  activity  declines,  presumably  as  a  consequence  of  general 


96  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

bodily  weakness.  Estimates  of  drive  strength  based  upon  consum- 
matory  responses  are  complicated,  however,  by  learned  tendencies 
to  eat  or  drink  at  certain  times  and  by  the  kind  of  deprivation 
schedule  in  effect  prior  to  the  test. 

Studies  of  the  effects  of  deprivation  upon  responses  instrumental 
to  securing  food  or  water  support  the  conclusion  that  the  speed  of 
these  responses  and  their  resistance  to  extinction  tend  to  be  en- 
hanced by  privation.  Learning  curves  for  different  privation  levels 
tend  to  diverge  at  a  relatively  early  stage  of  practice  and  to  main- 
tain a  constant  separation  thereafter,  asymptotic  performance 
levels  being  directly  related  to  deprivation  duration  from  about 
2  to  perhaps  72  hours,  but  not  beyond. 

Noxious  stimuli  appear  to  provide  a  convenient  primary  source 
of  drive,  and  performance  under  a  variety  of  conditions,  especially 
those  in  which  escape  responses  are  investigated,  is  directly  related 
to  stimulus  intensity.  The  fact  that  exceptions  are  common,  how- 
ever, indicates  that  noxious  stimuli  may  sometimes  elicit  compet- 
ing responses  and  may  thereby  lead  to  performance  decrements. 

Experiments  on  the  learning  of  spatial-choice  reactions,  as  in  T 
mazes,  are  relatively  consistent  in  showing  that  performance  is 
unrelated  to  privation  when  the  associative  strengths  of  the  alter- 
nate response  tendencies  are  deliberately  held  equal.  When  one 
response  is  more  frequently  reinforced,  however,  choice  behavior 
becomes  more  proficient  as  motivation  is  increased.  In  visual-dis- 
crimination problems  the  effects  of  drive  variations  remain  ob- 
scure, since  high  drive  sometimes  facilitates  performance  and 
sometimes  does  not. 


CHAPTER 

iiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiii^ 


4 


Motivational  and 
Associative  Interpretations 
of  "Motivated"  Behavior 

From  time  to  time  in  the  preceding  chapters  we  have  noted  that 
changes  in  behavior  following  the  manipulation  of  motivational 
variables  can  sometimes  be  explained  by  other  than  motivational 
concepts.  Moreover,  we  have  stressed  the  view  that  any  experi- 
ment purporting  to  demonstrate  motivational  effects  is  not  con- 
vincing unless  the  influence  of  other  factors  has  been  eliminated 
or  controlled.  Altering  a  so-called  motivational  variable  may  in- 
deed modify  drive  strength;  but  it  may  also  lead  to  changes  in  the 
intensity  and  kinds  of  effective  stimuli,  in  degree  of  learning,  or  in 
the  physiological  condition  of  the  organism.  Whenever  variations 
in  factors  such  as  these  provide  acceptable  explanations  for  the 
observed  behavior  the  concept  of  drive  may  become  expendable. 
The  question  arises,  therefore,  whether  a  specific  drive  construct 
is  needed  at  all  by  an  adequate  theory  of  behavior.  Certainly,  if 
drive  adds  nothing  to  the  clarity  of  our  explanations  or  to  the 
breadth  of  our  understanding,  the  principle  of  parsimony  would 
argue  for  its  complete  elimination.  This  possibility  is  tempting  to 

97 


98  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

motivational  theorists,  and  in  recent  years  it  has  claimed  their 
attention  to  an  increasing  degree.  Our  purpose  in  the  present 
chapter  is  to  evaluate  the  relative  merits  of  the  views  that  dispense 
with,  and  appeal  to,  a  drivelike  concept. 

To  facilitate  the  discussion  we  have  chosen  to  describe  the  al- 
ternative views  by  the  terms  motivational  and  associative.  A  mo- 
tivational theory  is  one  containing,  in  a  role  of  central  importance, 
a  unique  construct  to  which  a  specific  label,  e.g.,  drive,  may  be 
attached.  It  is  a  theory  in  which  the  behavior-determining  prop- 
erties assigned  to  the  drive  construct  are  clearly  different  from 
those  ascribed  to  cognitions,  habits,  excitatory  tendencies,  and 
other  constructs.  Hull's  theory,  which  we  have  already  considered 
briefly,  is  a  good  example  of  a  motivational  theory  because  it  con- 
tains the  construct  D  and  because  of  the  special  properties  as- 
signed to  D.  However,  a  motivational  theory,  by  our  definition,  is 
not  one  that  appeals  only  to  motivational  mechanisms  in  attempt- 
ing to  explain  behavior.  Nor  must  it  place  primary  emphasis  upon 
such  mechanisms  to  the  exclusion  of  others.  It  is  simply  one  that 
provides  specific  room  for  a  motivating  mechanism  as  well  as  for 
associative,  excitatory,  inhibitory,  and  other  mechanisms. 

By  way  of  contrast,  the  type  of  theory  we  shall  label  associa- 
tive contains  no  reference  to  concepts  having  such  motivational- 
sounding  names  as  drive,  tension,  or  libidinal  energy.  An  advocate 
of  this  type  of  theory  would  maintain  that  a  separate  drivelike 
intermediary  is  not  needed,  and  that  most,  if  not  all,  of  the  con- 
sequences of  motivational  variables  can  be  explained  by  invoking 
altered  associative  connections  and  their  complex  interrelations.  If 
this  kind  of  view  is  to  prove  successful  in  interpreting  the  known 
facts  of  motivated  behavior,  while  maintaining  an  adequate  degree 
of  internal  consistency,  it  must  not  introduce  additional  constructs 
having  drivelike  titles.  Moreover,  the  functional  properties  of  the 
constructs  in  an  associative  theory  must  be  different  from  those  of 
the  drive  construct  in  a  motivational  theory.  Renaming  drive  with 
a  nondrivelike  title  will  not  suffice.  Actually,  highly  detailed  and 
specific  versions  of  associative  theories  are  just  beginning  to  ap- 
pear, but  the  basic  position  has  gained  increasing  numbers  of 
adherents  in  recent  years,  and  it  deserves,  therefore,  serious  con- 
sideration. 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  99 

Motivational  Interpretations 

Hull's  Multiplicative-drive  Theory.  Probably  the  best  known 
and  most  influential  motivational  theory  is  that  of  Hull  (1943). 
As  we  have  already  seen  in  the  previous  chapter,  Hull  assumed 
that  behavior  is  determined  primarily  by  two  major  intermediary 
factors:  the  nonspecific  drive  state  (D)  and  a  variety  of  learned 
and  unlearned  reactive  or  associative  tendencies.  Unlearned  reac- 
tive tendencies  are  denoted  by  the  symbol  sUr,  and  learned  ten- 
dencies (habit  strengths)  by  sHr,  the  S  and  R  subscripts  being 
used  to  indicate  the  functional  association  of  stimuli  and  responses. 
We  have  chosen  to  apply  the  label  "multiplicative-drive  theory" 
to  this  conception  because  Hull  assumed  that  drive  combines 
multiplicatively  with  any  reactive  tendency  to  yield  a  response- 
determining  resultant  called  excitatory  potential  (sEr).  Expressed 
in  the  form  of  a  simple  equation  with  the  subscripts  omitted, 
E  =  D  X  H,  where  E  stands  for  excitatory  potential,  D  for  drive, 
and  H  for  learned  associative  tendencies.  If  the  reactive  tendency 
were  unlearned,  U  would  be  substituted  for  H  in  the  equation. 
Within  the  system,  excitatory  potential,  modified  by  inhibitory 
and  oscillatory  processes,  governs  the  speed  with  which  a  response 
will  be  made,  its  resistance  to  extinction,  its  amplitude,  and  so  on. 

This  assumption  that  behavior  is  determined  by  the  combined 
operation  of  drive  and  associative  tendencies  has  several  implica- 
tions that  should  be  made  explicit.  In  the  first  place,  since  drive 
is  conceived  simply  as  a  numerical  multiplicative  factor,  it  clearly 
cannot  determine  the  direction  behavior  will  take.  Such  direction- 
controlling  functions  reside  in  the  reactive  tendencies  which  may 
be  loosely  described  as  blueprints  for  action,  or  as  the  organism's 
"know  how."  Moreover,  D  as  a  nonspecific  activator  has  only  the 
one  multiplicative  function  irrespective  of  the  source  from  which 
it  springs. 

A  second  implication  of  the  multiplicative  hvpothesis  relates 
to  the  distinction  commonly  made  by  learning  theorists  between 
learning  and  performance,  where  learning  denotes  the  unseen 
hypothetical  changes  produced  by  training  and  performance  refers 
to  overt  behavior.  This  distinction  has  arisen  from  the  observation 
that  organisms  sometimes  do  not  perform  well  or  perhaps  do  not 


100  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

perform  at  all  even  when  there  is  no  good  reason  to  suppose  that 
they  have  forgotten  the  skills  requisite  to  a  successful  reaction.  In 
Hull's  system,  learning  is  represented  by  habit  strength,  and  per- 
formance is  determined  by  excitatory  potential.  On  the  assump- 
tion that  drive  and  learned  reactive  tendencies  combine  multi- 
plicatively,  it  is  possible  for  him  to  maintain  that  when  either 
D  or  H  has  a  value  of  zero,  the  product  of  the  two  is  zero  (i.e., 
E  =  0)  and  no  overt  behavior  should  be  exhibited.  Thus  an  or- 
ganism can  "know"  what  to  do  (i.e.,  H  can  be  greater  than  zero) 
yet  never  exhibit  this  "know  how"  in  its  performance  if  the  value 
of  D  is  zero.  Such  a  conclusion  could  not  be  reached  if  D  and  H 
were  assumed  to  combine  by  addition  rather  than  by  multiplica- 
tion. 

A  further  consequence  of  Hull's  hypothesis  is  that  one  cannot, 
from  the  manifest  characteristics  of  overt  behavior  alone,  make 
accurate  estimates  of  the  relative  contributions  of  the  two  inter- 
mediaries, D  and  H,  unless  a  number  of  tests  are  given  under  a 
variety  of  conditions.  Any  particular  response  could  be  due  to 
the  presence  of  a  strong  drive  combined  with  a  weak  reactive 
tendency  or  to  a  weak  drive  and  a  strong  reactive  tendency.  When 
behavior  does  become  manifest,  both  determinants  are  assumed 
to  be  present.  But  if  no  response  is  exhibited,  one  cannot  decide, 
without  additional  information,  whether  a  reactive  tendency  is 
present  and  drive  is  not,  or  the  reverse.  If  a  response  suddenly 
fails  to  be  exhibited  where  formerly  it  was  commonplace,  Hull's 
position  would  suggest  that  associative  tendencies  are  present  but 
not  drive,  since  the  former  are  assumed  to  be  relatively  permanent 
and  not  subject  to  abrupt  fluctuations. 

Practical  Implications  of  the  Multiplicative-drive  Theory.  From 
Hull's  assumptions  as  to  the  manner  in  which  a  variety  of  different 
antecedent  conditions  (motivational  variables)  contribute  to  drive, 
and  from  his  hypothesis  of  drive  as  a  multiplier,  a  number  of  prac- 
tical implications  may  be  derived.  In  so  far  as  these  implications 
can  be  supported  by  research  findings,  the  drive  concept  gains  in 
acceptability. 

For  one  thing,  the  theory  implies  that  any  motivational  variable 
can,  within  unspecified  limits,  be  substituted  for  another  since  the 
D  provided  by  each  is  identical.  Thus  if  a  response  has  a  high  prob- 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  101 

ability  of  being  elicited  by  a  stimulus  when  a  subject  is  hungry, 
it  should  also  be  elicitable,  though  not  necessarily  at  the  same 
strength,  when  a  subject  is  thirsty  or  in  pain.  In  principle,  the 
response  could  be  either  learned  or  unlearned,  because  both  kinds 
of  responses  are  affected  by  D  in  the  same  way.  If  positive  results 
are  obtained,  the  theory  tends  to  be  supported.  But  negative 
results,  as  we  shall  see  at  a  later  point  in  this  chapter,  may  be 
inconclusive  since  the  shift  from  one  drive-producing  antecedent 
condition  to  another  may  have  modified  the  cues  to  which  the 
response  was  attached, 

A  second  implication  of  the  theory  is  that  variations  in  strength 
of  drive  produced  by  changing,  say,  time  of  food  deprivation, 
should  ordinarily  alter  the  quantitative  but  not  the  qualitative 
features  of  a  response.  Increasing  D  should  increase  the  speed, 
amplitude,  frequency,  and  resistance  to  extinction  of  a  response; 
but  its  specific  direction  should  remain  unaltered.  Here  again, 
either  learned  or  unlearned  behavior  could  be  studied,  but  positive 
results  would  be  expected  only  if  the  motivational  variable  does 
not  lead  to  marked  changes  in  stimuli  (Smvs)  in  addition  to 
changes  in  D. 

The  drive  theory  also  implies  that  a  wide  variety  of  responses 
should  be  enhanced  by  an  increase  in  drive  and  weakened  by  a 
decrease  in  drive.  This  is  an  obvious  expectation  from  the  hy- 
pothesis that  D  multiplies  all  reactive  tendencies.  This  prediction 
might  be  tested  experimentally  by  determining  which  response  is 
most  likely  to  occur  in  each  of  a  variety  of  different  situations 
when  the  subject  is  operating  under  a  given  level  of  drive.  An 
increase  in  drive  produced  by  suitable  manipulations  of  the  ante- 
cedent conditions  should  ordinarily  lead  to  the  enhancement  of 
all  of  these  maximum-probability  reactions.  Conversely,  all  such 
reactions  should  be  weakened  when  drive  is  lowered. 

The  Multiplicative-drive  Theory  Applied  to  Various  Kinds  of 
Behavioral  Data.  In  order  best  to  understand  how  the  multiplica- 
tive theory  functions  in  the  interpretation  of  behavior,  let  us  apply 
it  to  some  experimental  data  of  the  kind  described  in  the  previous 
chapter.  Later  on  we  shall  show,  for  purposes  of  comparison,  how 
an  associative  theory  containing  no  concept  of  D  might  account 
for  the  same  results. 


102  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Consider  first  an  experimental  result  such  as  that  reported  by 
Koch  and  Daniel  (1945).  These  investigators  trained  rats  to 
depress  a  bar  to  obtain  food  in  a  modified  Skinner-box  apparatus. 
At  the  time  the  response  was  acquired,  the  subjects  were  motivated 
by  22  hours  of  food  deprivation,  and  upon  the  completion  of 
training,  the  response  was  strongly  established.  After  being  thor- 
oughly satiated  with  food,  however,  the  rats  would  scarcely  press 
the  bar  at  all.  The  median  number  of  responses  elicited  from  the 
32  subjects  prior  to  a  five-minute  no-response  interval  was  only 
one.  From  this  result,  Koch  and  Daniel  concluded  that  the  effec- 
tive response  strength  under  conditions  of  satiation  was  essentially 
zero. 

Now  according  to  Hull's  theory,  the  strength  of  the  reactive 
tendency  (habit)  to  press  the  bar  is  not  weakened  by  the  operation 
of  satiation.  The  animal  has  forgotten  neither  how  to  make  the 
response  nor  where  the  food  is  located.  Rather,  the  failure  to  act 
is  a  consequence  of  the  marked  decrease  in  D  accompanying 
satiation.  Suppose  the  associative  tendency  is  given  an  arbitrary 
numerical  value  of  5,  and  the  D  resulting  from  22  hours  of 
deprivation  a  value  of  10.  Multiplying  these  two  quantities  together 
vields  an  excitatory  tendency  (E)  with  a  value  of  50.  Since  the 
animal  does  react  under  these  conditions  it  must  be  presumed  that 
E  is  above  threshold.  But  if  the  drive  is  reduced  through  relatively 
complete  satiation  to  a  value  of,  say,  1  unit,  the  product  of  D  and 
H  is  only  5,  and  the  threshold  may  or  may  not  be  exceeded.  If 
the  threshold  lies  above  5,  the  animal  will  not  respond  at  all. 
The  less  complete  the  process  of  satiation,  the  smaller  the  reduc- 
tion in  the  value  of  D  and  the  less  the  performance  decrement. 
In  this  way,  then,  the  multiplicative-drive  theory  attempts  to 
account  for  the  fact  that  an  animal  will  display  a  previously 
learned  response  when  it  has  been  deprived  of  food,  and  not, 
or  to  a  lesser  degree,  when  satiated. 

In  addition  to  affecting  D,  the  operation  of  satiation 
doubtless  eliminates  some  of  the  internal  stimuli  (Sj/rs)  pro- 
duced by  food  deprivation  and  may  also  introduce  new  cues 
arising  from  stomach  distention.  As  we  have  already  observed  in 
our  discussion  of  Horenstein's  and  Siegel's  experiments  (Chapter 
3),  these  interoceptive  cues  may  function  importantly  as  determin- 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  103 

ants  of  behavior  under  changing  conditions  of  deprivation  pro- 
vided they  have  become  associated  with  critical  responses.  A  "pure" 
motivational  interpretation  cannot  appeal  to  such  internal  cues. 
To  do  so  would  be  to  invoke  a  nonmotivational  (associative) 
explanatory  mechanism.  In  the  foregoing  interpretation  of  the 
Koch  and  Daniel  results,  no  such  associative  mechanism  was 
found  necessary. 

As  Koch  and  Daniel  have  pointed  out,  however,  the  almost 
complete  lack  of  responses  by  their  animals  is  apparently  incon- 
sistent with  Hull's  assumption  that  other  primary  sources  of  drive, 
e.g.,  sexual  deprivation,  also  contribute  to  nonspecific  D.  Their 
subjects  had  been  deprived  of  all  recent  sexual  experiences,  yet 
D,  which  should  have  resulted  from  this  deprivation,  seemingly 
did  not  multiply  the  bar-pressing  tendency  when  hunger  was 
eliminated  by  satiation.  The  theory  asserts  that  D,  considered 
solely  as  a  multiplier,  is  unrelated  to  the  source  from  which  it 
springs.  Consequently,  a  shift  from  one  primary  source  of  drive 
to  another  should  result  in  almost  perfect  response  transfer,  pro- 
vided that  the  second  primary  variable  contributes  as  much  to  D 
as  the  first,  and  provided  the  change  involves  the  introduction 
of  no  competing  tendencies.  To  explain  instances  in  which  a  shift 
from  one  deprivation  condition  to  another  results  in  little  transfer, 
other  principles  must  be  introduced.  The  animals  of  Koch  and 
Daniel  were  not,  of  course,  shifted  from  one  primary  source  of 
drive  to  a  second.  Rather  their  D  was  reduced  from  a  level  pro- 
duced by  hunger  plus  sex  (and  other  factors)  to  a  level  dependent 
only  upon  sex  and  other  factors.  Studies  of  the  effects  of  gona- 
dectomy  upon  the  activity  level  of  rats  (e.g.,  Richter,  1933)  sug- 
gest that  sex  does  make  some  contribution  to  general  drive  level. 
It  may  be,  therefore,  that  in  the  Koch  and  Daniel  study  the 
motivating  effects  of  sexual  deprivation  were  overridden  by  com- 
peting tendencies  to  rest  induced  by  the  extreme  degree  of  satia- 
tion. 

The  effects  of  changes  in  deprivation  conditions  upon  the 
behavior  of  animals  in  a  spatial-choice  situation  constitute  a  second 
typical  observation  to  which  the  multiplicative-drive  theory  may 
be  applied.  As  was  noted  in  Chapter  3,  the  experimental  proce- 
dures used  to  study  behavior  in  these  situations  may  be  such 


104  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

that  the  number  of  responses  to  each  of  the  alternatives  is  either 
equal  or  unequal.  The  multiplicative  interpretation  yields  a  dif- 
ferent prediction  for  each  of  these  situations,  and  it  is  instructive 
to  consider  them  in  turn. 

Ramond's  (1954)  study  with  a  two-bar  choice  box  (see  Chapter 
3)  provides  us  with  an  example  in  which  twice  as  many  rein- 
forced trials  were  given  to  one  bar  as  to  the  other,  separate  groups 
of  animals  being  trained  under  22  and  4  hours  of  food  deprivation, 
respectively.  If  we  assume,  following  Hull,  that  the  strength  of  a 
habit  depends  upon  the  number  of  times  the  response  has  been 
reinforced,  then  the  habits  to  approach  and  touch  the  two  bars 
in  this  experiment  should  have  been  unequal,  and  since  both 
habits  are  multiplied  by  the  same  value  of  D,  the  corresponding 
excitatory  tendencies  should  also  have  been  unequal.  Therefore, 
the  animal  should  choose  the  more  frequently  rewarded  alterna- 
tive, since  the  dominance  of  one  mode  of  reacting  over  another  is 
assumed  to  be  determined  by  absolute  differences  in  the  strengths 
of  the  corresponding  E  values.  Thus  an  observed  dominance  of 
one  mode  of  action  over  another  is  attributed  by  this  theory  to 
differences  in  habits  or  reactive  tendencies.  Drive  makes  it  possible 
for  the  "know  how"  to  be  exhibited  in  overt  performance,  but  it 
does  nothing  to  alter  the  ranks  of  two  (or  more)  reactive  ten- 
dencies. Drive  has  no  inherent  capacity  to  steer  behavior  into  one 
channel  rather  than  another. 

To  continue  the  analysis,  let  us  consider  the  effect  on  perform- 
ance in  the  two-choice  lever  box  of  differences  in  D.  Here  Hull's 
assumption  of  a  multiplicative  relation  between  drive  and  habit 
leads  to  conclusions  quite  in  accord  with  Ramond's  findings. 
That  is,  the  relative  superiority  of  a  stronger  over  a  weaker  excita- 
tory potential  increases  as  drive  is  strengthened,  and  is  reduced  as 
drive  is  weakened.  To  see  precisely  how  this  works  let  us  assign 
an  arbitrary  value  of  10  to  the  habit  tendency  to  press  the  left 
bar,  and  a  value  of  5  to  the  right-bar  tendency  that  has  been 
reinforced  less  often.  If  the  drive  due  to  23  hours  of  deprivation 
is  assumed  to  be  4  units,  the  resulting  E  values  obtained  by 
multiplying  Hs  of  10  and  of  5  by  4  are  40  and  20,  respectively. 
The  absolute  difference  between  these  E  values  is  20,  with  the 
left-bar  excitatory  potential  the  stronger.  But  suppose  that  when 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  105 

the  animal  has  been  partially  satiated  the  strength  of  D  drops  to 
2  units.  In  this  case,  the  absolute  difference  between  the  E  values 
is  decreased  to  10,  since  the  E  value  for  the  left  bar  drops  to  20 
and  that  for  the  right  bar  to  10.  If  the  number  of  correct  responses, 
i.e.,  depressions  of  the  more  frequently  reinforced  bar,  is  deter- 
mined by  the  absolute  difference  between  the  two  Es,  performance 
should  become  poorer  under  the  partial  satiation  conditions.  Con- 
versely, of  course,  performance  should  improve  as  strength  of 
drive  is  increased.  Because  changes  in  drive  intensity  may  thus  lead 
to  either  better  or  poorer  performance,  drive,  in  an  indirect  sense, 
does  have  an  effect  upon  the  direction  behavior  will  take.  It  exerts 
this  effect,  however,  not  by  virtue  of  a  steering  function  inherent 
in  drive  itself,  but  through  its  power  to  change  the  absolute  differ- 
ence between  the  strengths  of  competing  excitatory  potentials. 

An  experiment  by  Teel  (1952),  described  in  Chapter  3,  illus- 
trates the  application  of  the  multiplicative  theory  to  behavior  in 
a  spatial  choice  situation  (T  maze)  where  practice  in  performing 
the  two  responses  has  been  equated.  In  this  study,  it  may  be 
recalled,  four  groups  of  rats  were  trained  under  food  deprivation 
times  of  1,  7,  15,  and  22  hours,  respectively.  Each  rat  was  forced 
to  run  to  one  side  as  often  as  to  the  other  to  equate  practice  in 
running  to  the  rewarding  and  nonrewarding  sides.  When  perform- 
ance was  evaluated  in  terms  of  the  number  of  trials  required  to 
reach  a  learning  criterion  of  eight  successive  correct  choices  on  the 
free  trials,  all  four  groups  learned  with  equal  facility. 

This  finding  can  be  handled  by  the  multiplicative  theory,  as 
Spence  (1956)  has  shown,  provided  one  makes  the  assumption 
that  the  forcing  procedure  which  produced  equal  runs  to  the  two 
sides  of  the  maze  resulted  in  equal  habit  strengths  to  approach  the 
rewarding  and  nonrewarding  arms.  This  assumption,  it  should  be 
noted,  is  not  one  that  Hull  would  have  made,  since  he  believed 
that  habit  strength  is  built  up  only  on  reinforced  trials.  Rather 
it  is  the  kind  of  assumption  made  by  those  who  hold  that  mere 
contiguity  of  stimulus  and  response  is  sufficient  to  produce  learn- 
ing (e.g.,  Guthrie,  1935).  On  the  supposition  that  the  habit 
strengths  are  equal,  the  multiplicative  theory  would  predict  no 
change  in  the  relative  frequency  of  correct  and  incorrect  responses 
as  a  function  of  differences  in  D,  since  the  two  E  values  obtained 


106  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

by  combining  D  with  the  two  Hs  would  be  identical  regardless 
of  strength  of  D.  This  was  the  result,  as  we  have  seen,  of  Teel's 
investigation.  To  explain  the  fact  that  animals  do  learn  to  perform 
correctly  under  these  experimental  conditions,  resort  must  be 
made  to  other  factors,  e.g.,  anticipatory  goal  reactions,  which  are 
unequal  for  the  two  sides  of  the  maze  (cf.  Spence,  1956). 

An  additional  and  quite  important  implication  of  the  multipli- 
cative theory  is  that  performance  will  be  degraded  by  an  increase 
in  drive  whenever  the  reactive  tendencies  corresponding  to  incor- 
rect responses  are  stronger  than  those  corresponding  to  correct 
reactions.  In  Ramond's  experiment,  for  instance,  if  the  more 
frequently  touched  bar  were  actually  the  wrong  one  from  the 
experimenter's  point  of  view,  intensification  of  D  would  lead  to  an 
increase  in  errors  and  hence  to  a  decline  in  proficiency.  Moreover, 
lowering  D  should  tend  to  make  performance  better,  a  prediction 
that  is  apparently  unique  to  the  multiplicative-drive  conception. 

In  this  context  it  should  be  noted  that  the  theory  cannot,  in  its 
"pure"  form,  explain  a  drop  in  performance  following  a  supposed 
increase  in  drive  if  there  is  reason  to  regard  the  correct  habit  as 
stronger  than  the  wrong  one.  When  such  results  are  obtained, 
appeal  is  customarily  made  to  the  presence  of  competing  ten- 
dencies, a  solution  that  is  essentially  associative  in  nature.  This  is 
legitimate,  of  course,  provided  independent  evidence  can  be 
presented  to  indicate  that  the  motivational  variable  which  led 
to  an  increase  in  D  also  led  to  an  increase  in  the  strengths  of 
interfering  habits  or  to  an  increase  in  the  intensity  of  stimuli 
associated  with  such  habits. 

In  summary,  a  motivational  theory  such  as  Hull's  explains 
certain  relatively  simple  behavioral  phenomena  by  introducing 
an  explicit  construct  of  drive  (D).  This  factor  is  assumed  to  com- 
bine in  a  multiplicative  fashion  with  habitual  or  instinctive  reac- 
tive tendencies  (Hs  or  Us)  to  yield  the  excitatory  potentials  (Es) 
of  which  behavior  is  said  to  be  a  more  or  less  direct  function. 
When  a  specific  overt  reaction  occurs  as  a  consequence  of  an 
operation  such  as  food  deprivation  and  does  not  occur  following 
satiation,  the  multiplicative  theory  holds  that  D  has  been  raised 
by  deprivation  and  the  value  of  the  corresponding  E  has  been 
elevated  above  a  threshold.  Since  D  itself  is  not  regarded  as  a 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE   INTERPRETATIONS  107 

director  of  behavior  but  only  as  a  broadly  acting  energizing  process, 
the  occurrence  of  one  response  rather  than  another  is  explained 
as  being  due  primarily  to  differences  in  the  strengths  of  simul- 
taneously present  reactive  tendencies.  When  two  or  more  such 
tendencies  are  present,  an  improvement  in  performance  following 
an  increase  in  deprivation  is  accounted  for  by  the  assumption  that, 
as  D  is  increased,  the  absolute  difference  between  the  strengths 
of  the  stronger  correct  E  and  the  weaker  competing  E  is  increased. 
But  if  the  wrong  habit  is  dominant  prior  to  the  increase  in  drive, 
then  raising  the  level  of  D  should  lead  to  poorer  performance. 
When  the  correct  tendency  is  believed  to  be  dominant  initially, 
but  increased  D  is  followed  by  a  decline  in  performance,  it  must 
be  assumed  that  other,  incorrect  habits  have  displaced  the  correct 
ones  at  the  top  of  the  hierarchy  of  habits. 

Other  Motivational  Theories 

Hull's  theory  has  served  as  the  focal  point  for  our  discussion 
of  motivational  interpretations  because  it  is  perhaps  more  widely 
known  than  others  and  has  been  carried  to  a  relatively  high  level 
of  systematic  refinement.  Numerous  other  theories,  however, 
might  also  qualify  as  motivational  interpretations,  and  although 
we  cannot  take  time  to  show  how  each  might  be  applied  to  experi- 
mental data,  a  brief  mention  of  several  is  appropriate  at  this  point. 

In  its  principal  elements,  Spence's  (1948,  1956)  theory  parallels 
Hull's  since  the  construct  of  drive  (D)  is  retained  along  with 
the  assumption  that  it  multiplies  associative  tendencies.  Spence 
holds  that  drive  is  a  direct  consequence  of  deprivation,  but  that 
variables  such  as  unconditioned  stimuli  (for  instance,  air  puffs 
in  eyelid-conditioning  experiments)  and  electric  shocks  affect 
drive  indirectly  via  the  elicitaiion  of  an  emotional  response.  Since 
drive  strength  is  taken  as  proportional  to  the  vigor  of  this  response, 
such  descriptively  different  factors  as  individual  differences  in 
emotional  reactivity  to  stress,  the  number  of  prior  exposures  to 
aversive  stimuli,  and  stimulus  intensity  can  all  affect  drive  and 
hence  performance  (Spence,  1958). 

Spence's  interpretation  also  departs  somewhat  from  Hull's  in 
placing  more   emphasis   upon   a   second  motivational   construct 


108  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

termed  incentive  motivation  (K).  As  a  behavior  determinant,  K 
is  assumed  to  combine  with  D  in  an  additive  manner,  and  Hke  D, 
therefore,  it  multiphes  reactive  tendencies.  The  variables  determin- 
ing K,  however,  are  different  from  those  upon  which  D  depends. 
Specifically,  K  is  a  function  of  magnitude  of  reward,  of  the  number 
of  times  the  reward  has  been  experienced,  its  palatability,  the 
length  of  the  chain  of  responses,  and  perhaps  also  of  the  time 
between  the  initiation  of  the  response  and  the  receipt  of  the 
incentive.  As  to  its  underlying  mechanism,  K  is  the  consequent 
of  the  occurrence  of  a  classically  conditioned  partial  consum- 
matory  goal  response  (r^).  After  an  animal  has  been  repeatedly 
fed  in  a  given  situation,  it  will  tend  to  make  anticipatory  chewing 
and  salivating  responses  prior  to  obtaining  food.  It  is  these 
responses  (r^s)  in  anticipation  of  reward  that  provide  the  mo- 
tivational increment  described  as  K.  Because  these  responses  are 
largely  learned,  they  qualify  as  secondary  sources  of  drive  and 
will  be  discussed  in  greater  detail  in  Chapter  5. 

Other  writers  who  have  followed  Hull  in  their  treatments  of 
motivation  (e.g..  Brown,  1953cz;  Farber,  1954ci;  Taylor,  1956^:; 
Amsel,  1958)  are  readily  identified  as  motivational  theorists,  but  it 
is  more  difficult  to  categorize  those  who  fall  outside  the  Hullian 
tradition.  Within  Tolman's  (1932)  early  system,  for  example, 
demands  (sometimes  identified  with  purposes)  tend  to  be  equated 
to  drives  or  motivations  and  to  occupy  the  status  of  intervening 
variables.  But  demands,  or  at  least  drives,  though  they  are  initiated 
by  physiological  conditions,  consist  in  part  of  a  sign-gestalt  readi- 
ness (a  sort  of  perceptual-idea tional  process)  which  at  other  times 
is  said  by  Tolman  to  be  a  constituent  of  cognitions.  Thus  Tolman 
is  a  motivational  theorist  in  postulating  intervening  variables 
named  drives  or  demands^  but  the  behavior-determining  properties 
of  these  variables  are  neither  clearly  specified  nor  carefully  differ- 
entiated from  those  of  cognitions.  In  certain  of  his  latest  formula- 
tions, Tolman  (1951,  1952)  seems  to  have  moved  even  closer  to 
a  concept  of  a  general,  nondirective  drive,  since  he  introduces  a 
libido  need  that  has  no  specific  goals  of  its  own  but  is  capable  of 
controlling  the  energy  that  is  available  for  the  satisfaction  of 
other  specific  needs. 

Duffy  (1934,  1951,  1957)   has  insisted  for  many  years  that  a 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  109 

clear  distinction  should  be  made  between  the  factors  that  deter- 
mine the  direction^  behavior  will  take  and  those  that  govern  its 
intensity.  Her  use  of  such  terms  as  "arousal,"  "activation/'  and 
"energy  mobilization,"  in  reference  to  the  dimension  of  behavior 
intensity  is  clearly  congruent  with  a  concept  of  a  nonspecific 
motivating  agency  such  as  Hull's  D.  Moreover,  she  has  also  main- 
tained that  the  concept  of  activation  aids  in  erasing  an  unwar- 
ranted distinction  between  "drives"  and  "emotions,"  a  view  that 
can  readily  be  related  to  theories  of  fear  as  a  learned  source  of 
drive  (Miller,  1951)  and  to  the  view  that  diverse  environmental 
variables  arouse  drive  through  a  mediating  emotional  response 
(Spence,  1958).  Malmo  (1957,  1958)  has  taken  a  position  much 
like  Duffy's,  though  he  has  tended,  where  she  has  not,  to  identify 
arousal  level  with  specific  physiological  variables. 

Among  physiologically  oriented  psychologists,  Morgan  (1943, 
1957)  might  be  described  as  having  espoused  a  motivational  inter- 
pretation because  of  his  concept  of  the  central  motive  state 
(c.m.s.),  which  he  defines  as  the  neural  integrative  activity  under- 
lying motivated  behavior.  On  the  antecedent  side,  the  c.m.s.  is 
aroused  by  receptor-mediated  stimuli  and  by  chemical  hormonal 
conditions.  The  latter  are  believed  to  affect  the  c.m.s.  by  direct 
stimulation  of  certain  brain  centers  or  in  such  indirect  ways  as  by 
the  excitation  of  internal  receptors.  Regarding  its  functional  prop- 
erties, the  long-perseverating  c.m.s.  appears  to  serve  in  part  as  a 
nonspecific  energizer,  since  it  leads  to  general  activity.  It  also  is 
capable,  however,  of  "emitting"  particular  responses  even  in  the 
absence  of  specific  stimuli,  and  can  sensitize  the  organism  to 
respond  selectively  to  certain  stimuli  rather  than  to  others.  Morgan 
has  listed  four  ways  in  which  the  c.m.s.  might  be  reduced  or 
negated:  (1)  by  removal  of  the  initiating  humoral  or  stimulus 
events;  (2)  by  the  release  of  other  "humoral  messengers"  having 
the  capacity  to  reduce  the  c.m.s.  directly;  (3)  by  the  excitation 
of  sensory  receptors;  and  (4)  by  the  performance  of  certain  acts 
generated  by  the  c.m.s.  As  we  have  already  noted  in  Chapter  3, 
Morgan  is  among  those  who  hold  that  drive  (c.m.s.?)  may  be 
controlled  by  sensory  stimulation.  Items  (2)  and  (3)  and  perhaps 
(4)  of  the  above  list  clearly  reflect  this  view.  Morgan  has  not, 
however,  presented  a  formalized  treatment  of  the  c.m.s.  or  applied 


no  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

it  to  experiments  in  which  motivational  variables  have  been  ex- 
pressly manipulated. 

Stellar  (1954)  has  accepted  Morgan's  c.m.s.  as  the  central 
nervous  mechanism  underlying  drive  and  has  suggested  that  it  be 
assigned  a  definite  physiological  locus  in  the  hypothalamus.  In 
broad  terms,  motivated  behavior  thus  becomes  dependent  upon 
the  level  of  activity  in  "certain  excitatory  centers  of  the  hypo- 
thalamus." 

Lindsley  (1951,  1957)  and  Hebb  (1955),  both  of  whom  have 
been  struck  by  the  nonspecific  activating  effects  of  excitation  in 
the  ascending  reticular  system  of  the  brain,  might  also  be  tenta- 
tively listed  among  the  motivational  theorists.  Hebb,  in  particular, 
has  identified  the  arousal  function  of  the  reticular  formation  with 
a  general  drive  state  and  has  urged  that  the  energizing  function 
be  distinguished  from  the  "S-R  or  cognitive  functions  that  are 
energized."  Neither  of  these  writers,  however,  has  presented  us 
with  a  formal  system  in  which  the  precise  role  of  the  arousal 
mechanism  has  been  delineated.  A  brief  resume  of  physiological 
findings  bearing  on  the  concept  of  a  nonspecific  drive,  as  cited  by 
these  and  other  writers,  will  be  found  below  in  Chapter  9. 

Finally  it  should  be  noted  that  concepts  such  as  Freud's  (1905) 
libido,  McDougall's  (1917)  instincts,  and  Woodworth's  (1918) 
drive  suggest  that  these  authors  might  be  classified  as  early  advo- 
cates of  motivational  interpretations.  By  certain  standards,  of 
course,  these  formulations  may  seem  relatively  unsystematic  but 
clear  anticipations  of  many  of  our  present-day  views  can  be  dis- 
covered therein. 

Associative  Interpretations  of  the  Role 
of  Motivational  Variables 

Although  motivational  theories  clearly  have  merit,  there  are 
other  reasonable  interpretations  of  the  same  phenomena  which, 
because  they  make  no  reference  to  a  construct  such  as  D,  may  be 
described  as  nonmotivational  or,  more  specifically,  as  associative. 
The  ideas  basic  to  any  associative  view  are  well  known  to  students 
of  motivation,  and  suggestive  allusions  to  them  may  be  found  in 
various  sources.  Fundamentally,  an  associative  view  would  hold 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  1 1 1 

that  the  manipulation  of  a  motivational  variable  leads  to  changes 
in  the  stimulus  conditions  effective  at  the  time  performance  is 
measured.  The  altered  stimuli,  in  turn,  would  affect  behavior 
through  changes  in  the  number,  relative  strengths,  or  kinds  of 
associations  between  those  stimuli  and  overt  reactions.  To  the 
author's  knowledge,  however,  the  specific  steps  involved  in  the 
development  and  application  of  associative  interpretations  have 
rarely  been  presented  previously.  The  following  discussion  repre- 
sents the  writer's  preliminary  attempt  to  formulate  and  evaluate 
several  versions  of  an  associative  theor)^ 

An  examination  of  existing  hypotheses  as  to  factors  responsible 
for  variations  in  associative  strengths  suggests  that  three  relatively 
distinct  versions  of  an  associative  theory  might  be  developed.  The 
basis  of  the  first  is  that  motivational  variables  alter  behavior  be- 
cause they  lead  to  the  addition  or  removal  of  critical  stimulus 
elements  and  hence  to  the  modification  of  existing  habit  strengths. 
In  the  second,  motivational  variables  are  assumed  to  operate  by 
changing  the  quality  or  intensity  of  critical  stimuli.  This,  in  turn, 
produces  variations  in  associative  strengths  in  accordance  with 
the  specific  hypothesis  of  habit-strength  generalization.  In  the 
third  version,  central  prominence  is  given  to  the  likelihood  that 
new  habits,  capable  of  either  facilitating  or  interfering  with  the 
old  are  brought  into  effective  action  by  the  manipulation  of  motiva- 
tional variables. 

Attributing  the  Effects  of  Motivational  Variables  to  the  Addi- 
tion or  Subtraction  of  Critical  Stimulus  Elements.  To  illustrate 
this  first  form  of  an  associative  interpretation,  let  us  refer  again  to 
the  Koch  and  Daniel  (1945)  experiment  wherein  animals  were 
trained  to  press  a  bar  under  long-term  deprivation  and  were  then 
tested  in  the  same  situation  under  short-term  deprivation  (satia- 
tion). In  this  case,  the  empirical  phenomenon  to  be  explained  is 
the  decrement  in  performance  produced  by  satiation. 

According  to  the  view  under  consideration,  the  original  training 
may  be  thought  of  as  producing  associations  between  the  bar- 
pressing  responses  and  a  constellation  of  both  internal  and  external 
stimuli.  This  assumption  is  represented  in  the  upper  part  of  Fig. 
4:1,  where  stimuli  Si,  S2,  S3,  and  S4  represent  internal  cues,  Se 
represents  all  the  external  cues  of  the  testing  situation,  and  H 


112 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


indicates  the  associative  connection  of  all  cues  to  the  bar-pressing 
response.  When  tests  are  conducted  under  conditions  of  complete 
or  partial  satiation,  some,  though  probably  not  all,  of  the  internal 
stimuli  originally  conditioned  to  the  reaction  would  presumably 
be  eliminated.  This  possibility  is  expressed  in  the  lower  half  of 
Fig.  4:1,  where  only  Si  and  S2  of  the  original  set  are  indicated  as 
present.  Now  if  we  make  the  explicit  assumption  that  the  strength 
of  an  existing  habit  is  directly  related  to  the  number  of  elements 
that  are  present  from  the  originally  conditioned  stimulus  aggregate, 
then  the  deletion  of  S3  and  Si  should  weaken  the  bar-pressing 
habit,  and  level  of  performance  should  decline.  In  effect  then, 
this  view  holds  that  behavior  occurs  when  stimuli  appropriate  for 
its  elicitation  are  present  and  does  not  occur  when  they  are 
absent.  Thus,  the  facilitative  effect  of  long-term  deprivation  as 
contrasted  with  the  effect  of  satiation  is  explained  without  refer- 
ence to  the  energizing  or  multiplying  effects  of  a  general  D. 

This  version  of  an  associative  theory  cannot,  however,  easily 
explain  the  facilitation  of  performance  that  might  occur  when 
training  has  been  carried  out  under  short-term  deprivation  and 
tests  are  then  made  under  long-term  deprivation.  Loess  (1952), 
for  example,  found  that  speed  of  response  in  a  two-bar  choice 
box  increased  when  time  of  deprivation  was  shifted  from  a  training 


Internal  cues  due 
to  long-term  - 
deprivation 

External  cues  — 


Training  conditions 


Sj,  S2,  S3,  S^ 


+ 


-H- 


-R 


bar  pressing 


Internal  cues  due 
to  short-term 
deprivation 

External  cues 


Testing  conditions 


bar  pressing 


Fig.  4:1.  Elements  of  an  associative  interpretation  of  a  decline  in  per- 
formance following  a  shift  from  a  long-term  to  a  short-term  deprivation 
schedule.  The  loss  of  stimuli  S3  and  Si  occasioned  by  the  shift  in  schedule 
is  assumed  to  weaken  the  original  associative  tendency.  The  stronger  habit 
is  indicated  by  H,  the  weaker  by  h. 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS 


113 


value  of  3  hours  to  a  testing  level  of  32  hours.  The  hypothetical 
factors  involved  in  this  series  of  events  are  shown  in  Fig.  4:2.  The 
upper  portion  of  this  figure  represents  the  assumption  that  the 
response  of  approaching  and  touching  a  bar  has  become  strongly 
attached  (H)  to  the  combination  of  Si,  S2,  and  Se-  If  at  this  point 
the  deprivation  period  is  lengthened,  stimuli  S3  and  S4  should  be 
added  to  the  complex  (lower  part  of  Fig.  4:2).  But  if  these  new 
cues  have  never  been  previously  associated  with  the  response  of 
approaching  and  touching  the  bar,  their  addition  to  the  stimulus 
complex  cannot  explain  the  observed  improvement  in  performance. 
In  fact,  as  deprivation  increases,  the  internal  stimulus  complex 
should  become  progressively  more  unlike  that  present  during 
original  training;  and  if  we  accept  current  views  as  to  the  role  of 
stimulus  similarity  in  determining  associative  strength,  we  must 
conclude  that  the  tendency  to  make  the  original  reaction  should 
become  weaker,  not  stronger,  as  the  difference  between  the  original 
and  subsequent  stimulus  complexes  is  increased.  This  possibility 
is  indicated  in  the  bottom  portion  of  Fig.  4:2  by  the  lower-case  h. 
It  thus  appears  that,  granting  the  above  assumptions,  we  must 
conclude   that   this   particular   associative   interpretation   cannot 


Internal  cues  due 
to  short-term  ■ 
deprivation 


External  cues 


Training  conditions 


■*■  Sj,  S2 

+ 
— ^  S^ 


>-H — R 


approach  and  touch  bar 


Internal  cues  due 
to  long-term  - 
deprivation 


External  cues  ■ 


Testing  conditions 


•Sj,  Sj,  S3,  S4 
+ 

^Sr, 


>-h—R 


approach  and  touch  bar 


Fig.  4:2.  The  application  of  an  associative  hypothesis  to  behavior  observed 
when  original  training  is  carried  out  under  a  short-term  deprivation  schedule 
and  subsequent  tests  under  long-term  deprivation.  From  these  assumptions 
alone  it  would  be  predicted  that,  as  deprivation  is  enhanced,  the  addition  of 
S3  and  Si  to  the  stimulus  complex  would  lead  to  a  weakening  of  the  association 
and  hence  to  poorer  rather  than  better  performance. 


114  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

readily  deal  with  the  case  where  original  training  has  been  admin- 
istered under  short-term  deprivation  and  improved  performance  is 
then  observed  under  long-term  deprivation. 

Special-purpose  modifications  of  the  theory  might  be  introduced, 
of  course,  so  as  to  make  it  work  more  convincingly.  Thus,  one 
might  maintain  that  Si  and  S2  become  more  intense  with  extended 
deprivation  and  are  therefore  more  likely  to  exceed  a  threshold, 
or  that  S3  and  Si  have  the  power,  as  the  result  of  previous  learning, 
to  facilitate  rather  than  interfere  with  the  approaching  response. 
Modifications  such  as  these,  however,  raise  additional  problems, 
which  when  carefully  analyzed  may  convert  the  theory  into  one  or 
the  other  of  the  two  forms  to  be  described  below. 

Our  first  associative  hypothesis  can,  however,  deal  adequately 
with  decrements  in  performance  attending  a  shift  from  one  need 
condition  to  another.  Here  it  would  be  presumed  that  a  change 
from  thirst  to  hunger,  for  example,  results  in  the  partial  elimina- 
tion of  the  thirst  stimuli  associated  with  the  response  during 
training.  The  fact  that  the  response  occurs  at  all  under  hunger 
would  be  explained  on  the  grounds  that  some  of  the  original  in- 
ternal (thirst)  stimuli  were  still  present  at  the  time  of  the  tests 
under  hunger.  The  theory  is  also  satisfactory  as  an  interpretation 
of  the  effects  of  deprivation  upon  the  acquisition  of  simple  instru- 
mental responses  (cf.  Fredenburg's  data.  Figs.  3:6  and  3:7).  One 
would  probably  assume,  in  this  case,  that  many  more  internal  cues 
are  present  under  22  than  under  4  hours  of  deprivation  and  that 
running  can  become  more  readily  conditioned  to  a  CS  complex 
consisting  of  many  elements  than  to  one  with  few  components. 
Thus  performance  differences  would  be  explained  in  terms  of 
differences  in  habit  strengths. 

In  attempting  to  extend  this  type  of  associative  theory  to  choice 
situations  in  which  one  or  more  associative  tendencies  are  simul- 
taneously present  and  in  which  the  deprivation  conditions  are 
altered,  reference  would  again  be  made  to  the  addition  or  deletion 
of  stimulus  elements.  If  a  rat  has  learned  to  turn  right  in  a  T  maze 
when  strong  need-produced  stimuli  are  present,  its  performance 
would  be  expected  to  suffer  if  the  need  were  reduced  through 
satiation.  On  the  other  hand,  if  the  reaction  has  been  conditioned 
to  weak  need  stimuli,  there  is  no  clear-cut  prediction  from  the 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  115 

theory  that  performance  will  improve  when  the  need  is  increased. 
As  in  the  case  of  the  single  reaction  considered  above,  it  is  difEcult 
to  see  how  performance  could  be  improved  by  suddenly  adding 
irrelevant  internal  cues  to  the  conditioned-stimulus  aggregate. 

Motivational-variable  Effects  Ascribed  to  Changes  in  the 
Strength  of  Habits  in  Accordance  with  the  Principle  of  Stimulus 
Generalization.  In  order  to  explain  this  second  type  of  associative 
interpretation,  in  which  changes  in  motivational  variables  are 
assumed  to  affect  the  intensity  or  quality  of  stimuli  rather  than 
their  mere  numerosity,  we  must  digress  briefly  to  consider  both 
the  empirical  phenomenon  of  stimulus  generalization  and  the 
hypothesis  of  generalized  habit  strength. 

The  empirical  phenomenon  of  stimulus  generalization  is  nicely 
illustrated  in  an  experiment  by  Grice  and  Saltz  (1950).  In  this 
study  rats  were  trained  to  traverse  a  short,  straight  black  alley 
to  obtain  food  from  a  small  compartment  in  the  center  of  a 
white  disk  located  on  the  end  wall  of  the  alley.  Seventy-five  animals 
were  trained  to  approach  when  the  disk  had  an  area  of  79  square 
centimeters.  Five  subgroups  of  15  animals  each  were  then  tested 
on  disk  sizes  of  79,  63,  50,  32,  and  20  square  centimeters,  respec- 
tively. These  tests  consisted  of  25  opportunities  to  approach  a 
disk,  but  no  food  was  given  on  any  trial.  The  strength  of  the 
approach  tendency  was  measured  by  counting  the  number  of 
times,  during  25  trials,  that  an  animal  approached  and  touched 
the  disk  within  60  seconds.  The  results  of  these  tests,  reproduced 
in  Fig.  4:3  (dashed-line  curve),  indicate  that  the  animals  approach 
disks  that  have  never  been  used  in  training,  but  that  as  the  size 
of  the  disk  decreases,  the  tendency  to  approach  becomes  progres- 
sively weaker.  The  phrase  empirical  stimulus  generalization  denotes 
the  fact  that  responses  do  occur  to  stimuli  even  in  the  absence  of 
specific  training  with  those  stimuli.  The  phrase  gradient  of  gen- 
eralization refers  to  an  observed  decrease  in  response  strength  as 
the  test  stimulus  differs  progressively  from  the  one  used  in  train- 
ing. 

An  additional  60  animals  were  trained  by  Grice  and  Saltz  to 
approach  and  secure  food  from  the  stimulus  with  the  smallest 
area  (20  square  centimeters).  Four  equal  subgroups  were  then 
given  extinction  tests  with  disks  having  areas  of  20,  32,  50,  and  79 


116 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


i.H 

;? 

/ 

/ 

12 

/ 

/ 

10 

\ 

/ 
/ 
/ 

• 

\-<^ 

8 

• 

6 

4 

- 

1                .       1 

<        1 

20 


32  50 

Area  of  test  stimulus  in  sq  cm 


63 


79 


Fig.  4:3.  The  results  of  an  experimental  study  of  the  generalization  of  in- 
strumental responses  to  stimuli  varying  in  the  dimension  of  size.  The  dashed- 
Hne  curve  shows  the  number  of  extinction  responses  made  by  animals  trained 
with  the  largest  stimulus  and  tested  on  the  others.  The  solid-line  curve  de- 
picts the  performance  of  rats  that  were  trained  on  the  20-cm  stimulus  and 
tested  on  that  and  on  larger  ones.  {From  Grice  and  Saltz,  19 SO.) 


square  centimeters.  Here  also,  stimuli  never  before  associated  with 
approaching  elicited  the  response,  and,  in  general,  the  more  deviant 
the  size  of  the  test  stimuli  the  less  resistant  the  response  to  extinc- 
tion. Data  obtained  from  these  animals  are  represented  by  the 
solid-line  curve  of  Fig.  4:3. 

This,  then,  is  the  empirical  phenomenon  of  stimulus  generaliza- 
tion: after  a  response  has  become  associated  with  one  stimulus, 
it  may  be  elicited,  though  often  with  a  decrement,  by  other  similar 
stimuli  in  the  absence  of  specific  training  with  those  stimuli. 

In  attempting  to  account  for  empirical  data  of  this  kind,  Hull 
(1943)  made  the  assumption  that  whenever  a  response  is  condi- 
tioned to  a  particular  stimulus,  associative  strengths  are  automat- 
ically built  up  to  (generalized  to)  other  similar  stimuli.  Moreover, 
the  greater  the  disparity  between  the  conditioned  and  test  stimuli 
the  weaker  the  generalized  habit  strength.  The  specific  details  of 
his  assumptions  are  shown  in  Fig.  4:4,  where  habit  strength  is 
indicated  on  the  ordinate  and  a  stimulus  dimension  on  the  ab- 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE   INTERPRETATIONS 


117 


scissa.  The  conditioned  stimulus  (CS)  is  shown  to  have  the 
greatest  habit  strength  and  the  generahzed  stimuh  (Ss  with  nu- 
merical subscripts)  are  shown  to  have  progressively  weaker  habit 
loadings  as  their  distance  from  CS  increases  in  either  direction 
along  the  base  line.  Hull  assumed  that  the  gradients  of  generalized 
habit  strength  will  always  have  the  general  form  shown  in  Fig.  4:4 
irrespective  of  the  particular  stimulus  dimension,  provided  the  test 
stimuli  have  been  located  at  subjectively  equal  distances  along 
the  abscissa.  It  is  important  to  note  that  these  curves  do  not 
represent  experimental  data  but  simply  Hull's  hypothesis  as  to  the 
way  in  which  the  strength  of  an  association  changes  with  variations 
in  the  stimulus.  It  is  an  assumption  advanced  to  explain  the  em- 
pirical phenomena  of  generalization.  This  assumption  and  the 
empirical  phenomena  must  be  kept  separate  in  one's  thinking  if 
confusion  is  to  be  avoided. 

Although  the  hypothetical  curves  of  generalized  habit  strength 
differ  considerably  from  the  empirical  curves  obtained  by  Grice 
and  Saltz,  the  latter  do  show  a  fairly  regular  decline  as  the  distance 
between  the  conditioned  and  the  test   (generalized)    stimuli  is 


'1         ^^  ^1 

Stimulus  dimension 

Fig.  4:4.  A  graphic  portrayal  of  Hull's  (1943)  hypothesis  of  generalized 
habit  strength.  CS  represents  the  stimulus  to  which  a  response  has  been  con- 
ditioned, and  the  habit  strength  at  that  point  is  assumed  to  be  maximal. 
The  stimuli  to  the  right  and  left  of  CS  are  assumed  to  be  located  at  psycho- 
logically equal  distances  along  the  dimension,  and  the  corresponding  values 
of  generahzed  habit  strength  are  shown  as  decreasing  with  increased  distance 
in  both  directions  from  CS. 


118  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

increased.  On  Hull's  hypothesis,  the  rats  in  the  Grice-Saltz  experi- 
ment approach  white  circles  of  sizes  other  than  that  used  in  train- 
ing because  habit  strength  generalizes  to  those  other  stimuli.  The 
fact  that  the  rats  show  less  resistance  to  extinction  as  the  test 
stimuli  depart  increasingly  from  the  one  used  in  training  is  at- 
tributed to  the  decline  of  habit  strength  with  distance  along  the 
stimulus  dimension. 

Bearing  in  mind  the  empirical  phenomenon  of  stimulus  gen- 
eralization and  the  hypothesis  of  generalized  habit  strength,  we 
may  now  return  to  the  associative  interpretation  to  which  we 
alluded  at  the  beginning  of  this  section. 

For  expository  purposes  we  shall  consider  an  experiment  by 
Deese  and  Carpenter  (1951)  in  which  two  groups  of  rats  were 
given  24  training  trials  in  running  down  a  short  straight  alley  for 
food.  At  the  time  of  this  training,  one  group  had  just  been  fed 
wet  mash  for  1  hour,  whereas  the  other  group  had  not  eaten  for 
22  hours.  At  the  end  of  this  training  period  the  drives  of  the  two 
groups  were  reversed  and  8  more  trials  were  administered.  Now 
according  to  the  associative  view  we  are  considering,  the  early 
training  should  produce  learned  connections  between  the  running 
response  and  a  stimulus  complex  consisting  of  environmental  cues 
plus  the  internal  cues  (Smfs).  Turning  first  to  the  group  trained 
under  22  hours  of  deprivation,  the  theory  predicts  that  when  the 
animals  are  shifted  to  near-satiation  conditions  their  speed  of 
running  should  decline,  since  the  internal  deprivation  cues,  if  still 
present,  should  be  much  weaker  and  the  generalized  habit  strength 
should  therefore  be  reduced.  To  make  this  clearer,  let  CS  in  Fig.  4:4 
represent  the  internal  stimuli  arising  in  conjunction  with  22  hours 
of  food  deprivation,  and  let  us  assume  that  the  running  response 
has  been  conditioned  to  these  cues  along  with  those  of  the  alley. 
The  stimuli  to  the  left  of  CS  would  then  represent  internal  cues 
corresponding  to  shorter  deprivation  periods.  Since  the  strength  of 
the  habit  declines  with  distance  on  the  stimulus  dimension  from 
CS,  the  strength  of  the  tendency  to  run  should  also  weaken  as 
time  since  eating  is  reduced.  The  results  of  the  Deese  and  Car- 
penter study  are  presented  in  Fig.  4:5,  where  it  may  be  seen  that 
the  performance  of  the  high-drive  group  (solid-line  curve)  did 
decline  when  deprivation  was  made  less  severe,  though  the  drop 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE   INTERPRETATIONS 


119 


is  not  extreme  and  performance  becomes  quite  variable.  This  find- 
ing is  thus  consistent  with  the  associative  hypothesis  under  exam- 
ination, but  it  also  supports  a  drive  theory  such  as  Hull's. 

An  associative  interpretation  involving  the  assumption  of  gen- 
eralized habit  strength  can  thus  explain  a  decrement  in  perform- 
ance following  a  shift  from  long-  to  short-term  deprivation.  It  is 
an  explanation  that  stresses  the  role  of  stimulus  variation  in  the 
determination  of  associative  strength.  In  this  instance,  however, 
the  stimulus  is  presumed  to  be  internal  rather  than  external,  as  in 
the  Grice-Saltz  experiment.  Unlike  the  preceding  associative  inter- 
pretation, this  one  does  not  appeal  to  changes  in  the  number  of 
associated  stimulus  elements.  Nor  does  it,  like  the  multiplicative- 
drive  theory,  require  the  postulation  of  a  general  drive  factor.  In 
Chapter  3  an  associative  interpretation  of  precisely  this  kind  was 
discussed  as  a  possible  alternative  to  the  multiplicative  theory  in 
connection  with  Horenstein's  experiment,  though  we  did  not,  at 
that  point,  introduce  the  concept  of  stimulus  generalization.  By 
its  very  nature,  incidentally,  this  associative  view  is  applicable 
only  to  studies  in  which  deprivation  is  shifted  from  one  level  to 


0.55 


qO.50 


0.45 


0.40 


0.35 


• •  High  drive-low  drive 

o o  Low  drive-high  drive 


."^^  k 


12        16         20        24    2     4     6    8 
Trials  (reinforcements) 


Fig.  4:5.  Starting-speed  scores  for  two  groups  of  rats  trained  under  long  and 
short  food-deprivation  schedules,  respectively,  for  24  trials  and  then  given 
8  more  trials  with  the  deprivation  durations  reversed.  {Adapted  from  Deese 
and  Carpenter,  1951.) 


120  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

another  or  to  those  in  which  one  need  is  substituted  for  another. 

From  the  relations  depicted  in  Fig.  4:4,  it  may  be  seen  that  our 
second  associative  formulation,  like  the  first,  cannot  easily  explain 
the  marked  improvement  in  performance  shown  by  the  Deese 
and  Carpenter  animals  that  were  trained  initially  under  near-satia- 
tion conditions  and  were  then  shifted  to  the  22-hour  deprivation 
regimen  (dashed-hne  curve  in  Fig.  4:5).  If  CS  in  Fig.  4:4  now 
represents  the  internal  cues  characteristic  of  near-satiation  at  the 
time  of  initial  training,  stimuli  to  the  right  of  CS  would  correspond 
to  cues  attending  deprivation  periods  of  greater  and  greater  dura- 
tion. As  these  stimuli  become  increasingly  different  from  CS  the 
corresponding  habit  strengths  decline,  and  performance  should 
become  poorer.  The  unelaborated  hypothesis  of  generalized  habit 
strength,  therefore,  leads  to  the  prediction  that  performance  will 
decline  regardless  of  whether  the  deprivation  period  is  increased 
or  decreased  from  that  used  in  original  training.  Deese  and  Car- 
penter, however,  found  that  performance  improved  immediately 
when  deprivation  duration  was  increased.  Other  experimenters 
have  also  observed  that  a  sudden  increase  in  deprivation  leads  to 
improved  performance  (e.g.,  Skinner,  1938;  Loess,  1952;  Hillman, 
Hunter,  and  Kimble,  1953;  Davis,  1957;  Barry,  1958;  and  Bass, 
1958),  though  the  magnitude  of  the  effect  varies  with  the  response 
being  measured  and  with  situational  variables. 

The  associative  hypothesis  could  be  modified  to  take  account 
of  the  Deese  and  Carpenter  findings  by  changing  the  basic  assump- 
tions concerning  the  form  of  the  generalization  gradients.  Specifi- 
cally, one  might  assume  that  when  the  stimulus  dimension  is  one 
of  intensity  rather  than  of  quality,  the  gradient  of  generalized 
habit  strength  actually  rises  progressively  from  the  point  of  condi- 
tioning {CS  in  Fig.  4:4)  to  other  points  at  the  right  of  the  dimen- 
sion. But  this  would  lead  to  the  conclusion  that  the  generalized 
habit  strength  for  an  intense  stimulus  is  greater  than  the  condi- 
tioned habit  strength  for  a  weaker  value  of  the  same  stimulus  even 
though  the  former  has  never  been  experimentally  associated  with 
the  response.  To  the  writer's  knowledge,  no  one  has  seriously 
championed  such  an  interpretation,  but  when  test  (generalized) 
stimuli  are  more  intense  than  the  conditioned  stimulus,  the 
empirical  generalization  gradients  tend  to  be  flatter  than  when 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  121 

the  test  stimuli  are  weaker  than  the  conditioned  stimulus  (cf. 
Miller  and  Greene,  1954).  A  consistent  associative  theorist  could 
not,  of  course,  assume  that  strong  stimuli  have  inherently  more 
driving  power  than  weak  ones,  since  this  would  constitute  a  moti- 
vational rather  than  an  associative  conception. 

Experiments  in  which  an  associative  tendency  is  established 
under  one  motivational  variable  and  performance  is  measured 
under  another  can  also  be  interpreted  in  terms  of  habit-strength 
generalization.  Here  the  underlying  supposition  is  that  the  internal 
stimuli  attending  the  substituted  variable  are  similar  to  those 
present  when  the  associative  tendency  was  first  established.  Thus 
it  might  be  supposed,  with  some  reason,  that  hunger,  thirst,  and 
nausea  all  involve  similar  visceral  stimuli.  From  the  postulate  of 
generalized  habit  strength  the  conclusion  is  reached  that  if  a 
response  has  been  learned  when  an  animal  is  thirsty,  the  same 
response  will  be  evoked,  but  with  a  decrement,  when  the  animal 
is  made  either  hungry  or  nauseated.  Note  once  more  that  this 
associative  explanation  of  the  effects  of  interchanging  motivational 
variables  does  not  rely  upon  the  intensifying  action  of  D  but  upon 
the  concept  of  habit-strength  variation  as  a  function  of  degree  of 
stimulus  similarity. 

Among  the  relatively  few  studies  involving  an  interchange  of 
motivational  variables,  those  by  Miller  (1948b)  are  of  special 
interest  here  because  his  interpretation  of  these  phenomena  is 
identical  with  the  habit-strength  generalization  hypothesis. 

In  Miller's  first  experiment  on  this  problem,  rats  were  taught 
when  thirsty  to  run  down  a  narrow  straight  alley  for  water  reward. 
They  were  then  divided  into  two  groups:  one  group  was  made 
hungry  but  was  satiated  with  water;  the  other  was  satiated  with 
both  food  and  water.  When  these  subjects  were  placed  in  the 
alley,  the  hungry  but  nonthirsty  animals  ran  significantly  faster 
and  actually  drank  more  water  at  the  goal  than  did  those  that 
were  neither  hungry  nor  thirsty.  Neither  group,  however,  ran  as 
fast  or  drank  as  much  as  they  had  when  thirsty. 

The  fact  that  the  running  and  drinking  responses  did  transfer 
from  a  water-deprivation-food-satiation  condition  to  a  food-depriva- 
tion-water-satiation condition,  though  with  some  decrement,  is 
explained  by  Miller  in  terms  of  generalization.  The  internal  cues 


122  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

present  during  original  learning  are  similar  to,  but  not  identical 
with,  those  present  at  the  time  of  the  tests  for  transfer.  Transfer 
should  occur,  therefore,  but  to  an  incomplete  degree.  These  same 
facts,  of  course,  are  perfectly  consistent  with  the  multiplicative- 
drive  hypothesis,  since  habits  acquired  under  thirst  should  also 
be  evoked  by  the  D  due  to  hunger.  As  a  matter  of  fact.  Miller's 
finding  that  hunger  seemed  to  facilitate  even  the  consummatory 
response  of  drinking,  which,  on  intuitive  grounds,  might  be  re- 
garded as  quite  specific  to  thirst,  fits  the  multiplicative  theory  very 
nicely.  It  is  a  finding  clearly  corroborative  of  the  notion  that  D 
can  catalyze  any  habit  into  action.  Nevertheless,  an  associative 
interpretation,  based  on  repeated  preexperimental  associations  be- 
tween hunger  stimuli  and  drinking,  would  also  be  defensible. 

In  Miller's  second  study,  hungry  rats  were  trained  on  an  elevated 
T  maze  to  turn  consistently  to  one  side  for  food.  After  their  learn- 
ing had  reached  a  high  degree  of  proficiency  they  were  thoroughly 
satiated  on  wet  mash  in  an  effort  to  eliminate  hunger  completely. 
They  were  then  placed  on  the  maze,  where  half  of  the  animals  in 
the  original  group  were  given  a  one-second  electric  shock  and  the 
others  not.  Since  the  shocked  animals  ran  faster  than  the  non- 
shocked  ones  and  made  significantly  fewer  errors  on  each  of  sev- 
eral successive  runs,  we  may  conclude  with  Miller  that  the  shock 
served  as  an  effective  substitute  for  the  absent  hunger.  Miller's 
associative  view  of  this  result  is  that  the  habit  learned  under 
hunger  generalized  to  pain.  The  internal  cues  characteristic  of 
these  two  states  would  seem  to  be  so  different,  however,  as  to 
make  a  generalization  interpretation  difficult.  To  overcome  this 
objection,  Miller  suggests  that  the  generalization  might  be  ".  .  . 
based  indirectly  on  stimuli  produced  by  similar  states  of  muscular 
tension  elicited  by  both  drives,  rather  than  upon  common  elements 
directly  present  in  the  drives  themselves"  (p.  165).  That  is,  the 
animals  made  fewer  errors  when  shocked  because  their  vigorous 
running  produced  proprioceptive  stimuli  much  like  those  present 
when  they  were  hungry. 

As  a  concomitant  to  the  general  problem  we  are  considering, 
we  should  also  note  that  the  presence  of  a  need  state  such  as  thirst 
can  apparently  increase  the  resistance  to  extinction  of  a  response 
learned  under  hunger.  Both  Webb  (1949)  and  Brandauer  (1953) 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE   INTERPRETATIONS  123 

have  shown  that  after  hungry  rats  have  been  taught  to  perform 
a  simple  instrumental  response  for  food  they  will  continue  to 
perform  the  response  longer  when  they  are  thirsty  and  not  hungry 
than  when  neither  thirsty  nor  hungry.  Moreover,  the  more  severe 
the  thirst,  the  greater  the  resistance  to  extinction.  To  explain  these 
findings  an  associative  theorist  would  probably  assume  that  as 
thirst  becomes  more  intense  thirst  stimuli  become  increasingly 
similar  to  hunger  stimuli.  This  assumption  is  defensible  if  one 
considers  only  the  dimension  of  stimulus  intensity,  but  one  might 
also  insist  that  as  thirst  grows  stronger  its  characteristic  internal 
cues  become  qualitatively  more  distinctive  and  hence  less  similar 
to  those  of  extreme  hunger.  Grice  and  Davis  (1957),  who  were 
unable  to  confirm  the  findings  of  Webb  and  of  Brandauer,  have 
suggested  that  when  such  results  are  obtained  they  may  be  due 
to  an  increase  in  hunger  induced  by  water  deprivation. 

Miller's  theoretical  treatment  of  the  results  of  his  T  maze  studies 
was  restricted  to  the  use  of  the  stimulus-generalization  hypothesis 
in  explaining  the  degree  to  which  one  motivational  variable  could 
be  substituted  for  another.  The  same  principles,  however,  may  be 
extended  to  the  interpretation  of  behavior  in  complex  choice  situa- 
tions following  alterations  in  the  strength  of  a  single  motivational 
variable.  Without  going  into  the  matter  at  great  length,  let  us  see 
what  might  be  predicted  in  the  case  in  which  a  rat  has  learned 
to  turn  left  in  a  T  maze  under  a  moderate  period  of  deprivation 
and  is  then  retested  in  the  maze  under  either  a  long-  or  short-term 
deprivation  schedule. 

The  basic  assumptions  regarding  the  habits  acquired  in  the 
maze  and  the  critical  stimuli  are  shown  in  Fig.  4:6.  If  the  left-turn- 
ing reaction  has  been  evoked  more  often  than  the  right-turning 
one,  the  habit  strength  of  the  former  (H)  will  be  stronger  than 
that  of  the  latter  {h).  Both  reactions,  however,  are  conditioned 
to  the  same  stimulus  compound  consisting  of  internal  stimuli  of 
moderate  intensity  (Sm)  plus  stimuli  at  the  choice  point  of  the 
maze  {Sep). 

Imagine  now  that  at  the  completion  of  the  initial  training  the 
deprivation  period  is  lengthened  (prior  to  a  retest  in  the  maze). 
This  should  result  in  an  increase  in  the  intensity  of  the  internal 
stimuli.  Conversely,  if  the  deprivation  period  is  shortened  (partial 


124  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Fig.  4:6.  Stimulus  com- 
ponents and  relative  habit 
strengths  presumed  to  be 
characteristic  of  a  situa- 
tion in  which  an  animal 
has   learned   to   turn   left       g 

in  a  T  maze  for  food  un-        -f-   jj >./j 

der  moderate  deprivation       S^p 
conditions.   Sm    =   mod- 
erately    intense     internal 
stimuli;  Sep  =  stimuli  at 
choice  point  of  maze;  H       c 

and  h  =z  strong  and  weak       -|-  h  — ^  jj 

habits,  respectively.  S^p 


right 


satiation),  the  internal  cues  should  become  weaker.  Presumably 
these  cues  resemble  one  another  in  varying  degrees,  and  they  can 
be  arranged,  therefore,  on  a  continuum  from  weak  {Sjw)  through 
medium  {Sm)  to  strong  (S/s).  Such  a  continuum  is  represented 
graphically  as  the  stimulus  dimension  in  Fig.  4:7.  According  to 
Hull's  postulates,  the  gradient  of  generalization  for  a  strong  habit 
would  correspond  approximately  to  the  upper  curve  in  the  figure 
and  the  gradient  for  a  weak  habit  to  the  lower  curve.  Since  the 
moderately  strong  stimuli  were  present  at  the  time  of  training, 
these  cues  would  be  more  strongly  associated  with  both  left  turn- 
ing and  right  turning  than  would  other  intensities  of  internal 
stimuli.  From  the  hypothetical  relations  of  Fig.  4:7,  it  follows 
that  the  absolute  strengths  of  both  the  right-  and  left-turning 
habits  should  decrease  regardless  of  whether  the  deprivation  period 
is  increased  (to  produce  Sis),  or  decreased  (to  produce  Siw).  More- 
over, and  this  is  the  critical  part  of  the  analysis,  a  shift  in  the 
length  of  the  deprivation  period  in  either  direction  from  its  training 
value  produces  a  decrease  in  the  absolute  difference  between  the 
right  and  left  habits.  In  the  figure  it  will  be  seen  that  the  difference 
between  H  and  h  is  larger  than  the  difference  between  H'  and  h' 
or  H"  and  h".  If  the  proportion  of  correct  turns  (to  the  left)  is 
determined  by  the  absolute  difference  in  the  strengths  of  the  two 
habits,  it  follows  that  the  efficiency  of  a  rat's  performance 
in  the  maze  should  decline  as  the  intensities  of  the  internal  cues 
are  shifted  either  up  or  down  from  an  intermediate  [training) 
point.  Although  no  one  has  apparently  performed  an  experiment 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE   INTERPRETATIONS 


125 


in  exactly  this  way,  Dinsmoor's  (1952)  study  of  discrimination 
learning  (see  Chapter  3)  is  most  nearly  relevant.  He  found,  it 
may  be  remembered,  that  his  animals  did  indeed  perform  more 
poorly  as  deprivation  level — actually,  he  used  per  cent  body-weight 
deficit,  not  hours  of  deprivation — was  decreased  from  the  value 
used  during  original  discrimination  training.  This  fits  the  general- 
ized habit-strength  view  quite  well,  though  it  is  also  consistent 
with  the  multiplicative  theory.  But  the  performance  of  Dinsmoor's 
subjects  improved  when  hunger  was  made  more  severe  than  at  the 
time  of  initial  training.  This  result  does  not  follow  from  an  un- 
modified generalization  theory  such  as  the  one  of  Fig.  4:7,  which 
predicts  a  decline  in  proficiency  with  lengthened  deprivation.  The 
multiplicative-drive  hypothesis,  however,  does  predict  improve- 
ment. Apparently  the  generalized-habit  view  runs  into  the  same 
difficulties  in  attempting  to  account  for  behavior  in  a  situation 
involving  two  habits  as  it  does  in  dealing  with  only  one.  Impair- 
ment in  performance  with  reduced  deprivation  can  easily  be  en- 
compassed, but  improvements  in  performance  following  increased 
deprivation  cannot.  The  theory  could  doubtless  be  improved  by 


Fig.  4:7.  Hypothetical  generalization  curves  for  a  relatively  strong  habit  (H) 
and  a  weaker  competing  one  (h).  Weak,  moderate,  and  strong  internal 
stimuli  are  plotted  along  the  abscissa  from  left  to  right.  It  is  assumed  that 
both  reactions  have  been  conditioned  to  the  moderately  strong  internal 
stimuli  at  the  center  of  the  dimension.  With  changes  in  the  stimuh  in  either 
direction,  the  strength  of  each  habit  decreases  as  well  as  the  absolute  differ- 
ence between  them. 


126 


THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 


the  introduction  of  special  assumptions,  but  considerable  addi- 
tional data  would  be  needed  before  a  judgment  could  be  reached 
as  to  its  adequacy  relative  to  a  motivational  theory. 

Interpreting  the  Effects  of  Altered  Motivational  Variables  in 
Terms  of  Competing  or  Facilitating  Reactive  Tendencies.  The 
type  of  associative  interpretation  to  be  considered  here  rests  on 
the  assumption  that  the  manipulation  of  a  motivational  variable 
produces  behavioral  changes  through  the  evocation  of  habits  that 
can  either  facilitate  or  compete  with  the  habit  under  investigation. 
Fig.  4:8  indicates  the  stimulus  elements,  associative  tendencies, 
and  responses  to  which  this  type  of  theory  might  appeal  in  explain- 
ing performance  decrements  following  a  shift  from  long-term  to 
short-term  deprivation.  It  has  been  assumed  that  the  response  is 
one  of  learning  to  approach  a  goal  for  food  under  moderately 
strong  hunger.  The  upper  half  of  the  figure  shows  that  during 
original  training  the  approaching  response  has  become  attached 
to  a  stimulus  compound  consisting  of  Si,  So,  S3,  S4,  and  Se.  When 
a  shift  is  made  to  short-term-deprivation  testing  conditions,  the 
important  elements  are  as  shown  in  the  lower  half  of  the  figure. 


Internal  cues  due 
to  long-term  - 
deprivation 

External  cues 


Training  conditions 


'1'  -^a'  ^3'  "^4 


-^S, 


—H R 


approach 


Internal  cues  due 
to  short-term 
deprivation 

Satiation  cues 


External  cues 


Testing  conditions 
^8^,82 yh 


approach 


Fig.  4:8.  Stimulus  elements  and  associative  tendencies  assumed  to  charac- 
terize a  situation  wherein  an  approach  response  has  been  learned  under  long- 
term  deprivation  and  tests  are  subsequently  conducted  under  short-term  de- 
privation. These  are  the  components  of  an  associative  interpretation  that 
relies  upon  competing  habit  strengths  to  explain  the  negative  eflfects  on  per- 
formance of  shifts  to  short-term  deprivation. 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS 


127 


For  one  thing,  S3  and  S4  are  assumed  to  drop  out  under  low  mo- 
tivation, which  causes  a  weakening  of  the  approaching  habit 
(shown  by  the  lower  case  h).  So  far,  this  is  identical  with  the 
stimulus-deletion  interpretation  discussed  in  an  earlier  section  of 
this  chapter.  The  new  feature  of  interest  at  this  point  is  the  addi- 
tion of  stimuli  S5  and  Se-  These  may  be  identified  as  the  typical 
cues  accompanying  partial  satiation,  e.g.,  stimuli  arising  from  a 
distended  stomach.  Now  it  might  be  assumed  that  as  a  consequence 
of  past  experience  these  cues  have  become  associated  with  responses 
of  resting,  lying  down,  or  being  inactive.  If  such  is  the  case,  then  a 
decline  in  performance  under  the  satiation  regimen  could  be 
explained  as  a  result  of  the  introduction  of  the  new  tendencies  to 
rest  which  compete  with  the  tendency  to  approach.  Thus  this  inter- 
pretation relies  on  the  assumption  that  overt  performance  will  be 
weakened  if  tendencies  to  make  incompatible  reactions  are  simul- 
taneously aroused. 

The  steps  involved  in  applying  this  competitive-tendency  view 
to  the  case  where  the  deprivation  term  is  changed  from  short  to 
long  are  shown  in  Fig.  4:9.  In  the  upper  part  of  the  figure,  stimuli 
S5  and  Sq,  with  their  already  formed  associated  tendencies  to  rest 


Internal  cues  due 
to  short-term 
deprivation 

Satiation  cues 

External  cues 


Internal  cues  due 
to  long-term 
deprivation 

External  cues 


Training  conditions 

■^81^,82- 


Testing  conditions 


-H- 


approach 


'approach 


Fig.  4:9.  Elements  and  relations  of  an  associative  interpretation  of  perform- 
ance facilitation  following  a  shift  from  short-  to  long-term  deprivation.  The 
presence  of  the  tendency  to  rest  during  original  learning  is  assumed  to  prevent 
the  development  of  a  strong  approach  habit.  Under  long-term  deprivation, 
cues  tending  to  elicit  resting  responses  disappear  and  performance  impro\'es. 


128  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

are  shown  as  present  when  the  approaching  response  is  being 
learned  to  the  complete  stimulus  complex.  If  during  the  course  of 
this  learning  the  strength  of  the  resting  tendencies  is  never  com- 
pletely extinguished,  the  ultimate  level  of  performance  attainable 
under  short-term  deprivation  would  be  reduced  by  an  amount 
depending  on  the  strength  of  the  incompatible  habits  to  rest. 
Thus  the  net  associative  tendency  to  approach  is  represented  by 
a  small  h.  Under  long-term  deprivation,  stimuli  S5  and  Sq  are 
eliminated,  and  the  subtractive  (interfering)  effect  of  the  com- 
petitive resting  tendency  (lower  part  of  Fig.  4:9)  disappears.  As 
a  consequence,  performance  might  improve,  provided  the  new 
stimuli  S3  and  S4  play  an  insignificant  role,  as  they  should  since 
they  have  not  previously  been  associated  with  approaching.  In 
effect,  then,  performance  facilitation  may  be  explained  by  assum- 
ing that  an  increase  in  deprivation  time  functions  to  remove  or 
eliminate  reactive  tendencies  which  have  prevented  performance 
from  reaching  its  potential  maximum.  It  is  also  possible,  however, 
that  if  So  and  Se  acquired  some  habit  strength  to  elicit  approach 
behavior  (dashed  hne  in  upper  part  of  Fig.  4:9)  during  the  orig- 
inal learning,  their  disappearance  under  long-term  deprivation 
would  tend  to  impair  performance  and  perhaps  to  offset  any  gains 
due  to  the  elimination  of  the  resting  responses.  Strictly  speaking, 
however,  this  is  a  stimulus-subtraction  mechanism  rather  than  one 
involving  the  interactions  of  habits. 

Performance  decrements  following  the  substitution  of  one  need 
for  another  could  be  readily  explained  by  the  competitive-tendency 
notion.  In  all  such  cases,  the  only  assumption  required  is  that  the 
new  need  produces  new  stimuli  to  which  incompatible  reaction 
tendencies  are  attached.  The  competing-habit  formulation  can  also 
be  extended  to  the  results  of  studies  (e.g.,  Fredenburg,  1956)  in 
which  separate  groups  of  subjects  have  been  maintained  under 
different  deprivation  levels  throughout  the  course  of  learning. 
Perhaps  interfering  tendencies  to  rest  become  weaker  as  the 
deprivation  period  is  lengthened  and  asymptotic  performance 
level  can  therefore  be  elevated  progressively. 

When  the  competing-habit  hypothesis  is  applied  to  behavior 
in  situations  such  as  the  T  maze,  the  interpretation  might  be 
structured  somewhat  as  follows ;  If  performance  declines,  following 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  129 

a  shift  from  long-  to  short-term  deprivation,  it  would  be  necessary 
to  suppose  that  competitive  tendencies  become  stronger  and  inter- 
fere more  with  correct  than  with  incorrect  habits.  Conversely,  if 
training  is  carried  out  under  a  short-term  deprivation  schedule, 
improvement  following  a  lengthening  of  the  deprivation  period 
would  be  ascribed  either  to  the  elimination  of  competing  habits 
or  to  the  accrual  of  compatible  ones. 

As  we  have  already  noted,  competing-habit  interpretations  of 
the  effects  of  variations  in  deprivation  conditions  have  not  been 
formulated  in  detail.  Clearly,  the  preceding  suggestions  toward 
such  a  theory  are  largely  ad  hoc,  and  much  remains  to  be  done  in 
the  way  of  refinement  and  extension.  Especially  needed  are  precise 
statements  as  to  how  associative  tendencies  compete  with  or  aug- 
ment one  another,  and  useful  ways  of  defining  competing  habits 
independently  of  the  situations  in  which  they  are  presumed  to  be 
degrading  performance.  Incidentally,  it  is  conceivable  that  the 
most  generally  adequate  associative  theory  would  be  one  that 
incorporates  all  of  the  best  assumptions  of  the  three  versions 
suggested  here.  Thus  the  notions  of  stimulus-element  addition  and 
subtraction,  of  stimulus  generalization,  and  of  competing  ten- 
dencies might  be  combined  into  a  single  more  potent  theory  of 
the  effects  on  behavior  of  changes  in  motivational  variables. 

Advocates  of  Associative  Interpretations 

At  the  start  of  our  discussion  of  the  various  forms  that  an  asso- 
ciative interpretation  might  take  it  was  noted  that  although  no 
one  writer  has  presented  us  with  a  full-blown  theory  of  this  sort, 
psychological  literature  contains  numerous  suggestions  to  the 
effect  that  the  construct  of  drive  may  be  superfluous.  Postman 
(1953b),  for  instance,  has  clearly  seen  that  since  the  manipulation 
of  certain  so-called  motivational  variables  may  affect  drive  stimuli 
as  well  as  drive,  it  might  be  possible,  and  certainly  more  econom- 
ical, to  dispense  with  the  concept  of  drive  entirely  and  to  base 
one's  interpretations  of  motivated  behavior  solely  upon  changes 
in  drive  stimuli.  Postman's  (1953d)  analysis  of  experiments  on 
motivational  selectivity  in  perception  is  consistent  with  this  sug- 
gestion since,  following  the  work  of  Solomon  and  Howes  (1951), 


130  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

he  has  placed  heavy  emphasis  upon  the  contribution  to  "moti- 
vated" perception  of  associative  predispositions.  It  would  be  pre- 
mature to  attempt  to  identify  Postman's  views  as  characteristic 
of  any  of  the  three  associative  versions  presented  above,  but  he 
has  appealed  both  to  competing  associative  tendencies  and  to 
modified  stimuli  in  his  interpretations  of  the  effects  on  perception 
of  motivational  variables. 

Probably  the  most  explicit  associative  theory  of  the  effects  of 
motivational  variables  is  that  of  Estes  (1958),  who  has  extended 
his  statistical  theory  of  learning  specifically  to  the  problems  of 
motivation.  This  development,  which  appeared  after  the  preceding 
associative  conceptions  were  written,  and  which  can  be  presented 
only  in  broad  perspective  because  of  its  specialized  terminolog)', 
is  essentially  an  extension  and  formalization  of  Guthrie's  (1935) 
contiguity  theory.  According  to  this  view,  the  probability  that  a 
response  will  occur  depends  upon  the  proportion  of  the  stimulus 
elements  in  a  situation  that  have  been  conditioned  to  the  response. 
In  the  case  of  a  variable  such  as  food  deprivation,  the  internal 
drive  stimuli  assume  a  role  of  relatively  great  importance.  An 
increase  in  deprivation  time  has  two  principal  consequences:  (1) 
the  probability  of  occurrence  of  a  drive  stimulus  increases,  and  ( 2 ) 
the  probability  of  occurrence  of  stimuli  characteristic  of  satiation 
decreases.  From  these  assumptions  and  from  additional  ones  con- 
cerning the  relative  weights,  as  behavior  determinants,  of  these 
cues,  of  conditioned  cues,  and  of  extraneous  cues,  Estes  predicts 
the  outcomes  of  several  experiments  in  which  deprivation  has  been 
manipulated.  For  example,  the  theory  specifies  that  if  training  is 
carried  out  at  a  single  level  of  deprivation,  asymptotic  perform- 
ance will  be  higher  the  more  severe  the  deprivation.  It  is  also 
predicted  that  if  a  single  group  is  trained  at  several  deprivation 
levels,  as  in  Cotton's  (1953)  experiment  (see  Chapter  3  above), 
asymptotic  performance  level  should  vary  with  deprivation  if 
behavior  on  all  trials  is  counted,  but  not  if  those  trials  on  which 
competing  responses  occur  are  eliminated.  The  theory  also  predicts, 
as  was  true  of  the  associative  hypotheses  we  have  just  considered, 
that  if  training  is  carried  out  under  a  moderate  level  of  deprivation, 
performance  should  become  worse  if  deprivation  is  suddenly  en- 
hanced. This  expectation  follows  from  the  assumption  that  an 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  131 

increase  in  deprivation  will  change  the  drive-stimulus  complex  by 
introducing  new  elements  not  previously  associated  with  the 
response,  and  will  thereby  reduce  the  proportion  of  elements 
conditioned  to  the  response.  Since  this  effect  is  attributed  to  the 
tendency  for  the  new  elements  to  elicit  interfering  or  competing 
responses,  this  aspect  of  the  theory  is  comparable  to  the  third 
associative  interpretation  presented  above.  But  since  the  findings 
of  such  studies  as  those  of  Deese  and  Carpenter  (1951),  Loess 
(1952),  and  Hillman,  Hunter,  and  Kimble  (1953)  contradict 
this  theoretical  expectation,  the  drive-stimulus  conception  may 
require  modification.  Bolles  (1958)  has  also  pointed  out  that  the 
theory  may  encounter  difficulty  in  explaining  (1)  the  correlation 
of  vigor  of  running  with  degree  of  deprivation  when  training  has 
been  administered  at  a  single  level  of  deprivation,  and  (2)  the 
phenomena  of  incentive  motivation.  Nevertheless,  Estes'  formula- 
tion, which  he  has  also  applied  to  the  problems  of  need  combina- 
tion and  stimulus  generalization,  undoubtedly  constitutes  the  most 
systematic  attempt  yet  made  to  replace  the  concept  of  general 
drive  with  purely  associative  mechanisms. 

Bindra  (1959),  expanding  on  Estes'  (1950)  original  theory,  has 
suggested  that  the  interfering  responses  responsible  for  perform- 
ance decrements  following  stimulus  changes  are  actually  "novelty 
reactions"  and  that  the  performance  decrement,  therefore,  is  due 
to,  and  directly  dependent  upon,  the  novelty  of  the  test  situation. 
Although  Bindra  does  not  relate  this  hypothesis  specifically  to  the 
problem  of  motivational  variables,  it  is  apparent  that  it  might  be 
extended  to  the  effects  of  changes  of  needs  or  to  changes  in  dep- 
rivation severity.  One  wonders,  however,  whether  it  would  be 
meaningful  to  suppose  that  a  rat  would  ever  find  his  own  internal 
hunger  or  satiation  stimuli  to  be  novel  even  when  they  are  con- 
siderably different  from  what  they  were  at  some  previous  time. 

Other  hints  that  motivational  phenomena  can  perhaps  be  inter- 
preted without  reference  to  a  drive  construct  may  be  found  in 
the  earlier  writings  of  Hebb  (1949),  and  in  the  theoretical  inter- 
pretations of  Child  and  Waterhouse  (1953),  Meyer  (1953),  Mc- 
Clelland, Atkinson,  Clark,  and  Lowell  (1953),  Campbell  and 
Kraeling  (1954),  Farber  (1955),  Davis  (1957),  Holder,  Marx, 
Holder,  and  Collier  (1957),  and  Meyer  and  Noble  (1958). 


132  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Resume  of  Evidence  Bearing 
on  Motivational  Interpretations 

Although  associative  conceptuaHzations  appear  to  possess  the 
virtue  of  simphcity,  it  would  be  premature  to  conclude  that  the 
idea  of  a  general  energizing  drive  must,  therefore,  be  rejected 
completely.  One  of  the  major  reasons  for  retaining  the  hypothesis 
of  a  general  drive  is  that  certain  variables  such  as  strong  stimula- 
tion and  food  or  water  deprivation  have  facilitative  effects  upon 
surprisingly  diverse  kinds  of  responses.  Considering  intense  stimuli 
first,  we  find  that  electric  shock  or  its  aftereffects  facilitates  eat- 
ing (Siegel  and  Brantley,  1951),  drinking  (Amsel  and  Maltzman, 
1950),  running  speed  and  correct  choices  in  a  T  maze  after  train- 
ing under  hunger  (Miller,  1948ib),  wheel  turning  to  an  auditory 
signal  (Nagaty,  1951),  visual  discrimination — when  shock  is  ad- 
ministered intracerebrally — (Fuster,  1958),  reaction  time  (Johan- 
son,  1922),  human  eyelid  conditioning  (Spence,  Farber,  and  Tay- 
lor, 1954),  and  of  course,  escape  and  avoidance  behavior  in  many 
different  situations.  Moderate  degrees  of  muscular  tension  also 
exhibit  facihtative  effects  of  considerable  generahty.  Courts  (1942), 
who  has  summarized  these  findings,  states  that  all  of  the  following 
have  been  shown  to  be  augmented  by  tension :  conditioned  salivary 
responses  in  dogs,  pursuit-rotor  performance,  the  knee  jerk,  vibra- 
tory sensitivity,  reaction  time,  mental  arithmetic,  tapping,  startle 
responses,  electric-shock  thresholds,  and  ball  throwing  for  accuracy. 
In  the  case  of  food  deprivation,  it  is  interesting  to  note  that  in 
addition  to  its  familiar  role  as  a  facilitator  of  diverse  instrumental 
acts  and  of  general  activity  (Siegel  and  Steinberg,  1949;  Hall  and 
Hanford,  1954)  it  enhances  reactions  to  intracranial  electrical 
stimulation  (Brady,  Boren,  Conrad,  and  Sidman,  1957),  drinking 
(Miller,  1948b),  escape  from  light  (Bahrick,  1953),  and  the  rein- 
forcing effect  of  light  onset  (Davis,  1958).  Moreover,  as  we  have 
previously  observed,  loud  noises,  bright  lights,  and  air  deprivation 
also  activate  a  variety  of  responses  under  particular  conditions. 

The  important  point  in  connection  with  all  these  observations 
is  that  each  of  the  several  motivational  variables  has  the  capacity 
to  amplify  activities  whose  manifest  topographies  and  controlling 
stimulus  complexes  differ  extensively.  In  some  cases  it  may  be 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  133 

reasonable  to  suppose  that  the  internal  (or  other)  cues  produced 
by  the  variable  have  been  associated  with  the  reference  response 
during  previous  periods  of  training.  But  it  is  difficult  to  imagine 
that  this  has  occurred  in  every  instance  where  facilitation  has  been 
observed.  Wherever  such  associations  cannot  be  invoked,  a  non- 
specific energizing  drive  becomes  a  reasonable  alternative. 

The  fact  that  motivational  variables  sometimes  cause  decre- 
ments in  performance  must  be  noted,  but  it  is  not  of  crucial  im- 
portance for  either  the  motivational  or  the  associative  theories. 
Hull's  multiplicative-drive  theory  interprets  such  findings  by  assert- 
ing that  drive  is  indeed  increased  and  that  either  (1)  associative 
tendencies  to  make  the  wrong  responses  are  initially  dominant 
over  the  correct  ones,  or  (2)  that  the  motivational  variable  pro- 
vides new  stimuli  to  which  overriding  competitive  responses  are 
attached.  The  second  of  these  is  obviously  the  same  conception 
upon  which  associative  interpretations  rely. 

A  second  major  line  of  evidence  favoring  a  general-drive  theor}', 
as  against  a  purely  associative  view,  is  provided  by  studies  in 
which  an  increase  in  deprivation  from  that  employed  during  train- 
ing produces  augmented  performance.  We  have  already  reviewed 
these  studies  and  have  observed  that  none  of  the  associative  ver- 
sions, unless  modified  by  special  ad  hoc  assumptions,  can  readily 
encompass  this  phenomenon.  However,  shifts  from  short  to  long 
deprivation  sometimes  lead  to  the  decrements  in  performance 
predicted  by  associative  theory  (cf.  Yamaguchi,  1952),  and  much 
additional  research  is  needed  to  determine  the  direction  and  extent 
of  the  effects. 

Other  evidence  consistent  with  the  concept  of  general  drive 
stems  from  studies  in  which  the  combination  of  two  different 
motivational  variables  leads  to  better  or  more  vigorous  perform- 
ance than  does  either  alone.  For  instance,  Amsel  (1950(3)  reports 
that  speed  of  running,  as  motivated  by  a  conditioned  pain-fear 
reaction,  is  enhanced  when  a  primary  need  for  food  is  added  to 
the  motivational  complex.  Similarly,  Meryman  (1952)  has  ob- 
tained clear  evidence  that  unconditioned  startle  responses  in  rats 
are  amplified  more  by  a  combination  of  hunger  and  conditioned 
fear  than  by  either  separately.  Jerome,  Moody,  Connor,  and 
Fernandez  (1957)  recorded  the  number  of  crossings  made  by  rats 


134  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

from  one  side  to  another  of  a  multiple-door  shuttle  box,  and  noted 
that  the  addition  of  hunger  to  an  aversive  light  stimulus  led  to 
more  crossings  than  did  either  hunger  or  light  alone.  Probability  of 
error,  however,  proved  to  be  unrelated  to  level  of  motivation.  A 
satisfactory  associative  explanation  of  these  findings  might  be 
developed,  provided  one  could  show  that  the  motivation-variable 
stimuli  had  been  previously  associated  either  with  the  reference 
response  or  with  responses  capable  of  augmenting  that  response. 
But  this  may  prove  to  be  difficult,  especially  in  the  Meryman 
study,  where  one  would  have  to  suppose  that  the  cues  of  hunger 
and  fear  had  somehow  become  conditioned  to  vigorous  startle  re- 
sponses during  the  normal  cage  life  of  laboratory  rats. 

Experiments  in  which  two  appetitive  variables  are  combined 
have  yielded  conflicting  results.  Kendler  (1945)  found  that  the 
addition  of  moderate  periods  (up  to  12  hours)  of  water  depriva- 
tion to  hunger  led  to  an  increase  in  the  resistance  to  extinction  of 
a  food-reinforced  bar-pressing  response,  but  that  a  reverse  effect 
was  obtained  when  the  period  of  water  deprivation  was  increased 
to  22%  hours.  Other  studies,  such  as  that  of  Verplanck  and  Hayes 
(1953),  indicate  that  consummatory  activities  either  of  eating  or 
drinking  are  reduced  by  the  arousal  of  the  opposite  need;  but 
Powloski  (1953)  reports  that  discrimination  learning  is  as  effective 
under  both  hunger  and  thirst  as  with  either  alone.  In  general, 
the  findings  of  these  and  related  investigations  do  not  support 
Hull's  view  that  two  need  states  summate  to  yield  a  higher  level  of 
general  drive.  The  discovery  of  interactive  effects  among  needs, 
though  not  crucial  to  the  concept  of  drive  as  a  behavior  determi- 
nant, suggests  the  need  for  changes  in  the  functions  that  have 
been  assumed  to  hold  between  drive  and  its  deprivation  an- 
tecedents. 

It  is  also  worth  noting,  as  Spence  (1956,  1958)  has  shown,  that 
the  specific  hypothesis  of  a  multiplicative  relation  between  drive 
and  habit  strength  has  been  supported  in  a  variety  of  studies, 
specifically  those  in  which  performance  curves  obtained  under  dif- 
ferent levels  of  deprivation  or  under  different  strengths  of  an  un- 
conditioned stimulus  have  been  found  to  diverge  as  a  function  of 
training.  Similar  curves  obtained  under  different  incentive  levels 
(i.e.,  magnitude  of  reward)  also  tend  to  diverge  over  training  trials. 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  135 

and  since  incentive  is  assumed  to  determine  a  motivational  factor, 
this  too  is  consistent  with  the  multipHcative  interpretation. 

In  conclusion,  it  appears  from  the  above  summary  of  experi- 
mental evidence  that  many  diverse  findings  are  consistent  with 
the  concept  of  a  nonspecific  activating  drive.  Certain  of  these 
facts,  however,  can  also  be  explained  as  instances  of  the  operation 
of  learned  or  unlearned  associative  predispositions.  The  principle 
of  parsimony  supports  the  wisdom  of  exploring  fully  the  utility  of 
associative  interpretations,  but  until  these  theories  have  been 
more  fully  developed  it  seems  wise  to  retain  both  an  intermediary 
construct  of  general  drive  and  associative  mechanisms.  In  Chapter 
9  additional  evidence  is  presented  from  the  field  of  physiological 
psychology  that  is  consistent  with  the  general-drive  conception. 

Summary 

In  this  chapter  we  have  analyzed  two  general  approaches  to  the 
problem  of  how  motivational  variables  function  to  modify  be- 
havior. One  type  of  conception,  termed  a  motivational  interpreta- 
tion, introduces,  and  places  in  a  role  of  central  importance,  a 
unique  motivational  construct  such  as  drive.  In  Hull's  multiplica- 
tive-drive theory,  which  is  used  as  the  major  example,  drive  is 
described  as  a  nondirective  factor  that  is  aroused  by  a  variety  of 
antecedent  conditions  and  becomes  manifest  in  behavior  through 
its  capacity  to  multiply  existing  associative  tendencies  (habits). 
The  multiplicative  combination  of  drive  with  habits  is  assumed 
to  yield  a  quantity  termed  excitatory  potential  which,  though 
modified  by  other  factors,  is  more  or  less  directly  reflected  in  be- 
havior. Those  who  hold  that  intervening  motivational  constructs 
are  useful  also  maintain  that  motivational  variables  have  stimulus 
consequences  in  addition  to  their  capacity  to  arouse  drive  and  that 
responses  of  many  kinds  are,  or  can  become,  associated  with  these 
stimuli. 

The  principal  implications  of  Hull's  multiplicative  theory  are 
reviewed  and  are  seen  to  be  the  following:  First,  the  fact  that  be- 
havior is  exhibited  when,  for  example,  an  animal  is  hungry  but 
not  when  he  is  satiated  is  attributed  to  the  multiplying  effect  of 
drive  and  the  resulting  elevation  of  the  appropriate  excitatory  tend- 


136  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

encies  to  a  suprathreshold  level.  Likewise,  correlations  between  the 
vigor  of  overt  responses  and  time  of  deprivation  are  ascribed  to 
level  of  drive,  provided  that  habit  strength  is  held  constant.  Sec- 
ond, if  two  or  more  reactive  tendencies  are  present,  the  absolute 
difference  between  their  respective  excitatory  potentials  will  in- 
crease as  drive  is  strengthened  and  decrease  as  drive  is  diminished. 
This  leads  to  the  prediction  tli^t  whenever  the  correct  reactive 
tendency  is  stronger  than  any  pther,  heightened  drive  will  result 
in  improved  performance.  But  if  an  incorrect  tendency  is  strongest, 
increased  drive  should  lead  to  poorer  performance.  Conversely, 
reduced  drive  can  lead  either  to  poorer  or  to  better  performance 
depending  upon  which  tendency  is  at  the  top  of  the  response 
hierarchy.  These  predictions  will  not  be  fulfilled,  however,  if  the 
motivational  variable  determining  drive  strength  also  serves  as 
the  source  of  stimuli  to  which  competitive  or  facilitative  responses 
have  been  associated.  When  the  manipulation  of  a  variable  re- 
sults in  the  introduction  of  salient  cues,  the  hierarchical  order  of 
habit  strengths  can  be  radically  altered,  and  predictions  based 
upon  the  initial  order  must  be  modified  appropriately.  Third,  if 
in  spatial-  or  discrimination-choice  situations  the  habits  corre- 
sponding to  the  two  responses  are  held  equal,  drive  strength 
should  be  unrelated  to  choice  of  the  conect  alternative. 

The  second  major  type  of  conception  considered  in  this  chapter 
is  one  that  rejects  the  need  for  constructs  such  as  drive  and  ap- 
peals only  to  variations  in  associative  strengths  in  accounting  for 
the  effects  on  behavior  of  changes  in  motivational  variables.  Be- 
cause associative  theories  of  this  kind  are  just  beginning  to 
appear,  it  has  been  necessar}'  to  be  somewhat  speculative  concern- 
ing the  several  forms  that  such  theories  may  eventually  assume. 
One  possible  version  of  an  associative  theory  might  stress  the 
notion  that  performance  is  altered  by  a  change  in  a  motivational 
variable  from  that  used  during  training  because  some  of  the 
stimulus  elements  associated  with  the  response  have  been  elimi- 
nated and/or  new  elements  have  been  added.  One  might  thus 
explain  a  decline  in  performance  following  a  shift  from  hunger 
to  near-satiation;  but  without  additional  assumptions,  performance 
facilitation  due  to  enhanced  deprivation  would  be  difficult  to 
interpret. 


MOTIVATIONAL  AND  ASSOCIATIVE  INTERPRETATIONS  137 

A  second  variety  of  associative  theory  would  emphasize  the 
idea  that  changes  in  motivational  variables  alter  the  intensity  or 
quality  of  cues  and  that  alterations  in  existing  associative  strengths 
would  then  occur  in  accordance  with  the  principle  of  habit- 
strength  generalization.  In  effect,  this  principle  is  a  guess  as  to  how 
the  level  of  a  reactive  tendency  is  altered  as  a  function  of  specific 
modifications  of  the  stimulus  to  which  the  response  was  originally 
conditioned.  In  the  extension  of  this  principle  to  motivational  phe- 
nomena, emphasis  is  placed  more  upon  the  generalization  of 
internal  stimuli  than  upon  changes  in  external  cues.  This  asso- 
ciative model  can  encompass  the  effects  of  shifts  from  long  to 
short  deprivation,  changes  from  one  need  state  to  another,  and, 
with  some  additional  assumptions,  the  transfer  to  a  noxious  stim- 
ulus of  a  response  learned  under  an  appetitive  need.  As  was  true 
of  the  first  associative  theory,  however,  the  second  encounters 
difficulties  in  attempting  to  interpret  performance  enhancement 
following  changes  from  mild  to  severe  deprivation. 

A  third  associative  interpretation  might  be  developed  which 
stresses  the  possibility  that  new  habits,  either  facilitative  or  com- 
petitive, are  brought  into  effective  action  by  manipulations  of 
motivational  variables.  On  this  hypothesis,  the  original  habit  is 
not  changed  to  a  major  degree  by  the  addition  or  subtraction  of 
stimulus  elements  or  by  variations  in  the  quality  or  intensity  of 
the  relevant  stimulus  complex.  Instead,  the  motivational  variable 
modifies  the  effective  strength  of  the  original  associative  tendency 
by  evoking  new  habits  and  thus  leads  to  different  behavior.  For 
this  interpretation  to  become  widely  useful,  specific  principles  of 
habit  interaction  would  have  to  be  developed  and  substantiated. 

At  the  close  of  the  chapter,  evidence  bearing  on  the  concept  of 
a  nonspecific  drive  was  reviewed,  and  the  tentative  conclusion  was 
reached  that  although  associative  theories  can  successfully  account 
for  a  number  of  motivational  phenomena,  the  construct  of  drive 
is  nevertheless  supported  by  a  wide  variety  of  findings. 


CHAPTER 


5 


Learned  Responses  as 
Sources  of  Drive 

As  WE  HAVE  SEEN,  particularly  in  Chapter  3,  the  various  primary 
motivational  variables  may  influence  behavior  in  profound  and 
widespread  ways.  In  our  society,  however,  with  its  high  standard  of 
living,  the  large  majority  of  individuals  are  seldom  racked  by  the 
pangs  of  severe  hunger  or  by  the  tormenting  sensations  of  intense 
thirst,  and  the  experience  of  intense  or  prolonged  pain  is  the  ex- 
ception rather  than  the  rule.  It  is,  in  part,  because  of  this  meliora- 
tion of  man's  condition  that  the  tendency  to  regard  biological 
needs  and  intense  stimuli  as  the  principal  motivators  of  complex 
human  behavior  has  waned  in  recent  times.  In  its  place  the  wide- 
spread conviction  has  arisen  that  the  most  significant  source  of 
motivation  for  human  beings  lies  in  the  elaborate  experiential  struc- 
ture produced  by  learning  and  acculturation.  Human  beings  are 
said  to  be  motivated  to  a  significant  degree  by  the  so-called  ac- 
quired drives  for  success,  prestige,  security,  power,  affection,  money, 
property,  and  the  like.  As  we  shall  indicate,  it  is  questionable 
whether  specific  directed  tendencies  of  this  sort  should  be  called 
"drives"  at  all,  but  it  is  clear  that  learning  plays  a  major  role  in  the 

138 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  139 

activities  described  by  these  terms.  The  infant  human  organism 
certainly  does  not  possess  these  tendencies,  and  it  seems  logical, 
therefore,  to  assume  that  they  represent  complex  relationships 
among  the  diversified  products  of  the  learning  process. 

Before  beginning  our  discussion  of  the  acquired-drive  problem, 
a  word  or  two  concerning  terminology  is  in  order.  In  earlier  chap- 
ters it  was  pointed  out  that  we  are  attempting  to  maintain  a 
clear  distinction  between  a  nondirective,  nonspecific  motivating 
agency,  e.g.,  Hull's  D,  on  the  one  hand,  and  habits,  with  their 
corresponding  responses,  on  the  other.  As  a  consequence  of  this 
attempt,  we  have  avoided  the  use  of  the  term  "primary  drives" 
and  have  spoken  instead  of  "primary  sources  of  drive."  The  pri- 
mary motivating  variables,  it  may  be  recalled,  were  assumed  to 
affect  behavior  by  contributing  to  drive,  and/or  by  modifying 
the  stimulus  complex  {Smv)  in  certain  ways. 

This  usage  is  continued  in  the  present  chapter  and  extended  to 
the  traditional  problem  of  acquired  drives.  To  do  so,  however, 
means  that  we  shall  seldom  speak  of  acquired  drives,  in  the 
plural.  If  the  word  "drive"  is  used  to  mean  a  nonspecific,  nondi- 
rective, behavior-facilitating  agency,  then  it  is  a  construct  to 
which  unitary  properties  should  be  ascribed.  Many  variables  may 
function  motivationally,  but  since,  in  so  doing,  they  are  all  affect- 
ing behavior  in  the  same  way,  it  is  simpler  to  refer  to  them  as 
"sources  of  drive,"  not  as  drives.  This  explains  why  the  present 
chapter  has  been  entitled  "Learned  Responses  as  Sources  of 
Drive,"  rather  than  "Learnable  Drives,"  or  "Secondary  Drives,"  or 
"Acquired  Drives." 

The  Acquired-drive  Problem 

That  both  learning  and  motivation  are  significantly  involved  in 
secondary-drive  phenomena  is  strongly  implied  by  the  words  ac- 
quired drive.  For  many  psychologists  the  outcome  of  learning  is 
the  acquisition  of  a  response  or  a  tendency  to  respond,  and  on 
this  assumption  what  is  acquired  in  the  case  of  an  acquired  drive 
is  a  new  or  altered  response.  To  have  an  acquired  drive,  therefore, 
an  organism  must  have  learned  to  respond,  and  when  this  response  \ 
is  evoked  the  organism's  behavior  must  be  affected  motivationally./ 


140 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


Thus  the  so-called  acquired  drives  may  be  described  as  learned 
responses  having  many  of  the  general  properties  of  all  responses, 
and,  in  addition,  the  capacity  to  affect  other  responses  in  the  same 
ways  in  which  they  are  affected  by  motivational  variables.  Stated 
somewhat  differently,  the  acquired-drive  problem  demands  answers 
to  the  questions  of  how,  and  to  what  extent,  the  variables  that 
govern  the  learning  of  one  response  function  as  though  they  were 
motivational  variables  when  that  response  is  interacting  with 
other  responses.  Within  the  framework  of  a  motivational  theory 
such  as  Hull's,  this  idea  is  expressed  by  the  assumption  that  some 
actions  are  capable  of  adding  increments  to  drive  and  thereby  of 
multiplying  the  habit  strengths  of  other  responses. 

This  conception  of  an  acquired  source  of  drive  is  represented  in 
the  upper  part  of  Fig.  5:1,  where  the  learned  (motivating)  re- 
sponse is  shown  as  dependent  upon  learning  variables  and  stimulus 
variables  (at  the  left),  and  as  leading  to  an  increment  in  general 
drive  (at  the  right).  This  drive  increment,  in  turn,  is  assumed  to 
multiply  the  habit  strength  of  a  reference  or  indicant  response. 


Learning  variables, 
stimulus  variables, - 
etc. 


Learned 
motivating 
response 


Response-produced 
->-  increment  to 
general  D 


I      / 

Donse-  / 


Learning  variables, 
stimulus  variables, 
etc. 


Response 
produced 

stimulus 


Habit 
strength 


X 


Reference 
response 


Fig.  5:1.  Elements  involved  in  two  conceptualizations  of  an  acquired  source 
of  drive.  The  three  components  at  the  top  of  the  diagram  indicate  that  the 
strength  of  a  learned,  motivating  response  depends  primarily  upon  learning 
variables  and  stimulus  variables  and  that  this  response  may  bring  about  an 
increment  to  general  drive  level.  This  drive  increment  may  then  affect  a 
reference  response  by  multiplying  the  habit  strength  of  that  reaction.  How- 
ever, the  motivating  response  may  also  affect  the  reference  response  by  pro- 
viding stimuli  capable  of  modifying  the  latter's  habit  strength.  If  reliance  is 
placed  upon  the  response-produced  drive,  the  theory  becomes  associative- 
motivational.  But,  if  the  entire  explanatory  burden  is  placed  upon  the  re- 
sponse-produced stimuli,  the  theory  should  perhaps  be  described  as  associa- 
tive-associative. 


LEARNED   RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF   DRIVE  141 

Since  both  associative  processes  and  the  construct  of  general  drive 
are  involved  in  this  interpretation,  it  may  be  appropriate  to  term 
it  an  associative-motivational  conception. 

Should  one  choose  to  omit  drive  entirely  in  dealing  with  the 
so-called  acquired  motivations,  appeal  could  be  made  to  the 
stimuli  produced  by  the  learned  (motivating)  response.  These  are 
shown  in  the  center  of  Fig,  5:1  and  are  indicated  as  affecting  the 
reference  response  by  modifying  its  habit  strength.  Since  the 
strength  of  the  learned  motivating  response  rests  upon  associative 
processes,  and  the  mechanism  of  its  influence  upon  the  reference 
activity  is  also  associative,  this  second  conception  might  be  termed 
associative-associative. 

Thus  for  an  associative-motivational  theorist,  learning  variables 
have  motivational-variable  consequences  by  virtue  of  their  effects 
upon  the  strength  of  a  drive-producing  response.  But  for  the 
associative-associative  advocate,  learning  and  stimulus  variables 
determine  the  original  response  and  also  mediate  its  effects, 
through  response-produced  stimuli,  upon  indicant  reactions.  In 
order  to  reduce  our  discussion  to  manageable  proportions,  we  shall 
proceed  throughout  the  remainder  of  this  chapter  on  the  assump- 
tion that  an  intermediary  construct  of  drive  is  still  desirable, 
thereby  adopting  the  associative-motivational  position  as  a  work- 
ing hypothesis.  There  are  good  reasons  for  believing,  however, 
that  the  implications  and  ramifications  of  an  associative-associative 
theory  are  worth  extensive  exploration.  The  development  of  such 
a  theory  would  probably  proceed  along  lines  similar  to  those  that 
characterize  the  associative  theories  described  in  Chapter  4. 

In  order  to  simplify  our  exposition,  the  above  description  of  the 
associative-motivational  view  has  been  presented  without  mention 
of  the  general  drive  produced  by  variables  other  than  the  learned 
response.  Within  the  theory,  however,  the  strength  of  the  motivat- 
ing response  and  hence  also  the  magnitude  of  the  response-pro- 
duced increment  to  D  should  depend  upon  other  sources  of  drive. 
This  raises  the  interesting  possibility  that  the  response-produced 
drive,  when  added  to  general  D,  can  enhance  the  learned  (motivat- 
ing) response  and  hence  itself.  We  shall  make  the  simplifying 
assumption,  however,  that  this  does  not  occur,  the  response-pro- 
duced drive  being  assigned  the  power  to  affect  other  reactions, 


142  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

but  not  itself.  With  respect  to  the  latency  of  a  motivating  re- 
sponse, this  assumption  appears  quite  reasonable,  since  the  time 
of  onset  of  a  given  response  can  hardly  be  affected  by  a  motiva- 
tional increment  that  is  contingent  upon  the  appearance  of  that 
same  response.  It  is  by  no  means  certain,  however,  that  a  motivat- 
ing response,  once  it  has  become  fully  aroused,  cannot  enhance 
itself.  An  analogous  self-augmenting  process  occurs  in  electronic 
circuits  under  conditions  where  "positive  feedback"  from  output 
to  input  is  possible,  and  the  childhood  temper  tantrum  may  be  a 
psychological  instance  of  the  phenomenon.  Moreover,  if  we  take 
the  alleged  motivating  response  of  fear  as  an  example,  it  would  be 
premature  to  insist  either  that  fear  reduction  cannot  function 
to  reinforce  fear  itself — perhaps  this  is  why  some  fears  are  so 
remarkably  persistent — or  that  the  presumed  increase  in  drive  ac- 
companying fear  cannot  act  to  inhibit  fear.  Miller  (1951)  has 
presented  an  illuminating  discussion  of  certain  aspects  of  these 
problems,  but  it  is  the  writer's  belief  that  our  knowledge  of  such 
matters  as  the  nature  of  reinforcement  and  the  rise  and  fall  of 
motivating  responses  with  time  is  too  meager  to  warrant  further 
extensive  speculation  at  present. 

Although  we  have  maintained  that  only  learned  responses  or 
readinesses  to  respond  qualify  as  secondary  sources  of  motivational 
effects,  this  assumption  is  not  as  restrictive  as  one  might  imagine. 
It  does  not  mean  that  attitudes,  opinions,  expectancies,  perceptual 
readinesses,  hopes,  and  the  like,  are  necessarily  eliminated  from 
consideration  as  acquired  motivators.  But  it  does  mean  that  the 
processes  or  events  designated  by  these  terms  would  have  to  be 
treated,  within  the  theory,  as  responses  or  readinesses  to  respond. 
In  many  instances,  this  is  not  a  difficult  step.  An  attitude  or  an 
expectancy  is  not  a  directly  observable  entity.  Therefore,  useful 
inferences  about  expectancies  or  attitudes  must  rest  ultimately 
upon  the  fact — if  and  when  it  is  a  fact — that  indicant  responses  of 
such  and  such  a  kind  have  occurred  in  a  specific  environment. 
When  subjected  to  critical  analysis,  therefore,  attitudes,  hopes, 
fears,  opinions,  and  expectancies  can  probably  all  be  reduced  to 
learned  reaction  readinesses.  And  to  the  degree  that  these  re- 
sponses affect  other  behaviors  as  do  motivational  variables,  they 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  143 

too  would  conform  to  our  conception  of  acquired  sources  of  drive. 

The  general  way  in  which  we  have  posed  the  acquired-drive 
problem  may  seem  abstract  and  impalpable  because  reactive  tend- 
encies and  even  many  responses  cannot  be  observed  in  any  simple 
and  direct  way.  This  need  not  be  a  matter  for  grave  concern,  how- 
ever, since  corresponding  formulations  of  the  problem  can  be 
couched  in  the  purely  descriptive  language  of  the  empirical  psy- 
chologist or  in  the  neurophysiological  terms  of  the  physiological 
psychologist.  Thus,  the  empirically  minded  scientist  may  wish  to 
deal  only  with  directly  observable  relations  between  an  organism's 
molar  behavior  and  other  variables  in  its  training  or  environment. 
For  such  a  psychologist  the  acquired-drive  phenomenon  would 
be  typified  by  the  observation  that  one  response  is  affected  in  cer- 
tain specifiable  (motivational)  ways  by  the  kinds  and  amounts  of 
practice,  among  other  things,  that  an  organism  has  had  in  making 
some  other  response.  In  the  case  of  the  physiologically  inclined 
psychologist,  the  acquired-drive  problem  might  be  stated  as  a 
search  for  the  neurological  or  other  bodily  mechanisms  involved 
when  one  bit  of  behavior  is  affected  in  motivational  ways  by  other, 
previously  learned,  reactions.  The  manner  in  which  the  acquired- 
drive  problem  is  phrased  will,  of  course,  influence  the  kind  of  re- 
search one  is  led  to  do,  but  the  basic  relations  and  critical  questions 
remain  essentially  unchanged  throughout  such  transformations. 

The  foregoing  analysis  of  the  acquired-drive  problem  serves  to 
set  the  stage  for  discussions  to  follow,  but  it  also  raises  numerous 
questions  for  which  satisfactory  answers  are  not  yet  available.  For 
example,  one  wonders  whether  motivating  responses  can  be  dis- 
tinguished from  other  responses  by  a  consideration  of  such  manifest 
attributes  as  their  latencies,  durations,  or  anatomical  bases.  Or  is 
the  course  of  the  acquisition  and  the  extinction  of  a  motivating 
response  determined  by  the  same  variables  (e.g.,  number  of  trials, 
degree  of  distribution  of  practice,  percentage  of  reinforcement) 
that  are  now  known  to  affect  other  reactions?  Moreover,  it  would 
be  important  to  know  something  of  the  nature  of  the  neural  and/ 
or  chemical  mechanisms  by  means  of  which  motivating  responses 
can  influence  other  activities.  And  finally  we  shall  eventually  find 
it  desirable  to  determine  precisely  which  of  the  criteria  for  the 


144  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

identification  of  a  motivational  variable  (cf.  Chapter  2)  have  been 
met  on  any  given  occasion  when  an  acquired  drive  is  alleged  to 
have  been  generated. 

Conditioned  Fear  as  a  Source  of  Drive 

Up  to  this  point,  our  discussion  of  learned  motivating  reactions 
has,  of  necessity,  been  rather  general.  To  make  our  analysis  more 
specific  we  turn  now  to  the  consideration  of  one  particular  re- 
sponse that  seems  to  be  rather  well  established  as  a  motivator  for 
other  responses.  This  is  the  response  of  conditioned  fear,  which, 
in  its  motivating  role,  has  usually  been  described  as  "the  acquired 
drive  of  fear  or  anxiety." 

The  general  notion  that  a  tendency  to  be  fearful  or  anxious  may 
have  motivating  effects  upon  other  responses,  though  historically 
old,  became  significant  for  modern  psychology  through  the  writ- 
ings of  Cannon  (1929)  and  Freud  (1936).  The  translation  of 
this  general  conception  into  the  more  specific  language  of  the 
modern  behavior  scientist,  however,  was  the  work  of  Mowrer 
(1939).  According  to  Mowrer,  anxiety  or  fear  is  a  learned  emo- 
tional reaction  to  stimuli  denoting  the  advent  of  a  painful  or 
noxious  event.  It  is  a  reaction  acquired  in  accordance  with  the 
associative  laws  of  classical  conditioning.  Moreover,  certain  of  its 
behavioral  effects  are  comparable  to  the  effects  produced  by  such 
primary  motivational  variables  as  food  deprivation  and  strong 
stimuli.  Specifically,  fear  sometimes  seems  to  function  as  a  gen- 
eral energizer,  and  its  reduction,  following  the  elicitation  of  a  new 
directed  response,  may  serve  to  reinforce  the  learning  of  the  new 
reaction.  Since  fear,  described  in  this  manner,  is  evidently  learned, 
and  since  its  effects  upon  other  bits  of  behavior  resemble  the 
effects  of  motivational  variables,  it  qualifies  by  our  criteria  as  an 
acquired  source  of  drive. 

Procedures  Used  in  Conditioning  Fear  Reactions.  Although  psy- 
chologists hold  different  views  as  to  how  fear  is  learned,  all  follow 
essentially  the  same  procedures  in  attempting  to  produce  condi- 
tioned fear  in  the  laboratory.  The  training  or  conditioning  trials 
always  involve  paired  presentations  of  a  neutral  stimulus — the  so- 
called  conditioned  stimulus    {CS) — and  a  definitely  painful  or 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  145 

noxious  stimulus.  The  painful  stimulus  fulfills  the  role  of  the 
familiar  unconditioned  stimulus  {UCS).  Quite  frequently  the 
UCS  is  an  electric  shock  intense  enough  to  produce  overt  signs  of 
"emotional"  excitement  or  disruption.  In  establishing  condi- 
tioned fear  reactions  in  rats,  for  example,  a  buzzer,  light,  or  click- 
ing sound  may  be  used  as  the  CS.  It  is  presented  for  perhaps  a 
second,  though  sometimes  much  longer,  before  the  animal  is 
given  one  or  more  short,  strong  shocks.  Typically,  the  paired  ad- 
ministration of  the  CS  and  UCS  is  said  to  result  in  the  acquisition 
by  the  CS  of  a  tendency  to  evoke  an  anticipatory  emotional  (fear) 
response  that  resembles,  but  need  not  be  identical  with,  the  pain- 
produced  reactions  to  the  UCS. 

When  the  responses  in  a  conditioning  experiment  can  be  directly 
observed  and  recorded,  as  in  studies  of  eyeblinks  or  leg  flexions, 
strength  of  conditioning  is  usually  estimated  in  one  of  two  ways. 
First,  the  CS  may  be  presented  alone,  either  following  the  comple- 
tion of  the  conditioning  trials,  or  at  irregular  intervals  throughout 
the  course  of  conditioning.  A  conditioned  response  is  defined  as 
the  appearance  on  a  CS-only  test  trial  of  a  reaction  of  a  certain 
(arbitrarily  defined)  magnitude  and/or  latency.  Second,  on  any 
trial  on  which  both  the  CS  and  the  UCS  are  presented,  a  response 
having  the  defined  characteristics  may  appear  between  the  onsets 
of  the  CS  and  UCS,  or  after  the  onset  of  the  UCS,  but  sooner 
than  if  it  had  been  a  response  to  the  UCS  itself.  Such  responses 
are  tallied  as  conditioned  responses. 

These  procedures  are  also  occasionally  used  in  studies  of  condi- 
tioned fear.  For  example,  if  the  response  being  recorded  is  a  change 
in  heart  rate  or  in  skin  resistance,  the  frequency  or  magnitude  of 
these  changes  to  the  CS  alone  or  to  the  CS  in  anticipation  of  the 
UCS,  are  commonly  taken  as  indicating  degree  of  conditioning.  It 
is  rather  difficult,  however,  to  measure  the  presumed  autonomic 
components  of  fear  in  rats  because  of  the  animals'  small  size  and 
because  of  their  tendency  to  struggle  violently  against  restraint. 
But  since  the  laboratory  rat  is  a  convenient  subject,  investigators 
desiring  to  use  rats  have  found  it  necessary  to  develop  other  tech- 
niques for  estimating  strength  of  conditioning  in  these  subjects. 
Specificalh ,  it  has  become  common  in  recent  years  to  estimate  the 
presence  and  strength  of  conditioned  fear  from  observations  of 


146  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

the  manner  in  which  some  other  reaction  of  known  strength  is 
modified  by  the  presentation  or  by  the  termination  of  a  CS  that 
has  been  paired  with  a  noxious  UCS.  The  response  that  serves  as 
the  indicator  may  or  may  not  be  one  that  a  naive  observer  would 
describe  as  "fearful."  Reactions  such  as  eating,  drinking,  bar  press- 
ing, urinating,  defecating,  jumping,  turning  a  wheel,  and  crossing 
a  hurdle  have  all  been  used  as  indicants  of  conditioned  fear. 

Studies  of  fear  in  which  the  more  indirect  methods  are  used 
may  be  divided  into  three  broad  groups  according  to  the  ways  in 
which  the  CS  is  presented  and  the  indicator  response  is  affected. 
The  experiments  in  one  group,  which  are  consistent  with  the  con- 
cept of  fear  as  an  energizer,  show  that  the  reference  response,  if 
elicited  while  the  CS  is  on,  tends  to  be  enhanced  or  augmented. 
Moreover,  since  degree  of  enhancement  of  the  reference  response, 
which  is  itself  never  conditioned  to  the  CS,  tends  to  increase  with 
the  number  of  CS-UCS  pairings  and  to  decrease  during  extinction 
trials,  it  is  reasonable  to  suppose  that  the  changes  in  the  indicant 
reaction  reflect  strength  of  conditioning. 

A  second  group  of  experiments  consists  of  those  in  which,  fol- 
lowing fear-conditioning  trials,  tests  are  made  to  determine  whether 
the  probability,  speed,  or  amplitude  of  an  indicant  reaction  in- 
creases over  a  series  of  trials  on  each  of  which  an  ongoing  CS  is 
terminated  immediately  after  the  response  is  evoked.  When  learn- 
ing of  the  reference  response  is  demonstrated  under  these  condi- 
tions, it  is  clear  that  the  termination  of  the  CS  is  reinforcing,  and 
this  event  thus  meets  one  of  our  suggested  criteria  for  identifying 
motivational  variables  (cf.  Chapter  2).  And  since  the  reinforcing 
power  of  CS-offset  varies  with  the  number  of  CS-UCS  pairings,  an 
associative  variable,  the  conditions  for  an  acquired  source  of  drive 
have  been  met.  Usually  the  further  assumption  is  made  that  the 
CS  arouses  fear  and  that  it  is  the  reduction  in  fear  due  to  the 
termination  of  the  CS  that  functions  as  the  reinforcing  agent. 

In  a  third  group  of  investigations,  it  has  been  found  that  the 
presentation  of  a  CS  that  has  been  paired  with  a  noxious  UCS 
may  inhibit  or  interfere  with  an  ongoing  overt  response  or  response 
sequence.  By  the  proper  choice  of  conditioning  and  testing  meth- 
ods it  can  be  shown  that  the  degree  of  interference  suffered  by  the 
indicant  response  increases  as  a  function  of  the  number  of  CS- 


LEARNED   RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF   DRIVE  147 

UCS  pairings,  and  that  the  reference  reaction  tends  to  regain  its 
initial  strength  with  repeated  presentations  of  the  CS  alone  as  in 
the  customary  extinction  procedure.  If  the  reference  response  that 
is  being  weakened  is  followed  by  the  onset  of  the  CS,  the  condi- 
tions and  the  resulting  effect  meet  one  of  the  criteria  for  the  iden- 
tification of  motivational  variables.  And  since  this  effect  also 
varies  with  associative  variables  governing  acquisition  and  extinc- 
tion, the  picture  is  consistent  with  our  general  conception  of  an 
acquired  source  of  drive.  Where  the  time  relations  of  response  to 
stimulus  onset  differ  from  those  mentioned  here,  however,  the 
inhibitory  effects  can  perhaps  be  attributed  to  response-produced 
stimuli  and/or  to  CS-induced  changes  in  the  response  hierarchy. 
We  shall  return  to  this  problem  at  a  later  point  in  this  chapter. 

We  turn  now  to  an  examination  of  some  typical  experimental 
studies  from  each  of  the  three  groups  we  have  just  described. 

Studies  of  the  Energizing  Function  of  Fear.  Although  fear,  at 
times,  may  serve  as  a  debilitating  deterrent  to  action,  ample  evi- 
dence from  daily  experience  indicates  that  it  often  functions  as  a 
potent  goad  to  action.  The  reader  has  but  to  recall  the  frequency 
with  which  frightened  persons  in  stories,  movies,  and  plays  are 
depicted  as  capable  of  almost  superhuman  feats  of  climbing,  leap- 
ing, and  running,  to  realize  that  the  notion  of  fear  as  an  energizer 
is  exceptionally  widespread. 

Within  the  body  of  scientific  writing,  this  basic  notion  has  been 
strongly  supported  by  the  physiologist  Cannon  (1929),  whose 
studies  of  hunger  and  thirst  we  have  already  mentioned.  According 
to  Cannon,  fear  is  an  emergency  reaction  involving  the  mobiliza- 
tion of  energy  resources  of  the  body  and  their  effective  utilization 
in  expediting  whatever  responses  are  evoked  by  the  situation  at 
hand.  This  conception  has  been  widely  adopted  during  the  past 
two  decades,  and  it  is  only  quite  recently  that  the  soundness  of 
certain  of  its  elements  has  been  questioned.  Incidentally,  Can- 
non's views  as  to  the  dynamogenic  properties  of  fear  were  not 
based  upon  evidence  from  studies  of  behavior  at  the  molar  level, 
but  upon  the  biochemical  and  physiological  consequences  of  fear. 

Experimental  studies  by  psychologists  of  the  facilitating  conse- 
quences of  fear  are  of  relatively  recent  vintage.  Relevant  data, 
though  somewhat  peripheral  in  origin,  may  be  found  in  early 


148  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

studies  of  conflict  and  especially  in  supporting  experiments  on 
fear-motivated  avoidance  (cf.  Bugelski  and  Miller,  1938;  Brown, 
1948) .  In  these  studies  hungry  rats  were  first  trained  to  run  down  a 
short  straight  alley  for  food  reward.  They  were  then  given  electric 
shocks  of  various  intensities  at  the  goal  and  were  subsequently 
tested  without  shock,  when  satiated,  to  determine  how  vigorously 
they  would  avoid  the  region  where  they  had  been  shocked.  The 
results  indicated  that  the  speed  and  vigor  of  the  avoidance  re- 
sponses on  test  trials  increased  with  strength  of  shock  used  during 
training.  Since  shock  was  omitted  on  test  trials,  it  may  be  presumed 
that  the  avoidance  was  motivated  by  a  learned  tendency  to  be 
fearful,  which  should  vary  with  intensity  of  shock  and  with  other 
factors  such  as  nearness  to  the  point  in  the  alley  where  the  shocks 
had  been  administered. 

A  direct  attempt  to  determine  whether  an  alleged  fear-arousing 
CS  can  intensify  an  overt  skeletal  response  has  been  described  by 
Brown,  Kalish,  and  Farber  (1951).  From  the  assumption  that  fear 
as  a  learned  source  of  drive  should  multiply  existing  reactive  tend- 
encies, and  from  clinical  observations  that  anxious  persons  show 
exaggerated  startle  responses,  these  investigators  reasoned  that 
during  the  presentation  of  a  CS  that  had  been  paired  with  shock, 
rats  should  exhibit  intensified  startle  reactions  to  loud  sounds.  Ac- 
cordingly, an  experimental  procedure  was  arranged  with  the  aims 
of  producing  increasing  fear  during  the  course  of  fear-conditioning 
trials  (i.e.,  CS-UCS  pairings)  and  decreasing  fear  during  extinc- 
tion trials,  and  of  providing  an  opportunity  for  fear  to  show  spon- 
taneous recovery  during  rest  periods  following  extinction  periods. 
Measurements  were  made  at  intervals  throughout  conditioning 
and  extinction  to  determine  whether  the  amplitude  of  the  startle 
reaction  varied  concomitantly  with  the  assumed  variations  in 
fear. 

The  apparatus  used  in  this  study  was  a  stabilimeter,  by  means 
of  which  accurate  graphic  records  of  a  rat's  bodily  jumps  to  a  loud 
sound  could  be  obtained.  A  drawing  of  this  device  is  reproduced 
in  Fig.  5:2.  While  confined  in  the  rectangular  box,  the  subjects 
could  be  presented  with  visual  or  auditory  stimuli  and  mildly 
painful  electric  shocks.  The  fear-conditioning  procedure  involved 
seven  paired  presentations  of  a  CS  (consisting  of  a  buzzer  and  a 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE 


Confinement  box 


149 


Polygraph 


Fig.  5:2.  Schematic  drawing  of  stabilimeter  used  to  measure  the  ampHtude 
of  rats'  startle  responses  to  loud  sounds.  {Adapted  from  Brown,  Kalish,  and 
Farber,19Sl.) 


light)  and  a  UCS  (electric  shock)  on  each  of  four  successive  days. 
Three  test  trials  were  also  given  per  day,  interspersed  among  the 
seven  fear-conditioning  trials.  On  each  test  trial  the  CS  was  pre- 
sented, but  in  place  of  shock  a  toy  pistol  was  shot  off  to  produce 
a  loud,  sharp  sound.  The  sound  of  this  pistol  almost  invariably 
elicited  a  definite  startle  response  from  the  rats,  even  prior  to 
training  of  any  kind.  No  shocks  were  ever  presented  on  test  trials. 
The  members  of  one  group  of  experimental  subjects  were  condi- 
tioned and  tested  in  this  manner.  The  members  of  a  control  group 
were  tested  in  the  same  manner,  but  the  temporal  spacing  of  the 
CS  and  UCS  during  their  training  trials  was  designed  to  minimize 
or  prevent  the  conditioning  of  fear  to  the  CS. 

The  results  obtained  from  tests  interspersed  among  the  condi- 
tioning trials  are  summarized  in  Fig.  5:3.  The  curves  shbw  how 
the  animals  of  the  two  groups  responded  to  the  sound  of  the  pistol 
shot  on  successive  days.  The  plotted  points  are  medians  of  15 
values,  each  of  which  is  a  mean  of  three  responses.  The  values 
plotted  at  the  zero  point  on  the  abscissa  were  derived  from  prelimi- 


150 


THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 
25 


E 
E 
.E  20 

a> 
ir> 
c 
o 

Q. 
in 

03 
V 

r  15 

to 

ro 
"•a 
<u 

10 
0 


12  3  4 

Successive  days  of  training 

Fig.  5:3.  Median  amplitude  of  startle  responses  of  fearful  and  nonfearful  rats 
to  a  loud,  sharp  sound.  The  upper  curve  shows  that  experimental  animals 
presumed  to  be  fearful  jumped  more  and  more  vigorously  to  the  sound  as 
the  number  of  fear-conditioning  trials  increased.  The  responses  of  control 
(nonfearful)  subjects,  however,  did  not  change  progressively  or  significantly 
during  the  same  period.   {From  Brown,  Kalish,  and  Farber,  1951.) 

nary  measurements  of  startle-response  amplitude  on  the  day  prior 
to  the  start  of  training.  These  data  were  used  to  equate  the  mem- 
bers of  the  two  groups  with  respect  to  their  inherent  reactiveness 
to  the  sound  of  the  pistol. 

An  examination  of  Fig.  5:3  shows  that  the  magnitude  of  the 
startle  responses  evoked  by  the  pistol  shot  in  the  presence  of  the 
CS  increased  progressively  during  the  course  of  conditioning  for 
the  experimental  animals  but  not  for  the  controls. 

The  intervals  between  the  CS  and  UCS  and  their  orders  of 
presentation  were  chosen,  of  course,  so  as  to  maximize  conditioned 
fear  in  the  experimental  animals  while  minimizing  it  in  the  con- 
trols. It  seems  reasonable  to  conclude,  therefore,  that  the  CS 
elicited  more  fear  in  the  experimentals  than  in  the  controls  and 
that  fear  functioned  as  a  drive  to  augment  unlearned  startle  re- 
sponses. Stated  in  other  terms,  this  portion  of  the  experiment 
provided  evidence  for  an  acquired  source  of  drive,  since  an  associa- 
tive variable  (number  of  conditioning  trials)  functioned  as  though 


LEARNED   RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF   DRIVE 


151 


it  were  a  motivational  variable  in  its  effects  upon  a  reference 
response  which  was  itself  not  conditioned. 

On  three  successive  days  following  the  period  of  fear  condition- 
ing, the  animals  of  both  groups  were  placed  in  the  stabilimeter 
and  were  given  12  nonreinforced  test  trials.  On  each  trial  the  CS 
was  presented  and  the  pistol  was  shot  off,  but  the  shock  was 
omitted.  Since  these  trials  would  qualify  as  fear-extinction  trials, 
it  was  anticipated  that  fear  would  be  weakened  and  startle-response 
amplitude  would  decline.  The  curves  for  day  1  in  Fig.  5:4  confirm 
this  expectation,  since  the  startle  responses  of  the  experimental  ani- 
mals were  relatively  large  at  the  beginning  of  the  day,  but  dimin- 
ished progressively  with  successive  nonshock  trials.  By  way  of  con- 
trast, the  control  (nonf earful)  rats  started  at  a  much  lower  level 
and  showed  a  much  smaller  decline  during  the  shot-only  trials.  As 
can  be  seen  from  the  curves  for  day  2,  the  startle  responses  of  the 


12  3  4        5  6  7  8 

Successive  blocks  of  three  nonreinforced  trials 

Fig.  5:4.  These  curves  show  the  marked  dedine  in  startle-response  amphtude 
exhibited  by  fearful  (experimental)  animals  when  a  presumed  fear-arousing 
CS  is  repeatedly  presented  without  shock.  The  smaller  decrease  in  response 
amplitude  shown  by  the  nonfearful  control  subjects  appears  to  be  the  result 
of  adaptation.  The  rise  of  the  solid  curve  at  the  start  of  further  extinction 
trials  on  day  2  may  be  due  to  the  spontaneous  recovery  of  fear  in  the  interval 
between  the  two  tests.  {From  Brown,  Kalish,  and  Farber,  1951.) 


N.                  Day  1 

^ 

Day  2 

'^                         \ 
\                      V 

• •  Experimental  group  iV  =  15 

\ 
\ 
\ 

\ 

V 

/ 
/ 

/ 
/ 

^ 

o  — -o  Control  group  A^=15 

1                   1                   1                   1 

1               1 

I 

152  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

experimental  rats  showed  a  spontaneous  increase  in  strength  fol- 
lowing a  day's  rest.  This  phenomenon  is  clearly  consistent  with 
expectations  from  the  laws  of  classical  conditioning.  If  fear  were 
undergoing  extinction  during  the  12  nonshock  trials  of  day  1,  we 
should  expect  a  period  of  rest  to  lead  to  some  increase  in  its 
strength.  And  if  fear  serves  as  a  source  of  drive  to  enhance  startle 
reactions,  a  resurgence  in  the  strength  of  the  partially  extinguished 
fear  should  be  reflected  by  a  rise  in  startle-response  amplitude,  as 
was  indeed  the  case.  Further  support  for  the  belief  that  fear  is 
weakened  by  trials  without  shock  is  provided  by  the  progressive 
fall  of  the  solid  curve  during  the  nonreinforced  trials  of  day  2. 
Additional  test  trials  given  on  day  3  showed  no  further  systematic 
effects,  and  they  have  been  omitted  from  Fig.  5:4. 

Another  study  supporting  the  view  that  conditioned  fear  may 
serve  as  a  learned  source  of  drive  is  that  conducted  by  Meryman 
(1952).  This  experiment  represents  an  important  confirmation  and 
extension  of  the  investigation  of  Brown,  Kalish,  and  Farber. 
Meryman  was  concerned  with  the  problem  of  whether  a  primary 
source  of  drive,  such  as  food  deprivation,  would  intensify  sound- 
induced  startle  responses  in  rats  and  whether  hunger  and  condi- 
tioned fear  together  would  produce  greater  augmentation  of  startle 
than  either  alone. 

Meryman's  apparatus  was,  in  principle,  the  same  as  that  used  by 
Brown,  Kalish,  and  Farber.  His  rats  were  given  fear-conditioning 
trials  and  startle  trials  in  a  cylindrical,  plastic-walled  cage  having 
a  grid  floor.  The  cage  was  mounted  on  the  end  of  a  pivoted  alu- 
minum lever  arm  and  any  slight  movements  or  startle  responses  of 
the  rats  could  be  recorded  on  a  polygraph. 

Meryman's  design  called  for  four  groups  of  animals.  The  animals 
in  group  F-46  were  motivated  both  by  CS-aroused  fear  and  by  46 
hours  of  food  deprivation  at  the  time  of  their  tests;  group  F-1  was 
fearful  but  had  been  satiated  one  hour  prior  to  the  tests;  group 
NF-46  was  not  fearful  but  hadn't  eaten  for  46  hours;  and  group 
NF-1  was  not  fearful  and  had  been  satiated  one  hour  previously. 

Following  some  initial  adaptation  trials  to  the  sound  of  the  pistol 
shot  alone,  all  animals  were  given  three  trials  at  20-minute  intervals 
in  the  stabilimeter  each  day  for  ten  days.  On  each  of  the  first  two 
trials  the  animals  were  individually  placed  in  the  cage  and  the 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE 


153 


amplitudes  of  their  startle  responses  to  the  sound  of  the  toy  pistol 
were  recorded.  On  the  third  trial  of  each  day,  the  procedure  of  the 
first  two  trials  was  repeated  for  the  fearful  groups  (F-46  and  F-1), 
save  that  a  brief  electric  shock  was  substituted  for  the  sound  of  the 
shot.  This  was  calculated  to  produce  an  association  between  fear 
and  the  tactual,  visual,  and  olfactory  cues  provided  by  the  sta- 
bilimeter  cage.  These  environmental  cues,  rather  than  a  buzzer  or 
light,  served  as  the  CS  in  this  experiment.  Thus  the  first  two  daily 
trials  provided  measurements  of  startle  responses  as  modified  by 
conditioned  fear  due  to  shocks  received  on  the  previous  day  or 
days.  The  animals  in  the  nonf earful  groups  (NF-46  and  NF-1) 
were  also  given  two  shot-only  trials  at  the  start  of  each  day  but 
were  not  shocked  when  placed  in  the  stabilimeter  for  their  third 
daily  trial. 

The  results  of  Meryman's  experiment  are  reproduced  in  Fig.  5:5. 
The  values  plotted  in  this  graph  are  means,  based  upon  the  two 
daily  startle  responses  to  the  shot  for  each  of  eight  animals  in  each 
group.  Inspection  of  the  curves  reveals  that  on  the  first  day,  be- 
fore any  of  the  animals  had  had  any  shocks  in  the  apparatus,  all 
four  groups  were  about  equal  in  their  reactions  to  the  shot.  How- 


24 


20 


B  16 


12 


«    8 


Fearful -46  hours - 
hungry 


Nonfearful-1  hour  hungry 
9-  — -9- 9 K?-- 


3         4  5         6  7         8         9 

Successive  blocks  of  two  daily  test  trials 


10 


Fig.   5:5.  Startle-response  amplitude  as  a  function  of  fear,  no  fear,  intense 
hunger,  weak  hunger,  and  their  combinations.  {From  Meryman,  1952.) 


154  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

ever,  during  the  course  of  the  ten  days  of  training  and  testing,  the 
responses  of  the  two  shocked  groups  (F-46  and  F-1)  exhibited  a 
marked  increase  over  their  initial  level.  The  responses  of  the  fear- 
ful-nonhungry  group  (F-1)  showed  a  considerable  increase  in  am- 
plitude when  compared  with  those  of  the  nonfearful-nonhungry 
group  (NF-1),  and  the  fearful-hungry  animals  (F-46)  exhibited  an 
even  more  marked  rise  in  their  responses  relative  to  the  nonfearful- 
hungry  (NF-46)  rats.  These  results  clearly  support  our  conception 
of  an  acquired  source  of  drive,  since  an  associative  variable  {CS- 
UCS  presentations)  affected  the  startle  response  as  if  a  motiva- 
tional variable  had  been  introduced. 

Two  other  findings  by  Meryman  are  of  interest.  First,  the  startle 
responses  of  the  NF-46  group  were  significantly  greater  than  those 
of  the  NF-1  group.  This  is  important  because  it  adds  another  re- 
sponse to  the  list  of  those  that  are  facilitated  by  food  deprivation, 
and  because,  to  a  degree,  it  allays  the  suspicion  that  startle,  because 
of  some  unique  relationship  to  fear,  can  be  facilitated  only  by 
fear.  Nevertheless,  as  the  two  middle  curves  show,  fear,  either  be- 
cause it  is  strong  or  because  it  is  innately  associated  with  startle,  is 
far  more  effective  than  intense  hunger  in  enhancing  startle.  Sec- 
ond, a  comparison  of  the  upper  three  curves  reveals  that  fear  and 
hunger,  when  simultaneously  present,  are  more  potent  than  either 
one  alone.  Precisely  what  the  mechanism  is  by  which  these  two 
act  in  concert  as  facilitators  is  not  clear.  Conceivably,  when  hunger 
and  fear  are  combined  the  result  is  simply  an  increase  in  level  of 
general  drive,  multiplying  the  unlearned  startle  tendency.  Or 
hunger  might  function  somewhat  less  directly  by  augmenting  fear 
and  hence  its  capacity  to  affect  startle. 

In  a  subsequent  study,  Meryman  (1953)  has  shown  that  the 
amplitude  of  the  galvanic  skin  response  {GSR)  to  a  weak  auditory 
click  is  enhanced  by  conditioned  fear  in  human  subjects.  Fear 
was  presumably  established  by  pairing  a  brief  auditory  cue  (a  hiss- 
ing noise)  with  a  mildly  painful  shock,  an  interval  of  20  seconds 
separating  the  two  stimuli.  Because  of  this  long  interval,  almost 
no  conditioned  GSRs  were  evoked  by  the  CS  even  after  a  good 
many  trials.  But  on  the  occasional  test  trials,  when  a  click  replaced 
the  shock,  the  amplitude  of  the  GSR  to  the  test  click  showed  a 
marked  and  significant  increase  throughout  the  course  of  condi- 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  155 

tioning.  Since  the  click  was  never  paired  with  shock,  it  cannot  be 
argued  that  the  cHck  was  itself  becoming  a  conditioned  stimulus 
for  fear.  Meryman  concluded,  therefore,  that  the  noise  had  become 
a  conditioned  signal  for  fear,  in  spite  of  the  long  interval  between 
noise  and  shock,  and  that  fear  intensified  the  unlearned  tendency 
to  respond  to  the  weak  click. 

In  addition  to  these  experiments  in  which  the  dynamogenic 
effects  of  fear  upon  both  startle  and  the  GSR  have  been  rather 
clearly  demonstrated,  there  are  several  other  studies  that  provide 
less  direct  support  for  the  energizing  conception  of  fear.  Hunt 
and  Otis  (1953),  for  example,  report  that  defecation  in  rats,  dur- 
ing the  presentation  of  a  fear-arousing  conditioned  stimulus,  in- 
creases progressively  during  conditioning  and  declines  during  ex- 
tinction. They  interpret  this  finding  to  mean  that  the  CS  ac- 
quired the  power  to  "ehcit"  defecation  as  one  component  of  the 
general  emotional  response.  Alternatively,  one  might  suppose  that 
this  is  not  an  associative  phenomenon  but  a  consequence  of  the 
intensifying  effect  of  fear-produced  drive  upon  the  defecation  re- 
sponse when  it  is  evoked  in  the  emotional  situation.  This  view  is 
complicated,  however,  by  the  fact  that  another  response,  that  of 
bar  pressing,  which  was  also  elicited  in  the  situation,  tended  to 
decrease  as  fear  increased.  Amsel  (1950Z))  has  also  observed  that 
during  a  period  when  rats  are  recovering  from  the  emotional  after- 
effects of  shock,  defecation  starts  at  a  high  level  and  declines, 
whereas  drinking,  which  is  initially  inhibited,  is  gradually  resumed. 
Thus  fear  can  apparently  facilitate  one  response  and  inhibit  an- 
other at  the  same  moment.  Later  on  in  this  chapter  we  shall  con- 
sider the  implications  of  this  seeming  paradox. 

Some  investigators  have  applied  the  term  fear  to  the  general 
state  of  emotional  excitement  following  the  administration  of  elec- 
tric shock,  as  well  as  to  the  conditioned  emotionality  aroused  by  a 
CS  in  anticipation  of  impending  trauma.  A  distinction  should  prob- 
ably be  made,  however,  between  these  two  presumed  types  of  emo- 
tionality since  their  antecedent  conditions,  at  least,  are  quite 
unlike.  In  particular,  it  is  evident  that  postshock  emotionality 
does  not  qualify  as  an  acquired  source  of  drive  since  a  demonstra- 
tion of  its  behavioral  effects  does  not  involve  the  manipulation  of 
associative  variables.  Residual  emotionality  appears,  however,  to 


156  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

have  drivelike  energizing  effects  under  certain  conditions.  Amsel 
and  Maltzman  (1950),  for  example,  found  that  the  consummatory 
response  of  drinking  was  enhanced  following  shock,  provided  the 
shocks  were  administered  in  a  different  situation  from  the  one 
in  which  the  rats  were  accustomed  to  drink.  In  a  similarly  designed 
study,  Siegel  and  Brantley  (1951)  observed  that  if  hungry  rats 
were  shocked  in  a  separate  place  from  where  they  were  usually 
fed,  eating  was  facilitated.  In  both  of  these  studies,  the  conclu- 
sion was  reached  that  postshock  emotionality  served  as  a  source  of 
general  drive  to  intensify  whatever  reaction  was  dominant  in  the 
testing  situation.  Evidence  contrary  to  this  conclusion  has  been 
obtained,  however,  by  Kabrick  and  Farber  (1952),  who  report  that 
postshock  reaction  times  are  lengthened  in  human  subjects,  and 
by  Brown,  Meryman,  and  Marzocco  (1956),  who  find  that  ampli- 
tude of  startle  response  in  rats  is  diminished  immediately  after 
shock.  These  negative  findings  may  be  due  to  the  elicitation  by 
shock  of  competing  responses,  but  further  research  is  clearly 
needed  to  determine  the  range  of  conditions  under  which  facili- 
tation and/or  interference  can  be  obtained. 

Studies  of  the  Reinforcing  Effect  of  Fear  Reduction.  All  of  the 
experiments  in  this  group  show  that  when  a  CS  has  been  paired 
with  a  noxious  UCS,  terminating  the  CS  after  the  evocation  of  a 
new  response  serves  to  reinforce  the  learning  of  that  response. 
Since  the  capacity  to  function  as  a  reinforcer  is  one  of  our  sug- 
gested criteria  for  identifying  motivational  variables,  and  since 
this  capacity  varies  in  these  studies  with  CS-UCS  pairings  (an 
associative  variable)  the  operation  of  an  acquired  source  of  drive 
is  strongly  indicated. 

The  best-known  experiment  of  this  group  (Miller,  1948cz)  has 
been  quite  influential  in  establishing  the  view  that  fear  functions 
as  a  learned  source  of  drive.  The  basic  apparatus  used  by  Miller 
was  a  rectangular  box  divided  by  a  vertically  sliding  door  into  two 
separate  compartments.  One  of  these  was  painted  white  and  had 
a  grid  floor,  the  other  was  black  with  a  smooth  floor.  Twenty-five 
rats  were  given  a  series  of  preliminary  training  trials  on  which  they 
were  taught  to  escape  electric  shock  in  the  white  side  by  running 
through  the  open  door  into  the  black  compartment.  This  training 
was  also  designed  to  produce  a  strong  association  between  fear  and 


LEARNED   RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF   DRIVE  157 

the  visual  and  tactual  cues  of  the  white  box.  During  subsequent 
learning  trials,  the  door  was  closed,  but  it  would  open  automati- 
cally if  a  rat  rotated  a  small  wheel  located  directly  above  it.  To 
determine  whether  reduction  of  the  fear  conditioned  to  the  white 
box  {CS)  during  the  shock-escape  trials  would  actually  be  rein- 
forcing, Miller  placed  his  rats  in  the  white  compartment  without 
shock.  Since  the  door  was  closed,  they  were  faced  with  the  task 
of  learning  to  rotate  the  wheel  in  order  to  be  released  from  the 
white  box.  The  conditions  were  such  that  if  an  animal  made  the 
new  wheel-turning  response  within  100  seconds,  the  door  dropped, 
and  the  fear  aroused  by  the  white-box  cues  could  be  reduced  by 
escaping  into  the  black  section.  If  the  wheel-turning  response  was 
not  made  within  this  period,  the  animal  was  removed  from  the 
apparatus  to  await  another  trial. 

The  results  obtained  on  the  nonshock  trials  showed  that  if  a  rat 
succeeded  in  turning  the  wheel  a  number  of  times  during  the  early 
part  of  the  series,  the  new  response  was  rapidly  learned.  According 
to  Miller,  escape  from  the  fear-eliciting  white-box  cues  served  to 
reinforce  wheel  turning  and  to  bring  about  a  marked  increase  in 
the  speed  with  which  the  act  occurred.  Actually  12  of  the  25  rats 
did  not  turn  the  wheel  often  enough  at  first,  and  with  repeated 
nonshock  trials  in  the  white  side,  their  conditioned  fear  was  extin- 
guished before  they  could  learn  the  new  response.  The  13  rats 
that  did  learn,  however,  also  learned  a  second  new  response  with- 
out any  further  shock  trials.  After  wheel  turning  had  been  learned, 
the  door  was  closed  and  the  controlling  circuits  arranged  so  that  a 
small  metal  rod  had  to  be  depressed  to  operate  the  door-release 
mechanism.  During  further  trials  with  this  arrangement,  the  rats 
gave  up  their  earlier  response  of  wheel  turning,  since  it  was  no 
longer  effective  in  leading  to  fear  reduction,  and  acquired  the 
response  of  depressing  the  bar.  Shock  was  never  administered  on 
the  learning  trials,  and  Miller  concluded,  therefore,  that  fear  was 
aroused  by  the  white-box  cues  and  that  the  elimination  of  those 
cues  following  escape  into  the  black  compartment  led  to  a  reduc- 
tion of  fear,  which  reinforced  wheel  turning  and  bar  pressing. 

Using  Miller's  study  as  their  point  of  departure,  Brown  and 
Jacobs  (1949)  performed  an  experiment  which  provided  further 
support  for  Miller's  interpretation.  From  an  analysis  of  Miller's 


158  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

study,  these  experimenters  reasoned  that  some  other  kind  of  rein- 
forcement might  have  been  operating  in  addition  to,  or  instead  of, 
fear  reduction.  Specifically,  during  the  initial  training  phase  of 
Miller's  experiment,  the  animals  had  received  a  number  of  shock- 
motivated  trials  in  escaping  from  the  white  box  to  the  black  box. 
Quite  conceivably,  therefore,  during  the  subsequent  learning  trials 
the  animals  may  have  been  frustrated  when  prevented  by  the 
closed  door  from  further  escape.  If  so,  the  anger  or  frustration 
produced  by  interference  with  escape  could  have  served  as  a  drive, 
and  its  reduction,  following  wheel  turning  and  escape,  could  have 
been  reinforcing. 

Following  this  line  of  thought,  Brown  and  Jacobs  designed  their 
study  so  that  no  escape  responses  were  permitted  or  rewarded  dur- 
ing the  initial  fear-conditioning  trials.  These  trials  were  ad- 
ministered alternately  in  each  section  of  a  black-walled,  two-com- 
partment box.  Each  fear-conditioning  trial  consisted  of  the  paired 
presentation  of  a  compound  CS  (interrupted  tone  plus  blinking 
light)  and  a  pulsating  electric  shock  (UCS).  The  animals  could 
not  jump  from  one  side  of  the  box  to  the  other  on  these  trials,  and 
the  durations  of  the  CS  and  the  UCS,  as  well  as  the  interval  be- 
tween them,  were  completely  independent  of  the  animals'  activi- 
ties. In  all,  22  trials  of  this  kind  were  given,  10  on  each  of  the 
first  two  days,  and  2  at  the  start  of  the  third  day.  Half  of  the  trials 
were  given  in  each  side  of  the  box  so  that  fear,  if  it  became  con- 
ditioned to  the  cues  provided  by  the  apparatus,  would  be  equal  on 
both  sides. 

Tests  for  the  reinforcing  effects  of  fear  reduction  were  conducted 
by  putting  the  animals  into  one  side  of  the  box  and  turning  on  the 
compound  CS.  At  the  same  time,  a  guillotine  door  in  the  partition 
separating  the  two  compartments  was  lifted  and  the  animals  were 
permitted  to  jump  over  a  low  hurdle  into  the  opposite  compart- 
ment. If  they  made  this  new  response  within  60  seconds,  the  door 
was  closed  behind  them  and  the  CS  was  turned  off.  No  shocks 
were  ever  administered  on  these  trials.  It  was  anticipated  that  if 
the  CS  aroused  fear,  its  cessation  following  the  hurdle-jumping  re- 
sponse would  be  rewarding  and  the  performance  of  that  response 
would  improve.  Animals  not  shocked  during  the  initial  trials 
served  as  controls. 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE 


159 


The  time  taken  by  an  animal  to  jump  over  the  hurdle  after  the 
door  was  opened  provided  the  necessary  performance  data.  In- 
dividual trial  latencies  were  transformed  into  logarithms  to  nor- 
mahze  the  distributions  for  statistical  analyses,  and  the  resulting 
means  were  plotted  as  in  Fig.  5:6.  In  this  figure  the  solid  line 
shows  that  the  hurdle-jumping  latencies  of  the  experimental  (fear- 
ful) rats  decreased  progressively  during  the  first  20  trials  of  hurdle 
jumping.  The  significant  drop  in  these  latencies  suggests  that  the 
barrier-crossing  responses  of  these  rats  were  being  reinforced  by  the 
cessation  of  the  CS.  The  performance  of  the  control-group  animals 
contrasts  sharply  with  that  of  the  experimental  rats.  Whereas  both 
groups  crossed  the  hurdle  with  about  the  same  latencies  at  first, 
the  controls  showed  no  tendency  to  improve  their  level  of  perform- 
ance with  additional  trials.  In  fact,  a  statistical  comparison  of  the 
first  and  last  points  of  the  dashed-line  curve  indicated  that  the 
performance  of  the  control  animals  became  significantly  worse 
over  the  40  trials.  It  was  concluded  from  this  study,  therefore,  that/ 
fear  was  developed  in  the  experimental  animals  during  the  initial 


2.5 


2.0- 


£  1.5 


1.0 
0 


<^--' 

^            ■ — 

--'"( 

\ 

V 

^Control  group 

- 

\ 

\ 

1 

,  Experimental  group 

1 

1 

N 

1   . . 

1               I               1 

3  4  5  6 

Blocks  of  five  trials 


Fig.  5:6.  Hurdle-jumping  latencies  for  fearful  and  nonfearful  rats  (N  =  8 
per  group)  as  a  function  of  trials.  The  animals  of  the  fearful  (experimental) 
group  show  a  marked  decrease  in  latency  (improvement  in  performance) 
during  the  first  20  trials,  whereas  the  controls  do  not.  The  only  reinforce- 
ment was  that  provided  by  the  cessation  of  fear-arousing  cues  following  the 
response.  {From  Brown  and  Jacobs,  J 949.) 


160  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

conditioning  trials  even  though  escape  responses  were  neither 
permitted  nor  reinforced,  and  that  the  reduction  of  fear,  following 
the  cessation  of  the  CS  when  the  response  occurred,  functioned  to 
strengthen  the  tendency  to  perform  that  response. 

Kahsh  (1954),  using  procedures  patterned  after  those  of  the 
Brown-Jacobs  experiment,  has  carried  out  the  most  complete  study 
of  the  effects  on  fear  of  varying  numbers  of  acquisition  and  ex- 
tinction trials.  Previous  experiments  by  Miller  and  Lawrence 
(1950)  and  by  Gwinn  (1951)  had  yielded  somewhat  obscure  data 
concerning  fear  as  a  function  of  the  number  of  shock-reinforced 
trials. 

In  his  study  Kalish  used  four  principal  groups  of  animals  that 
were  given  1,  3,  9,  and  27  fear-acquisition  trials,  respectively,  in  a 
small,  grid-floored,  gray  box.  Each  trial  involved  the  presentation 
of  a  buzzer  plus  a  blinking  light  {CS)  for  five  seconds,  with  a  one- 
second  pulsating  shock  (UCS)  being  turned  on  during  the  last 
second  of  the  CS.  As  in  the  Brown-Jacobs  experiment,  these  ac- 
quisition trials  were  uncomplicated  by  the  learning  of  escape  or 
avoidance  responses.  Each  of  the  four  basic  groups  was  divided 
into  four  subgroups.  These  were  given  0,  3,  9,  and  27  extinction 
trials  {CS  presented  alone),  respectively,  following  the  initial 
conditioning  trials.  Immediately  after  extinction,  the  16  groups 
were  given  a  chance  to  learn  a  hurdle-jumping  response  with  the 
CS-cessation  providing  the  only  reinforcement.  Because  of  these 
procedures,  the  16  groups  should  have  differed,  at  the  time  the 
hurdle-jumping  trials  began,  with  respect  to  the  amount  of  fear 
remaining  after  varying  numbers  of  fear-acquisition  and  fear-extinc- 
tion trials.  Differences  in  proficiency  in  learning  the  hurdle-jump- 
ing response  would  be  expected  to  reflect  these  differences  in 
residual  fear. 

When  the  hurdle-jumping  latencies  for  the  16  groups  are  com- 
bined according  to  the  original  number  of  fear-conditioning  trials, 
irrespective  of  number  of  extinction  trials,  and  are  plotted  against 
the  trials,  the  four  curves  of  Fig.  5:7  are  obtained.  Here  we  see  that 
the  group  given  the  maximum  number  of  fear-conditioning  trials, 
i.e.,  27,  shows  the  greatest  decrease  in  latency  as  a  consequence  of 
the  reinforcement  provided  by  the  termination  of  the  CS.  As  the 
number  of  conditioning  trials  decreases  to  9,  3,  and  1,  the  degree 


LEARNED   RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF   DRIVE 


161 


1  2  3 

Blocks  of  three  learning  trials 

Fig.  5:7.  Hurdle-jumping  latencies  on  successive  blocks  of  three  trials  during 
which  the  response  was  reinforced  by  the  cessation  of  an  alleged  fear-arousing 
CS.  Each  curve  was  obtained  by  pooling  the  data  from  four  subgroups  of 
eight  animals  given  differing  numbers  of  extinction  trials.  {From  Kalish, 
19S4.) 

of  learning  in  the  hurdle-jumping  tests  declines,  though  some 
learning  seems  to  have  resulted  from  only  a  single  fear-condition- 
ing trial.  Thus  fear  seems  to  be  acquired  very  quickly,  though  its 
strength  continues  to  rise  with  additional  reinforcements  up  to  at 
least  27  trials. 

When  the  data  from  Kalish's  experiment  are  regrouped  to  show 
the  effects  of  variations  in  number  of  fear-extinction  trials,  the 
curves  of  Fig.  5:8  are  obtained.  Here  again  the  findings  accord 
well  with  expectation,  since  animals  given  no  extinction  trials 
learn  most  rapidly,  and  learning  becomes  progressively  worse  as 
the  number  of  extinction  trials  is  increased. 

The  procedures  and  findings  of  Kalish's  study,  it  may  be  seen, 
are  consistent  with  the  concept  of  acquired  sources  of  drive  devel- 
oped at  the  start  of  this  chapter.  Thus,  number  of  acquisition 
trials  and  number  of  extinction  trials,  though  clearly  associative 
variables,  affect  the  hurdle-jumping  reference  response,  which  was 
not  elicited  while  these  variables  were  being  manipulated,  much  as 
we  might  expect  it  to  be  affected  by  a  motivational  variable. 

Concerning  data  such  as  these,  however,  it  must  be  remembered 
that  although  decreases  in  response  latency  provide  evidence  for 
the  presence  of  fear,  and  differences  among  such  decreases  indi- 


162 


THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 


1  2  3 

Blocks  of  three  learning  trials 

Fig.  5:8.  Hurdle-jumping  latencies  for  groups  differing  with  respect  to  number 
of  fear-extinction  trials.  The  data  from  four  subgroups  of  eight  animals  each, 
given  different  numbers  of  fear-acquisition  trials,  were  combined  to  form  each 
of  these  four  curves.  {From  Kalish,  1954.) 

cate  differences  in  degree  of  fear,  absolute  reaction  latencies  do  not 
reflect  strength  of  fear  in  any  direct  manner.  This  is  because  the 
hurdle-jumping  training  is  carried  out  in  the  absence  of  further 
shock  trials.  During  such  trials  fear  must  be  presumed  to  be  under- 
going extinction.  Thus  proficiency  in  the  performance  of  the  new 
response  may  be  increasing,  but  this  increase  is  occurring  while 
the  absolute  strength  of  fear  is  doubtless  declining. 

The  experiments  described  in  this  section  on  the  reinforcing 
effects  of  fear  reduction  may  be  taken  as  representative  of  typical 
research  in  the  area.  Other  studies  by  Miller  and  Lawrence  (1950), 
Gwinn  (1951),  and  Mowrer  and  Lamoreaux  (1942)  have  also 
provided  evidence  that  fear  reduction  is  reinforcing. 

Studies  of  the  Inhibitory  Effects  of  Fear.  We  have  seen  that  if  a 
reference  response  is  elicited  while  a  CS  for  fear  is  on,  enhance- 
ment of  the  response  may  be  observed.  Under  other  conditions, 
however,  especially  when  the  CS  is  presented  after  a  response  (or 
response  chain )  has  been  initiated,  activity  may  be  inhibited  rather 
than  augmented.  At  first  sight  this  negative  effect  seems  to  conflict 
with  the  notion  of  fear  as  a  motivator.  Nevertheless,  it  can  be  in- 
terpreted as  an  instance  of  an  acquired  source  of  drive,  if  one 
grants  that  the  inhibition  or  abandonment  of  responses  that  are 
followed  by  the  introduction  of  a  motivational  variable  is  a  legiti- 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  163 

mate  criterion  (Chapter  2)  for  the  identification  of  such  variables. 
On  this  basis,  evidence  for  an  acquired  source  of  drive  would  be 
provided  by  the  observation  that  as  the  number  of  fear-condition- 
ing trials  (associative  variable)  increases,  the  likelihood  that  re- 
sponses which  are  followed  by  the  CS  will  be  inhibited  (motiva- 
tional variable)  should  also  increase. 

One  of  the  first  experimental  demonstrations  of  inhibiting  ef- 
fects of  this  kind  has  been  reported  by  Estes  and  Skinner  (1941). 
In  their  experiment  rats  were  trained  initially  to  press  a  bar  to 
obtain  a  pellet  of  food.  By  presenting  pellets  at  fixed  intervals  of 
time  rather  than  after  every  response,  the  rats  were  taught  to  re- 
spond at  a  continuous  rate.  That  is,  they  would  depress  the  bar 
repeatedly  even  though  only  one  pellet  was  given  them  every 
four  minutes.  Subsequently,  fear  reactions  were  conditioned  (while 
the  animals  were  pressing  the  bar)  by  turning  on  a  tone  [CS)  for 
several  minutes  and  giving  the  rats  a  strong  shock  at  the  time  the 
tone  was  terminated.  At  first  the  rats  continued  to  respond  at 
their  usual  rate  while  the  tone  was  sounding,  but  as  the  number 
of  tone-shock  trials  increased,  the  onset  of  the  tone  produced  a 
more  immediate  and  more  nearly  complete  cessation  of  bar  press- 
ing. Animals  tested  under  low  hunger  drive  did  not  exhibit  this 
effect  to  as  marked  a  degree  as  did  others  tested  under  a  strong 
hunger  drive.  This  latter  finding  is  of  special  interest  since  it  is 
consistent  with  the  view  that  fear  may  be  intensified  by  the  pres- 
ence of  hunger.  This  possibility  was  suggested  above  in  connection 
with  Meryman's  startle-response  study. 

The  Estes-Skinner  technique  for  investigating  the  behavioral 
consequences  of  fear  has  proved  to  be  rather  generally  useful.  Hunt 
and  Brady  (1951 )  and  their  associates,  in  particular,  have  employed 
the  method  repeatedly  in  their  studies  of  the  effects  of  electrocon- 
vulsive shock  (ECS)  upon  fear.  Though  space  does  not  permit  a 
detailed  review  of  their  experiments  here,  these  investigators  have 
demonstrated  rather  clearly  that  the  immediate  aftereffects  of 
ECS  treatments  are  to  abolish  conditioned  fear.  Rats  given  ECS 
"therapy"  are  not  deterred  from  repetitive  bar  pressing  when  a 
stimulus  is  presented  that  was  formerly  followed  by  strong  shock. 

Amsel  (1950fo)  has  shown  that  conditioned  fear  inhibits  the 
consummatory  response  of  drinking  in  thirsty  rats,  provided  fear 


164  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

and  the  consummatory  act  have  been  associated  with  the  same 
cues.  In  his  experiment  rats  were  given  prehminary  training  in 
running  from  the  larger  of  two  similar  white  compartments  into 
the  smaller  to  drink  from  a  calibrated  water  container.  During  this 
training,  which  was  carried  on  for  24  days  under  a  constant  water- 
deprivation  regimen,  the  amount  of  water  consumed  during  a  five- 
minute  period  on  successive  trials  increased  in  a  smooth,  negatively 
accelerated  manner  until  a  stable  level  was  reached.  At  this  point 
the  animals  in  one  group  were  placed  in  the  larger  box  and  were 
given  two  shocks  per  day  for  four  days.  Control  animals  were 
also  put  into  the  larger  section  but  were  not  shocked.  Subse- 
quently, when  the  animals  of  both  groups  were  again  permitted 
to  run  to  water,  those  in  the  shocked  group  showed  a  sharp  drop 
in  water  consumption.  The  water  intake  of  the  no-shock  control 
group,  however,  did  not  change  following  the  four-day  no-drinking 
period.  During  additional  no-shock  test  periods,  the  shocked  ani- 
mals exhibited  a  gradual  increase  in  the  amount  of  water  drunk 
during  the  five-minute  period.  In  interpreting  his  findings,  Amsel 
assumed  that  fear  was  conditioned  (in  the  experimental  group)  to 
the  cues  of  the  larger  white  box  and  generalized  to  the  smaller 
white  compartment.  The  decrease  in  water  intake  of  these  animals 
on  the  postshock  trials  was  ascribed  to  the  presence  of  "anxiety- 
motivated"  competing  responses.  Thus  fear  did  not  facilitate 
drinking  because  its  presence  led  to  the  appearance  of  new  re- 
sponses which  interfered  with  drinking.  One  of  these  competing 
responses  may  have  been  emotional  defecation,  since,  as  we  have 
previously  noted,  the  frequency  of  defecation  by  the  fearful  ani- 
mals was  extremely  high  at  the  time  when  water  consumption  was 
low.  Moreover,  defecation  decreased  as  fear  was  extinguished  and 
water  consumption  rose. 

This  concludes  our  discussion  of  selected  studies  illustrating  the 
inhibitory  effects  of  fear  upon  other  responses.  Unfortunately,  we 
are  not  yet  in  possession  of  a  large  body  of  experimental  data  in 
this  area,  and  interpretations  and  generalizations  must  be  cau- 
tiously proposed.  We  need,  for  example,  more  detailed  information 
concerning  the  kinds  of  responses  that  are  inhibited  by  fear,  in- 
formation as  to  the  strengths  of  those  responses  relative  to  others. 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  165 

and  information  about  the  specific  characteristics  of  those  fear- 
conditioning  situations  that  lead  to  maximum  inhibition. 

Fear  as  Both  Inhibitor  and  Energizer.  At  the  start  of  the  preced- 
ing section  it  was  noted  that  an  apparent  contradiction  is  imphcit 
in  the  fact  that  fear  sometimes  functions  as  an  energizer  and  some- 
times as  an  inhibitor.  However,  it  was  asserted  that  within  the 
framework  of  the  present  conception  of  acquired  sources  of  drive 
these  opposite  efFects  are  not  paradoxical,  since  one  of  our  criteria 
of  a  motivational  variable  is  that  its  introduction  following  a  re- 
sponse tends  to  lead  to  the  abandonment  or  inhibition  of  that  re- 
sponse. But  this  interpretation  is  applicable  only  when  one  can 
provide  reasonable  evidence  that  the  inhibited  response  was  in- 
deed elicited  before  the  onset  of  the  fear-arousing  CS.  Unfortu- 
nately, this  is  usually  not  easy  to  do,  especially  in  instrumental  con- 
ditioning situations  where  the  onset  and/or  termination  of  the 
CS  may  not  be  precisely  controlled.  The  evaluation  of  this  concep- 
tion must  be  delayed,  therefore,  pending  the  accumulation  of  addi- 
tional data. 

An  alternate  hypothesis  as  to  why  fear  has  inhibitory  properties 
can  be  developed  along  purely  associative  lines.  Let  us  suppose,  for 
example,  that  bar  pressing  is  the  reference  response.  If  that  re- 
sponse occurs  consistently  prior  to  fear  conditioning,  then  the  bar- 
pressing  habit  must  be  stronger  than  other  habits.  Moreover,  since 
bar  pressing  is  not  enhanced  by  the  drive  increment  that  might  be 
produced  by  the  first  fear-conditioning  trial,  but  is  either  slightly 
depressed  or  is  unchanged,  it  must  be  further  postulated  that  one 
trial  is  sufficient  to  shift  some  habit  other  than  bar  pressing  into  a 
position  of  dominance.  Thus  a  tendency  to  freeze  or  to  crouch  or 
to  move  away  from  the  region  of  the  bar  could  have  become 
slightly  stronger  than  the  tendency  to  press  the  bar.  Whatever  the 
nature  of  the  newly  dominant  tendency,  it  must  be  regarded  as 
one  that  can  prevent  or  interfere  with  bar  pressing.  It  could  be 
either  an  innate  or  a  learned  response  to  fear-produced  internal 
stimuli.  As  fear  increases  with  training,  the  internal  cues  would  be 
expected  to  increase  in  intensity,  or  more  of  them  might  rise  above 
a  threshold  value,  producing  an  increase  in  the  superiority  of  the 
interfering  tendency  relative  to  the  bar-pressing  tendency. 


166  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

Should  one  choose  to  do  so,  the  construct  of  D  could  be  added 
to  this  associative  theoty  without  changing  its  predictions.  Both 
the  new  competing  habit  and  the  bar-pressing  habit  would  be  mul- 
tiplied by  the  drive  due  to  hunger  and  by  the  mounting  fear-pro- 
duced drive.  Crouching  or  avoidance  reactions  and  bar  pressing 
should  therefore  both  become  stronger,  but  with  the  increase  in 
drive  and  in  the  difference  between  the  two  habits,  the  strength 
of  the  interfering  excitatory  tendency  would  become  progressively 
greater  relative  to  the  bar-pressing  excitator)^  tendency.  Conse- 
quently, overt  bar  pressing  should  decline,  even  though  the  ab- 
solute magnitude  of  its  excitatory  tendency  was  rising.  As  we  have 
already  seen,  the  multiplicative-drive  assumption  alone  cannot  ex- 
plain declining  performance  under  circumstances  in  which  drive 
level  is  presumably  increasing.  One  must  further  hypothesize  that 
the  variable  leading  to  increased  D  also  serves  to  bring  a  new,  in- 
compatible reactive  tendency  into  a  position  of  ascendance  over 
the  old.  This  is  clearly  an  associative  assumption,  but  its  use  per- 
mits one  to  retain  the  hypothesis  of  D  as  a  multiplying  agent  even 
where  an  indicant  reaction  is  becoming  overtly  weaker. 

Variables  Influencing  the  Strength  of  Fear.  Some  of  the  vari- 
ables determining  strength  of  fear  have  already  been  mentioned  in 
our  discussions  of  specific  experimental  studies  of  fear.  There  are 
numerous  others,  however,  which,  though  they  cannot  be  treated 
here  in  detail,  are  of  sufficient  importance  to  mention.  For  an  ex- 
cellent analysis  of  many  of  these  the  reader  is  referred  to  Miller's 
(1951)  treatment  of  learnable  drives  and  rewards. 

The  most  general  statement  one  can  make  concerning  the 
strength  of  fear  is  that  it  is  influenced  by  many  of  the  same  associ- 
ative variables  that  determine  the  strength  of  other  conditioned 
responses.  For  example,  fear  tends  to  become  stronger  as  the  in- 
tensity of  the  noxious  UCS  is  increased  (Miller  and  Lawrence, 
1950).  And  if  electric  shock  of  near  tetanizing  intensity  is  used, 
with  dogs  at  least,  fear  becomes  so  firmly  ingrained  that  its  ex- 
tinction is  accomplished  only  with  great  difficulty  (Solomon,  Ka- 
min,  and  Wynne,  1953).  Fear  also  tends  to  increase  progressively 
as  the  number  of  paired  presentations  of  the  CS  and  UCS  is  in- 
creased (Brown,  Kalish,  and  Farber,  1951;  Kahsh,  1954).  Beyond  a 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  167 

certain  point,  however,  fear  may  decline  with  further  conditioning 
trials.  This  possibility  is  suggested  by  Libby's  (1951)  finding  that 
80  fear-conditioning  trials  appeared  to  yield  weaker  fear  than  40. 
Electric  shocks  of  long  duration  may  also  produce  stronger  fear 
than  short  shocks,  but  the  evidence  is  far  from  convincing 
(Mowrer  and  Solomon,  1954).  Fear  also  is  known  to  vary  with 
the  length  of  the  interval  between  the  CS  and  UCS  (Libby,  1951; 
Murfin,  1954),  and  perhaps  with  degree  of  massing  of  fear-condi- 
tioning trials  (Armus,  1954).  Moreover,  fear  reactions  may  be 
more  intense  when  an  organism  is  hungry  than  when  it  is  not 
(Estes  and  Skinner,  1941;  Meryman,  1952). 

Although  existing  studies  of  factors  influencing  strength  of  fear 
are  illuminating,  systematically  gathered  data  in  this  area  are  still 
relatively  meager.  Much  additional  work  certainly  remains  to  be 
done  before  we  can  be  reasonably  certain  as  to  what  the  optimum 
conditions  are  for  the  acquisition  of  fear.  Investigations  are  rare,  for 
example,  of  the  generalization  of  fear  or  of  the  effects  on  fear 
of  shock  duration  and  changes  in  the  characteristics  of  the  CS. 
More  data  are  also  needed  on  fear  as  a  function  of  the  distribution 
of  both  acquisition  and  extinction  trials. 

Concerning  the  problem  of  the  elimination  or  extinction  of  fear, 
it  seems  likely  that  any  factor  tending  to  increase  strength  of  fear 
should  also  enhance  its  resistance  to  counteracting  influences.  As 
is  well  known,  degree  of  resistance  to  extinction  is  often  used  as 
a  measure  of  strength  of  fear  and  other  responses.  The  procedures 
for  the  conditioning  of  fear  are  those  of  classical  Pavlovian  condi- 
tioning, and  experimental  extinction,  therefore,  is  the  basic  method 
for  eliminating  fear.  Thus,  to  weaken  fear  it  is  only  necessary,  in 
principle,  to  present  the  fear-arousing  CS  without  the  UCS.  We 
have  already  seen  from  Kalish's  study  (1954)  that  fear  declines 
progressively  with  the  number  of  such  nonreinforced  presentations 
of  the  CS.  Solomon  and  Wynne  (1953)  have  suggested  that  fears 
often  show  remarkable  resistance  to  extinction  because  the  individ- 
ual's avoidance  responses  remove  him  too  quickly  from  the  pres- 
ence of  the  fear-arousing  CS.  Presumably,  for  extinction  to  be  suc- 
cessful, fear  must  be  more  or  less  fully  aroused  by  the  CS  and  yet 
not  be  reinforced  by  the   UCS.   These  authors   have   also  hy- 


168  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

pothesized  that  traumatically  strong  shocks  may  produce  condi- 
tioned fears  that  can  never  be  completely  eradicated  by  normal 
extinction  procedures. 

The  process  of  fear  extinction  can  be  accelerated  by  massing 
extinction  trials  (Burros,  1949)  or  by  permitting  or  persuading  the 
subject  to  engage  in  appetitive  activity  while  in  the  presence  of  the 
CS.  This  latter  relationship  has  been  demonstrated  experimentally 
by  Farber  (1948).  Those  of  his  rats  that  ate  in  the  fear-arousing 
environment  lost  their  fears  more  quickly  than  animals  that  spent 
the  same  amount  of  time  in  the  same  environment  but  did  not 
eat.  In  Jones's  (1924)  classic  demonstration  of  this  principle,  a 
child's  fear  of  a  rabbit  was  overcome  by  first  presenting  the  rabbit 
at  a  distance  while  the  child  was  eating  and  by  then  bringing  the 
animal  closer  and  closer  to  the  child  on  successive  occasions. 

Conditioned  fear  in  rats  can  also  be  very  nearly  eliminated  by 
the  use  of  electroconvulsive  shocks  (Hunt  and  Brady,  1951),  as  we 
have  already  noted,  and  by  the  elicitation  of  audiogenic  seizures 
(Brady,  Stebbins,  and  Galambos,  1953).  Moreover,  alcohol,  which 
is  well  known  for  its  ability  to  reduce  human  fears  and  anxieties, 
tends  also  to  reduce  the  fears  of  rats  in  laboratory  conflict  situa- 
tions (Conger,  1951). 

The  problem  of  precisely  which  variables  govern  the  learning  of 
emotional  reactions  such  as  fear  has  engaged  the  attention  of 
numerous  theorists.  For  some,  the  learning  of  both  emotional  and 
nonemotional  responses  is  governed  by  the  same  principles;  others, 
however,  hold  that  the  known  facts  cannot  be  encompassed  unless 
two  or  more  different  laws  or  principles  are  invoked.  Marshalling 
and  analyzing  the  evidence  relative  to  this  problem  is  a  fairly 
lengthy  matter,  and  we  postpone  it,  therefore,  to  our  final  chapter 
which  is  devoted  to  theoretical  issues  of  this  sort. 

Anxieties  or  Fears  as  Learned  Sources 
of  Drive  in   Human   Behavior 

Thus  far  our  discussion  of  acquired-drive  problems  has  been 
restricted,  for  the  most  part,  to  laboratory  studies  of,  and  theories 
derived  from,  conditioned  fear  responses  in  animals.  We  have 
followed  this  course  because  the  most  carefully  controlled  experi- 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  169 

ments  have  been  done  with  animals,  not  because  the  study  of  their 
artificially  induced  fears  is,  in  itself,  to  be  regarded  as  of  primary 
importance.  The  study  of  fear  in  animals  is,  of  course,  a  perfectly 
legitimate  area  for  scientists  to  explore.  But  most  research  workers 
wish  to  know  whether  functional  relations  obtained  with  one  or- 
ganism can  be  generalized  to  other  organisms,  including  man. 
Actually,  the  process  is  a  two-way  one.  We  can  learn  important 
things  about  rats'  fears  from  human  beings,  and  vice  versa.  From 
everyday  experiences  with  our  fellow  men  and  from  laboratory 
studies,  we  often  get  hunches  as  to  the  ways  in  which  certain  vari- 
ables affect  behavior.  But  in  testing  out  these  hunches,  we  may  find 
it  desirable  to  use  animals  as  subjects.  This  is  often  true  when  we 
desire  to  minimize  the  role  of  verbal  mechanisms  or  when  it  is 
necessary  to  employ  fear-arousing  unconditioned  stimuli  of  a 
traumatically  intense  nature.  Studies  such  as  those  of  Solomon, 
Kamin,  and  Wynne  (1953)  on  traumatic-avoidance  learning  in 
dogs  could  never  have  been  done  with  human  subjects. 

That  human  fears,  anxieties,  and  feelings  of  insecurity  have 
widespread  effects  upon  behavior  is  almost  universally  acknowl- 
edged. In  Freudian  (1936)  theory  as  in  others,  feelings  of  anxiety, 
guilt,  and  the  like,  play  a  major  role  in  the  interpretation  of  nor- 
mal behavior.  These  feelings  or  reactions,  moreover,  are  believed 
to  constitute  the  cornerstones  of  the  bizarre  personality  structures 
of  the  neurotic  and  the  psychotic. 

Human  Fears  as  Learned  Responses.  Although  tendencies  to 
become  anxious  could  conceivably  be  transmitted  through  genetic 
channels,  human  beings,  by  and  large,  must  learn  to  be  anxious. 
During  a  child's  early  years  there  are  innumerable  opportunities 
for  it  to  acquire  fears  of  certain  stimulus  objects  in  certain  situa- 
tions. We  know  little,  unfortunately,  about  how  these  anxieties 
are  learned,  but  it  seems  reasonable  to  believe  that  they  are  ac- 
quired in  much  the  same  ways  as  are  conditioned  fears  in  animals. 
For  instance,  the  sight  of  a  flaming  match  may  serve  as  a  CS, 
with  the  subsequently  experienced  burn  providing  the  UCS.  Since 
similar  sets  of  events  occur  repeatedly,  ample  opportunities  are 
provided  for  children  to  acquire  fears  of  whatever  objects  society 
regards  as  dangerous.  Indeed,  in  order  to  save  children  from  injury, 
parents  spend  a  great  deal  of  time  making  certain  that  youngsters 


170  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

do  become  fearful  at  the  sight  of  a  hot  radiator,  an  oncoming  car, 
high  places,  deep  ditches,  electric  outlets,  and  so  on. 

At  first,  when  we  try  to  inculcate  these  protective  fears  into  our 
children,  we  cannot  use  language  in  any  effective  way.  The  words 
"hot,"  "hurt,"  "burn,"  and  "ouch"  mean  nothing  to  the  infant. 
During  the  early  stages  of  training,  therefore,  most  children  must 
actually  experience  the  trauma  and  pain  provided  by  noxious 
stimuli.  But  with  the  passage  of  time  the  child  experiences  re- 
peated pairings  of  warning  words  such  as  "hurt"  with  unpleasant 
or  painful  sensations.  These  warning  words  can  thus  come  to 
arouse  the  child's  anxiety  or  fear  in  the  same  way  as  do  other 
stimuli  such  as  the  sight  of  the  hot  stove,  the  sharp  razor  blade, 
or  the  electric  outlet.  The  conditioning  of  fear  to  verbal  cues  of 
this  variety  is  an  extremely  important  step  in  providing  the  child 
with  protective  fears,  since  by  this  means  the  parent  can  arouse  the 
child's  anxiety  in  new  situations  to  which  the  child  has  not  been 
previously  exposed.  The  child  may  never  have  seen  a  soldering 
iron,  but  the  parent  can  elicit  fear  and  withdrawal  simply  by 
pointing  to  the  iron  and  saying  "hot"  or  "hurt."  It  would  seem, 
therefore,  that  language  serves,  in  this  manner,  the  very  useful 
adaptive  function  of  eliciting  fear  and  withdrawal  in  a  large  assort- 
ment of  potentially  dangerous  situations.  The  widespread  effects 
of  this  type  of  training  are  well  illustrated  by  the  behavior  of  a 
)Oung  child  known  to  the  writer  who  used  the  word  "Ow!"  as  the 
name  for  flaming  matches,  cigarettes,  bonfires,  and  stoves,  long 
before  she  could  give  these  objects  their  correct  names.  A  child 
need  not  cut  his  fingers  on  a  power-driven  saw  to  acquire  a  fear 
and  an  avoidance  of  the  whirhng  blade.  But  to  do  so  without 
pain,  he  must  learn  to  react  with  anxiety  to  certain  verbal  or  ges- 
tural symbols,  and  these  symbols  must,  in  turn,  be  associated,  some- 
times repeatedly,  with  to-be-avoided  objects  or  situations. 

If  we  look  at  the  technical  details  of  this  process,  it  becomes  ap- 
parent that  the  initial  step  in  associating  fear  with  the  warning 
words  fits  the  pattern  of  classical  conditioning  precisely.  But  in 
new  situations,  where  the  child  may  not  actually  get  hurt,  the 
paradigm  is  different.  The  sight  of  the  new  object  (CS)  is  not 
associated  with  pain  but  with  the  word  "hurt,"  which,  because  it 
can  arouse  fear,  now  functions  as  a  substitute  UCS.  By  repeated 


LEARNED   RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF   DRIVE  171 

pairings  of  the  new  CS  with  the  fear-arousing  word,  the  new  CS 
also  comes  to  evoke  fear  and/or  withdrawal.  This  paradigm  will 
be  recognized  as  that  of  higher-order  conditioning,  a  procedure 
described  and  successfully  demonstrated  by  Pavlov  (1927)  and 
others.  While  the  higher-order  conditioning  of  salivary  and  skeletal 
responses  in  animals  is  rather  difiEcult  to  establish  and  is  some- 
what unstable,  it  may  be  that  the  higher-order  conditioning  of 
fear  can  be  more  readily  accomplished.  Moreover,  higher-order 
emotional  conditioning  of  a  strength  and  stability  unattainable 
with  animals  can  perhaps  be  produced  in  human  subjects  as  a 
consequence  of  the  operation  of  language. 

Proceeding  on  the  premise  that  human  behavior  is  fraught  with 
learned  anxieties  and  fears,  we  must  next  consider  whether,  and 
to  what  degree,  such  anxieties  can  lie  at  the  root  of  the  so-called 
acquired  drives  for  power,  money,  prestige,  and  the  like. 

Anxiety  as  an  Element  of  the  "Acquired  Drive"  for  Money.  Al- 
though the  paradigm  of  classical  conditioning  seems  to  serve 
rather  well  for  fear  and  anxiety,  it  cannot  easily  be  applied  to  an 
analysis  of  the  "drives  for  specific  goal  objects"  that  adult  human 
beings  are  alleged  to  possess.  Consider,  for  a  moment,  the  so- 
called  drive  for  money.  If  this  is  essentially  a  learned  or  condi- 
tioned response,  we  must  first  ask  how  it  has  become  conditioned. 
But  in  seeking  an  answer  we  immediately  run  into  difficulty,  since 
we  cannot  specify  any  unconditioned  stimulus  capable  of  eliciting 
the  money-seeking  drive  (or  response)  in  the  first  place.  If  there 
is  no  stimulus  that  can  elicit  the  response  without  training,  how 
can  we  arrange  for  the  response  to  become  associated  with  a  con- 
ditioned stimulus?  Whatever  the  so-called  acquired  drive  for 
money  may  be,  it  is  not  a  simple,  unitary  response  elicitable  by  a 
specific  unconditioned  stimulus  and  conditionable  to  other  stimuli 
by  the  procedures  of  classical  conditioning. 

Part  of  the  difficulty  here  arises  from  the  use  of  the  phrase  "ac- 
quired drive  for  money."  If,  as  we  have  suggested,  it  is  desirable  to 
use  the  word  "drive"  only  when  referring  to  a  construct  that  is 
nondirective  in  its  motivating  effects  upon  behavior,  then  we  can- 
not meaningfully  speak  of  a  drive  for  any  specific  goal,  whether 
it  be  for  money,  prestige,  power,  or  whatever.  On  this  view,  al- 
though both  learned  and  unlearned  responses  may  contribute  to 


172  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

drive,  one  can  have  neither  a  learned  nor  an  unlearned  drive  for 
anything.  While  working  in  factories,  schools,  stores,  offices,  and 
elsewhere,  people  do  learn,  of  course,  to  perform  a  multitude  of 
responses  for  which  monetary  rewards  are  provided.  And  in  a 
certain  sense  money  is  the  goal  toward  which  these  responses  are 
directed.  But  unless  our  concept  of  drive  is  changed,  the  drive 
underlying  those  activities  cannot  itself  be  directed  toward  money; 
nor  does  it  seem  likely  that  those  responses  can  serve  as  the  source 
of  drive  to  which  reference  is  made  in  speaking  of  a  "drive  for 
money."  In  fact,  it  is  precisely  these  day-to-day,  work-situation 
activities  that  are  themselves  presumably  motivated  by  the  money- 
seeking  drive,  and  we  are  forced  to  look  elsewhere,  therefore,  for 
learned  responses  having  the  motivating  properties  we  seek. 

According  to  one  interpretation  (Brown,  1953a),  anxiety  might 
serve  as  a  learned  motivating  agency  for  money-seeking  responses 
if  it  is  aroused  by  cues  indicating  the  absence  of  money.  On  this 
view,  stimulus  patterns  such  as  those  provided  by  an  empty  wallet 
or  by  an  "overdrawn"  notice  from  one's  bank  acquire,  through 
learning,  the  capacity  to  elicit  reactions  of  insecurity,  uneasiness,  or 
anxiety.  And  because  of  the  drive  properties  of  such  anxiety  reac- 
tions, a  wide  assortment  of  specific  stimulus-elicited  responses  can 
be  affected  as  though  some  motivational  variable  had  been  manip- 
ulated. Moreover,  a  reduction  in  anxiety,  should  it  occur  follow- 
ing a  particular  response,  would  be  expected  to  reinforce  that  re- 
sponse. At  the  heart  of  this  interpretation,  then,  is  the  basic  idea 
that  an  ".  .  .  important  motivating  component  of  many  of  the 
supposed  acquired  drives  for  specific  goal  objects  is  actually  a 
learned  tendency  to  be  discontented  or  distressed  or  anxious  in  the 
absence  of  those  goal  objects"  (Brown,  1953a,  p.  12). 

If  this  analysis  is  to  carry  conviction,  however,  it  is  necessary  to 
present  the  details  of  the  process  by  which  the  reaction  of  anxiety 
becomes  conditioned  to  stimuli  signifying  "no  money"  or  "insuf- 
ficient money."  We  need  to  know  why  we  have  learned  to  feel 
anxious,  embarrassed,  and  uneasy  if,  for  example,  after  ordering 
and  eating  a  meal  in  a  restaurant,  we  find  that  we  have  failed  to 
bring  sufficient  money.  By  what  process  does  anxiety  become  con- 
ditioned to  the  stimuli  provided  by  the  to-be-paid  check  in  com- 
bination with  the  empty  pocket? 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  173 

Probably  the  most  satisfactoty  answer  to  this  question  is  that 
these  anxieties  are  acquired  through  a  process  of  higher-order  con- 
ditioning, with  verbal  cues  playing  a  major  role,  in  essentially  the 
same  way  that  generalized  fears  of  dangerous  situations  are  learned. 
The  initial  stage  in  the  process  would  consist  of  repeated  child- 
hood experiences  in  which  pain  has  been  associated  with  verbal  or 
gestural  cues  of  alarm  or  warning  provided  by  adults.  In  their 
most  general  and  common  form,  these  are  statements  like  "Look 
out,  you'll  get  hurt,"  or  "If  you  do  that  something  bad  will  hap- 
pen to  you."  Or  the  cues  may  be  facial  expressions  of  alarm,  con- 
cern, and  worry  accompanying  the  verbal  warnings.  Following  the 
paradigm  of  classical  conditioning,  these  alarm-denoting  cues 
might  come  to  arouse  the  emotional  reactions  of  dread,  fear,  or 
anxiety,  even  in  the  absence  of  actual  pain. 

The  second  stage  of  the  process  involves  the  further  conditioning 
of  anxiety  to  a  wide  variety  of  cues,  all  of  which  indicate  a  lack 
of  money  or  its  relative  scarcity.  Because  of  the  nature  of  our 
society  and  the  great  significance  of  money  for  many  of  its  mem- 
bers, ample  opportunities  exist  therein  for  the  occurrence  of  this 
secondary  conditioning  of  anxiety.  This  could  be  accomplished 
in  a  number  of  ways.  Consider  the  typical  warnings  given  to 
children  by  parents.  "If  you  get  on  a  train  and  can't  pay  your 
fare,  the  conductor  will  throw  you  off,"  or,  "If  we  run  out  of 
money  before  the  end  of  the  month,  we  may  not  have  enough  food 
to  eat,"  or,  "If  you  don't  pay  for  your  meal,  the  restaurant  owner 
will  make  you  wash  all  the  dishes."  Now  in  each  of  these  state- 
ments, and  in  innumerable  ones  like  them,  an  anxiety-arousing 
warning  is  paired  with  a  statement  about  the  lack  of  money. 
Through  repeated  pairings,  by  other  children  as  well  as  by  parents, 
of  these  two  kinds  of  assertions,  cues  denoting  a  lack  of  money 
might  come  to  arouse  anxiety  reactions.  The  cues  become,  in  this 
way,  the  counterparts  of  the  fear-eliciting  CS  used  in  animal  ex- 
periments, and  the  anxieties  they  elicit  may  constitute  an  impor- 
tant motivational  component  underlying  human  money-seeking 
responses. 

It  is  not  necessary,  according  to  this  interpretation,  to  assume 
that  one  must  have  absolutely  no  money  in  order  to  experience 
anxiety.  Being  "broke"  means  different  things  to  different  in- 


174  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

dividuals.  The  college  professor  may  feel  "broke"  and  anxious 
when  his  bank  balance  drops  below,  say,  $25.  But  the  multimil- 
lionaire, who  owns  numerous  yachts,  planes,  estates,  and  cars, 
may  suffer  acute  distress  upon  finding  that  he  is  "down  to  his  last 
million."  Just  recently  one  of  the  richest  men  in  the  world  was 
quoted  as  having  said  that  "...  after  all,  a  million  dollars  isn't 
worth  what  it  used  to  be." 

One  of  the  consequences  of  this  view  relates  to  the  problem  of 
the  rewarding  or  reinforcing  value  of  money.  As  we  well  know, 
sequences  of  action  followed  by  monetary  rewards  tend  to  be 
learned  by  individuals  in  our  society  and  tend  to  be  abandoned 
if  these  rewards  are  withdrawn.  One  common  interpretation  of 
this  phenomenon  is  based  on  the  concept  of  secondary  reinforce- 
ment, which  was  derived  originally  from  Pavlov's  work  on  higher- 
order  conditioning.  As  usually  stated,  a  stimulus  object  acquires 
secondary  reinforcing  properties  when  it  has  been  closely  and 
repeatedly  associated  with  a  primary  rewarding  event.  Thus  if  a 
rat  has  been  repeatedly  fed  in  a  white  goal  box,  the  box  may  act 
as  a  learned  or  secondary  reward  in  other  situations  because  of 
its  association  with  the  consummatory  act  of  eating.  Applied  to 
money,  the  principle  would  be  that  money  has  become  secondarily 
rewarding  because  it  has  been  frequently  exchanged  for  food, 
which  in  turn  has  led  to  a  reduction  of  hunger.  The  behavior  of 
chimpanzees  in  the  well-known  token-reward  studies  of  Wolfe 
(1936)  and  of  Cowles  (1937)  has  commonly  been  explained  as 
an  instance  of  secondary  reinforcement.  These  studies  showed 
that  initially  neutral  objects,  such  as  poker  chips,  acquired  a 
rewarding  value  for  the  chimpanzees  if  the  chips  could  be  ex- 
changed by  the  animals  for  raisins  or  other  preferred  foods. 

The  foregoing  interpretation  of  how  anxiety  may  form  the 
motivational  substratum  of  money-seeking  behavior  leads  to  a 
different  view  of  the  process  by  which  money  acquires  its  reward- 
ing value.  If  cues  denoting  the  lack  of  money  or  its  relative 
absence  lead  to  anxiety,  then  the  actual  possession  of  money  must 
lead  to  a  diminution  of  anxiety.  Moreover,  if  anxiety  reduction 
functions  to  reinforce  antedating  responses,  then  some  of  the 
reinforcing  value  of  money  may  be  due  to  its  anxiety-quelling 
properties.  Thus  money  may  become  a  reinforcer,  in  part,  because 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  175 

anxiety  is  aroused  by  stimulus  events  denoting  a  lack  of  money 
and  because  money  in  one's  hand  counteracts  that  anxiety.  Inciden- 
tally, this  conception  does  not  negate  the  value  of  the  secondary- 
reinforcement  theory.  It  serves,  rather,  as  an  additional  explanatory 
mechanism,  capable  of  operating  jointly  with  secondary  reinforce- 
ment. 

Money,  though  of  major  significance,  is  by  no  means  the  only 
agent  capable  of  eliminating  the  anxiety  occasioned  by  cues 
denoting  money's  absence.  Quite  often  people  who  are  distressed 
by  the  knowledge  that  they  are  broke,  or  nearly  so,  escape  from 
the  disquieting  cues  by  going  to  sleep,  getting  drunk,  or  going 
to  the  movies.  Since  these  "escape"  reactions  are  followed  by 
anxiety  reduction,  they  too  tend  to  be  reinforced,  and  as  a  result 
may  become  well  established  though  unrealistic  modes  of  reacting 
to  a  lack  of  money. 

The  essence  of  this  interpretation  has  been  summarized  by 
Brown  (1953ci,  p.  14)  as  follows:  "In  many  instances,  if  not  all, 
where  adult  human  behavior  has  been  strongly  marked  by  money- 
seeking  responses  there  appears  to  be  little  need  for  postulating 
the  operation  of  a  learned  money-seeking  drive.  One  does  not 
learn  to  have  a  drive  for  money.  Instead,  one  learns  to  become 
anxious  in  the  presence  of  a  variety  of  cues  signifying  the  absence 
of  money.  The  obtaining  of  money  automatically  terminates  or 
drastically  alters  such  cues,  and  in  so  doing,  produces  a  decrease 
in  anxiety.  Money-seeking  responses,  or  other  reactions,  appearing 
during  the  arousal  of  anxiety  are  strongly  reinforced  by  the  decline 
of  anxiety  attending  the  receipt  of  money." 

As  a  final  point  we  must  emphasize  that  this  conception  is  not 
restricted  to  the  so-called  acquired  drive  for  money.  Anxiety-arous- 
ing properties  could  certainly  be  acquired  by  stimuli  denoting  a 
lack  of  prestige  or  affection  or  power,  and  could  thus  provide  a 
motivational  mainspring  for  responses  directed  toward  these  goals 
as  well.  Moreover,  this  view  of  anxiety  as  a  basic  component  of 
many  of  the  so-called  acquired  drives  is  very  similar  to  previously 
proposed  conceptions.  Tolman  (1942),  for  example,  has  presented 
a  somewhat  similar  explanation  of  the  "drive  of  gregariousness." 
Thus  he  maintains  that  in  gregarious  species  of  animals,  separation 
from  the  flock  or  herd  results  in  an  "internal  sufferance"  that  is 


176  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

eliminated  by  rejoining  the  group.  Clearly,  this  "internal  suffer- 
ance" is  functionally  much  the  same  as  the  anxiety  we  have  been 
considering,  and  like  anxiety  can  be  aroused  by  cues  indicating  a 
special  kind  of  deficit.  A  parallel  line  of  reasoning  has  been  fol- 
lowed by  Dollard  and  Miller  (1950)  in  their  brief  analysis  of  the 
anxieties  experienced  by  a  child  when  separated  from  its  mother. 
Certain  environmental  cues,  when  not  accompanied  by  the  sights 
or  sounds  of  the  mother,  are  assumed  to  lead  to  the  drive  of  fear, 
and  the  child's  responses  of  seeking  and  approaching  the  mother 
are  reinforced  by  the  reduction  in  fear  her  presence  provides. 


Other  Learned  Responses  as  Sources  of  Drive 

Anxiety  doubtless  constitutes  a  significant  secondary  motivating 
agency  for  human  behavior,  but  there  seems  to  be  scant  reason 
for  regarding  it  as  the  only  such  learned  motivator.  Quite  possibly 
other  responses  having  motivational  effects  are  learned  by  human 
beings,  and  some  perhaps  by  animals.  According  to  McClelland 
(1951),  for  example,  human  beings  are  driven  as  much  by  a 
"hope  of  success"  as  they  are  by  anxiety  or  by  a  "fear  of  failure." 
Of  the  several  attempts  that  have  been  made  to  develop  theories 
of  acquired  motivators  other  than  anxiety,  three  will  be  considered 
here.  The  first  is  the  Tg-Sg  "expectancy"  mechanism  of  Hull  and 
Spence;  the  second  is  the  "affective-arousal  model"  proposed  by 
McClelland,  and  the  third  is  the  writer's  tentative  hypothesis 
concerning  the  motivational  role  played  by  verbal  self-instructions. 

The  Tg-Sg  Mechanism  as  an  Acquired  Source  of  Drive.  In  some 
early  theoretical  articles,  Hull  (1931,  1937)  made  considerable 
interpretive  use  of  what  is  described  as  the  "expectancy"  or  rg-Sg 
mechanism.  According  to  Hull,  when  an  organism  is  rewarded 
while  making  a  consummatory  goal  reaction  {^g),  such  as  eating, 
associations  are  formed  by  the  process  of  classical  conditioning 
between  Kg  and  a  variety  of  stimuli,  both  internal  and  external. 
Since  some  cues,  e.g.,  those  arising  from  the  need  for  food  (S^s), 
are  present  throughout  all  phases  of  the  instrumental  response 
sequence,  there  is  a  tendency  for  them  to  elicit  Kq  at  every  point 
in  the  sequence.  But  only  certain  portions  or  phases  of  the  goal 


LEARNED   RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF   DRIVE  177 

reaction  of  eating  can  be  performed  prior  to  the  attainment  of 
food.  Responses  such  as  seizing  the  food,  biting  it,  chewing,  and 
swallowing  cannot  move  backward  (appear  at  an  earlier  time)  in 
the  sequence  since  they  lack,  at  those  points,  the  necessary  goal 
object  (food)  for  their  execution.  Reactions  such  as  sniffing,  sali- 
vating, smacking  the  lips,  and  swallowing,  however,  can  indeed 
be  elicited  before  the  goal  is  reached.  Hull  thought  of  responses 
like  these  as  split-off  portions  of  the  goal  reaction  (Rg)  •  He  named 
them,  therefore,  fractional  anticipatory  goal  reactions  and  denoted 
them  by  the  symbol  Vg.  It  should  now  be  clear  why  the  term  ex- 
pectancy is  appropriate  in  connection  with  these  responses.  Observ- 
able responses  of  salivating,  swallowing,  and  licking  the  chops,  if 
exhibited  by  a  pet  dog,  say,  just  before  he  is  fed,  constitute  about 
as  good  an  objective  index  of  his  "food  expectancy"  as  can  be 
found. 

Now  these  fractional  anticipatory  goal  reactions  would  be 
expected  to  give  rise  to  characteristic  internal  stimuli,  and  Hull 
completed  the  picture  by  adding  these  stimuli  (SgS)  to  the  VgS. 
Thus  the  complete  rg-Sg  mechanism  was  formed.  In  Hull's  earliest 
use  of  this  mechanism,  the  Sg  portion  played  the  principal  role 
as  a  behavior  determinant,  serving  both  as  a  stimulus  to  which 
a  variety  of  reactions  could  become  conditioned  and  as  a  secondary 
reinforcer.  On  a  number  of  occasions,  however,  Spence  (195 la, 
1956)  has  pointed  out  that  the  fractional  anticipatory  goal  response 
and  its  interoceptive  and  proprioceptive  stimuli  might  operate 
motivationally  as  well  as  associatively.  Since  the  classically  condi- 
tioned rg  is  learned,  it  would  qualify,  by  our  criteria,  as  a  secondary 
source  of  drive,  provided  it  does  indeed  have  the  motivational 
effects  suggested  for  it.  In  Spence's  formulation,  which  we  have 
outlined  in  Chapter  4,  the  strength  of  the  r^  is  dependent,  in  part, 
upon  the  magnitude  of  the  food  reward  given  an  animal.  And 
the  intervening  variable  K,  the  incentive-motivation  factor,  is,  in 
turn,  a  function  of  the  strength  of  r^.  Within  the  system,  K  affects 
behavior  in  much  the  same  way  that  D  does.  Thus  the  rg-Sg 
mechanism  and  the  related  K  factor  are  used  to  explain  the  fact 
that  animals  will  run  faster  through  a  maze  if  they  are  expecting 
a  large  piece  of  food  than  if  they  are  expecting  a  small  piece.  If 
they  have  been  given  large  pieces  of  food,  the  rg  is  stronger  and. 


178  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

therefore,  the  habit  of  approaching  the  food  is  multiphed  by  a 
higher  value  of  K. 

As  Spence  has  pointed  out,  a  similar  theory  was  proposed  earlier 
by  Crespi  (1944),  who,  in  interpreting  his  experiments  on  the 
effect  of  size  of  incentive,  appealed  to  what  he  called  an  "emo- 
tional drive."  In  this  so-called  "eagerness"  theory,  variations  in 
amount  of  reward  were  assumed  to  lead  to  differences  in  amount 
of  anticipatory  tension  or  excitement,  and  these  excitement  dif- 
ferences produced  corresponding  differences  in  motivation  and 
hence  in  level  of  performance. 

There  are  several  avenues  through  which  anticipator}^  goal  re- 
sponses and  their  interoceptive  cues  might  exert  their  motivational 
effects.  Within  Hull's  theory,  for  example,  s^  could  have  a  dy- 
namogenic  or  energizing  effect  resembling  that  of  intense  external 
stimuli.  The  effect  of  stimulus  intensity,  per  se,  Hull  called 
"stimulus  dynamism."  Or  it  may  be,  as  Spence  has  suggested,  that 
conflict  would  ensue  when  the  tendency  for  Tg  to  occur  at  an 
early  point  in  a  response  sequence  is  opposed  by  tendencies  to 
make  other  responses.  The  excitement  or  tension  produced  by  the 
conflict  might  have  motivational  consequences  by  adding  an  incre- 
ment to  the  existing  level  of  drive  (D).  This  possibility  is  dis- 
cussed in  more  detail  in  Chapter  6.  * 

An  interesting  application  and  extension  of  the  fg-Sg  concept 
appears  in  a  study  by  Birch,  Burnstein,  and  Clark  (1958).  During 
an  initial  35-day  training  period,  rats  were  allowed  to  eat  dry  food 
pellets  from  5:30  to  7:30  p.m.  each  day.  The  purpose  of  this 
training  was  to  develop  an  association  between  anticipatory  eating 
responses  (r^s)  and  the  internal  cues  characteristic  of  22  hours  of 
food  deprivation  (Sds).  On  the  assumption  that  the  r^  habit 
strength  generalized  along  the  dimension  of  So  intensity,  one 
would  expect  that  the  r<,s  evoked  by  the  combination  of  external 
cues  and  SdS  would  become  progressively  weaker  with  departures 
of  deprivation  time  in  either  direction  from  the  22-hour  training 
value.  And  on  the  further  hypothesis  that  drive  is  monotonically 
related  to  the  vigor  and/or  frequency  of  TgS,  drive  should  increase 
with  deprivation  up  to  the  customary  time  of  feeding  and  then 
decrease  as  deprivation  is  further  extended.  On  this  view,  then, 
the  strength  of  the  rat's  food  expectation  (r^)  is  contingent  upon 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  179 

how  similar  his  interoceptive  cues  are  to  those  that  have  usually 
been  present  at  the  time  of  eating,  and  his  drive  level  is  determined 
by  the  strength  of  his  expectancy. 

Data  interpreted  as  supporting  this  conception  v^^ere  obtained 
from  two  behavioral  measures.  The  first,  which  was  the  number 
of  times  the  rats  depressed  the  empty  food  trough  during  a  46-hour 
deprivation  test  period  on  the  thirty-sixth  and  thirty-seventh  days, 
showed  that  trough  depressions,  though  relatively  infrequent  during 
the  first  19  hours,  increased  rapidly  during  the  period  from  19 
to  24  hours  and  then  declined  to  zero  at  the  32-hour  point,  there 
being  some  suggestion  of  further  increases  in  the  period  from  32  to 
48  hours.  This  is  consistent  with  the  view  that  the  expectancy- 
generated  drive  increased  to  a  maximum  at  about  the  usual  time 
for  eating  and  then  decreased  with  further  deprivation.  Unfor- 
tunately, the  food  troughs  had  been  present  in  the  cages  through- 
out the  35-day  training  period,  and  hence  tendencies  to  approach 
the  troughs  for  food  at  deprivation  times  shorter  than  22  hours 
may  have  become  extinguished  through  nonreinforcement.  More- 
over, the  rats'  relatively  weak  tendency  to  depress  the  troughs  at 
intervals  longer  than  about  25  hours  may  have  been  due  in  part, 
as  the  authors  note,  to  extinction's  taking  place  during  the  middle 
periods  of  the  46-hour  testing  period. 

The  second  behavioral  measure,  speed  of  running  down  a  straight 
alley  for  food,  showed  that  on  the  first  trial  speed  tended  to  rise 
slightly,  but  not  significantly,  as  deprivation  time  was  increased 
from  15  to  37  hours.  On  subsequent  trials,  however,  running  speeds 
were  markedly  elevated  for  animals  running  under  22  and  25 
hours  of  deprivation  and  depressed  for  those  tested  with  15  and 
37  hours  of  deprivation.  Birch  et  al.  interpret  these  findings  as 
supporting  their  hypotheses  concerning  the  conditioning  of  Yg  to 
Sd,  and  the  contribution  of  r,,  to  D.  However,  all  of  their  measures 
showed  that  performance  under  25  hours  of  deprivation  was 
superior  to  that  at  22,  despite  the  fact  that  the  animals  were  never 
fed  save  at  the  22-hour  period.  If  generalization  of  Tg  along  the  So 
dimension  were  the  only  factor  involved,  performance  should  have 
been  worse  at  25  than  at  22  hours  and  there  should  have  been  no 
tendency  for  trough  depressions  to  be  greater  at  46  than  at  32 
hours.  Nevertheless,  the  experiment  suggests  that  rhythmical  feed- 


180  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

ing  schedules  may  influence  privation-motivated  behavior,  and  that 
estimates  of  drive  based  solely  upon  time  of  deprivation  may 
need  to  be  modified  when  such  schedules  have  been  employed. 

Before  leaving  this  topic,  we  find  it  appropriate  to  note  that  Mil- 
ler and  Bollard's  (1941)  analysis  of  acquired  drives  also  contains 
elements  that  are  quite  similar  to  those  involved  in  the  Tg-Sg  ->  K 
mechanism.  Thus  they  believe  that  any  strong  stimulus  has  drive 
value  (cf.  Hull's  stimulus-dynamism  concept)  and  that  the  stimuli 
produced  by  learned  responses  constitute  the  basis  for  all  acquired 
drives.  The  learned  responses  of  fear  and  anxiety  are  regarded  as 
especially  significant  contributors  to  level  of  motivation  (cf.  Mil- 
ler's experiment  on  fear  in  an  earlier  section  of  this  chapter),  but 
responses  toward  such  "positive"  goal  objects  as  food,  money,  and 
sexual  objects  also  provide  drive-augmenting  stimuli.  The  sight 
of  food,  for  example,  may  elicit  a  learned  appetitive  response,  and 
if  the  interoceptive  stimulation  attending  that  response  is  suffi- 
ciently intense  it  will  serve  as  a  drive  to  impel  food-seeking  (and 
other)  responses.  Moreover,  all  response-produced  stimuli  are  said 
by  Miller  and  Dollard  to  have  cue  value  as  well  as  drive-enhancing 
power.  This  aspect  of  their  conception  is  identical  with  the  notion 
that  a  variety  of  responses  can  be  associatively  connected  to  the  Sg 
portion  of  the  rg-Sg  mechanism. 

The  Affective-arousal  Model.  McClelland,  Atkinson,  Clark,  and 
Lowell  (1953),  expanding  upon  some  of  McClelland's  earlier 
work  (1951),  have  made  a  serious  attempt  to  solve  some  of  the 
acquired-drive  problems  and  have  proposed  what  they  call  the 
affective-arousal  model  as  a  general  theor}'  of  motivation.  According 
to  these  writers,  two  affective  states  of  the  organism  serve  as  im- 
portant motivators.  One  of  these  is  negative  (fear  or  anxiety)  and 
the  other  positive  (anticipation  of  rewards,  appetite).  Since  both 
of  these  motivating  states  are  learned  or  conditioned  reactions, 
they  fit  the  authors'  definition  of  a  motive:  "A  motive  is  the 
redintegration  bv  a  cue  of  a  change  in  an  affective  situation" 
(McClelland  et  al.,  1953,  p.  28).  As  shown  in  their  example,  if  a 
buzzer  is  associated  with  the  eating  of  a  sweet  substance  such  as 
sugar,  the  buzzer  will  eventually  come  to  evoke  (redintegrate)  a 
state  involving  positive  affective  change.  This  positive  affective 
condition  is  termed  appetite.  The  corresponding  negative  affective 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  181 

state,  anxiety,  is  conditioned  in  the  same  manner  as  is  fear,  accord- 
ing to  our  previous  description.  That  is,  a  buzzer,  if  associated  with 
shock,  acquires  the  capacity  to  redintegrate  a  negative  affective 
state  that  may  have  motivating  effects  on  behavior.  According  to 
this  theory,  then,  an  individual  learns  to  make  anticipatory  affective 
or  emotional  reactions  to  cues  denoting  the  coming  of  both  pleas- 
ant and  painful  events.  And  both  the  positive  and  negative  affects 
are  believed  to  have  important  motivating  properties. 

In  their  elaboration  of  this  view,  McClelland  et  al.  maintain 
that  all  motives  are  learned.  That  is,  unless  the  tendency  to  respond 
affectively  in  either  a  positive  or  negative  manner  is  a  learned  one, 
it  does  not  qualify  as  a  motive.  An  unlearned  primary  affective 
state  that  provides  the  basis  for  affective  conditioning  is  not  in 
itself  a  motive,  but  the  learned  or  redintegrated  image  thereof  is 
a  motive  and  is  motivating.  Following  this  line  of  reasoning,  they 
arrive  at  the  conclusion  that  a  newborn  rat,  when  it  experiences  a 
need  for  food  (primary  affect)  for  the  first  time,  is  not  motivated, 
or  at  least  its  hunger  motive  does  not  develop  until  it  has  eaten 
food  and  the  internal  need-produced  cues  have  come  to  function 
as  conditioned  stimuli  to  redintegrate  an  affective  arousal  like  that 
experienced  while  eating.  Unfortunately,  McClelland  and  his 
collaborators  do  not  tell  us  whether  an  unlearned  primary  ajfect 
has  motivating  effects  even  though  it  is  not  a  motive.  If  it  does, 
then  their  assertion  that  the  hungry  baby  rat  does  not  have  a 
motive  might  be  construed  as  having  the  same  meaning  as  the 
statement  (Brown,  1953a)  that  a  newborn  infant,  though  in  need 
of  food,  cannot  be  said  to  have  a  drive  for  food.  Apparently  a 
motive,  in  McClelland's  terms,  is  roughly  equivalent  to  Hull's 
excitatory  potential  (E)  in  the  sense  that  both  conceptions  are 
composites  of  associative  (habit)  factors  and  motivating  (drive) 
factors.  Just  as  Hull's  E,  which  equals  H  X  D,  would  have  a  zero 
value  if  the  habit  strength  (H)  were  zero,  so  too,  McClelland's 
motive  would  be  nonexistent  until  a  habit  had  been  formed,  even 
though  some  primary  affect  (D?)  were  present.  Identifying  Mc- 
Clelland's motive  with  E  makes  it  easier  to  understand  why  he 
insists  that  all  motives  guide  behavior  and  are  learned — this  is  the 
H  part.  It  is  uncertain,  however,  whether  the  motivating  effects 
of  McClelland's  motives  can  be  closely  equated  to  D  since  no 


182  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

clear  descriptions  are  provided  of  u'hat  z  motive  does  in  its  role 
as  a  motivational  determinant  of  behavior. 

Comparing  the  affective-arousal  model  with  some  of  the  views 
already  considered  here  is  of  some  interest.  As  has  been  noted,  the 
anxiety-conditioning  paradigm  of  McClelland  et  al.  is  the  same 
as  that  employed  by  Mowrer  (1939),  Miller  and  Bollard  (1941), 
Brown  and  Jacobs  (1949),  and  others,  in  their  treatments  of  the 
acquired  drive  of  fear.  All  of  these  latter  writers,  however,  differ 
from  McClelland  in  holding  that  both  the  learned  fear  and  the 
original,  unlearned  pain-fear  reaction  have  motivating  power.  Mc- 
Clelland's  positive  appetitive  motive  resembles  in  marked  degree 
the  Hull-Spence  Tg-Sg  mechanism.  Both  concepts  involve  learning, 
both  are  essentially  expectancies  of  reward,  and  the  conditions 
basic  to  their  establishment  are  essentially  identical.  The  concept 
of  positive  affective  arousal  also  appears  to  be  identical  with 
Mowrer's  (1950)  emotion  of  "hope,"  which  is  said  to  be  aroused 
by  signs  of  forthcoming  rewards  and  which,  like  fear,  can  energize 
response  tendencies. 

Verbal  Stimuli  as  Acquired  Sources  of  Drive.  It  is  traditional  to 
assert  that  human  behavior  differs  from  that  of  animals  primarily 
because  of  man's  capacity  to  use  language.  If  so,  then  one  is  led 
to  suspect  that,  in  so  far  as  human  motivational  systems  are 
unique,  language  may  be  involved  to  a  highly  significant  degree. 
Unfortunately,  httle  research  has  been  done  on  the  relation  of 
language  to  motivation  and  we  have  few  theories  as  to  how  behav- 
ior may  be  affected  by  words.  But  since  the  abihty  to  use  words 
is  clearly  learned,  it  is  interesting  to  consider  the  likelihood  that 
certain  words,  probably  by  virtue  of  the  learned  responses  they 
evoke,  have  motivating  functions  and  that  these  responses,  there- 
fore, would  qualify  as  acquired  sources  of  drive. 

To  begin  with,  it  is  clear  that  some  words  when  spoken  by 
certain  individuals  can  affect  the  behavior  of  others  as  though  a 
motivational  variable  had  been  introduced.  For  example,  verbal 
commands  like  "Hurry-up!"  "Pay  attention!"  "Come  on  now!" 
and  "Get  ready!"  when  spoken  by  a  parent  to  a  child,  tend  to 
facilitate  a  variety  of  different  acts  such  as  eating,  reading,  dressing, 
walking,  or  doing  the  household  chores.  On  some  occasions  these 
commands  can  be  given  in  a  relatively  soft  voice  and  still  be  effec- 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  183 

tive.  It  seems  unlikely,  therefore,  that  the  motivational  effects  of 
such  stimuli  can  be  due  simply  to  their  acoustic  intensity,  provided 
the  commands  are  loud  enough  to  be  heard  at  all.  Instead,  it 
seems  preferable  to  assume  that  these  verbal  commands  serve  as 
conditioned  stimuli  to  arouse  learned  responses  that  have  mo- 
tivating effects  upon  other  responses.  Viewed  in  this  way,  words 
are  analogous  to  fear-arousing  CSs,  and  the  learned  reactions  they 
elicit  are  functionally  comparable  to  conditioned  fear.  Just  what 
these  reactions  are  is  uncertain  at  present,  but  some  promising 
candidates  for  the  role  will  be  considered  shortly. 

A  distinctive  characteristic  of  motivating  words  is  that  they  do 
not,  for  the  most  part,  provide  cues  capable  of  eliciting  specific 
goal-directed  acts.  In  a  very  real  sense  they  have  no  definite  con- 
tent. When  we  tell  a  child  to  hurry  we  often  need  not  specify 
the  activities  that  must  be  performed  more  quickly.  Such  a  goalless 
command,  therefore,  may  function  to  speed  up  an  assortment  of 
very  different  actions.  Whatever  behavior  is  in  progress,  such  as 
running,  doing  arithmetic  problems,  bathing,  or  working,  will  tend 
to  be  facihtated  by  the  command  "Hurry!"  Because  of  their 
widespread  power  to  energize  almost  any  ongoing  behavior,  these 
motivating  words  bear  a  functional  resemblance  both  to  fear  and 
to  the  so-called  primary  sources  of  drive. 

Some  verbal  commands,  of  course,  like  "Drink  your  milk!"  are 
quite  specific  and  make  direct  reference  to  a  definite  concrete  act. 
Such  a  command  may  speed  up  milk-drinking  responses,  but  if 
this  is  its  only  effect  it  would  scarcely  qualify  as  a  general  motiva- 
tor. Rather,  we  would  tend  to  regard  it  as  a  specific  stimulus  to  a 
specific  learned  response.  It  fits  an  associative  interpretation  better 
than  a  motivational  one,  though  the  intonation  with  which  the 
command  is  given  may  have  motivational  effects.  Perhaps,  there- 
fore, verbal  commands  serve  as  learned  motivating  agents  only 
when  they  are  essentially  devoid  of  specific  content. 

Now  if  verbal  commands  like  these,  when  provided  by  parents 
and  other  individuals,  can  exert  widespread  facilitative  effects  upon 
ongoing  behavior,  it  appears  reasonable  to  suppose  that  they 
would  also  be  motivating  when  spoken  by  an  individual  to  himself. 
For  instance,  if  a  person  looks  at  his  wrist  watch,  and  sees  that 
only  a  few  minutes  remain  before  he  is  supposed  to  meet  a  friend. 


184  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

he  may  tell  himself  to  hurry.  Presumably,  these  self-administered 
verbal  commands,  because  of  their  similarity  to  commands  from 
others,  can  impel  the  individual  to  walk  more  briskly,  ride  a  bicycle 
faster,  or  drive  his  car  at  a  higher  speed.  Those  who  engage  in 
competitive  activities  doubtless  often  resort  to  self-exhortations 
like  "I  must  do  my  best,"  "I  must  give  it  everything  I've  got," 
and  "I  can't  quit  now!"  Because  of  the  nonspecific  nature  of  these 
instructions,  it  is  possible,  perhaps,  for  them  to  enhance  whatever 
activity  is  being  performed  by  the  individual.  And  since  all  in- 
dividuals of  a  given  society  tend  to  learn  the  same  words,  the 
same  self-administered  "pep  talk"  could  facilitate  the  offensive 
and  defensive  play  of  a  football  hero,  the  pole  vaulting  of  a  track 
man,  the  cerebrations  of  a  chess  champion,  or  even  the  responses 
of  an  expert  on  a  television  quiz  program.  Moreover,  the  assump- 
tion that  the  commands  can  be  self-administered  means  that 
motivation  from  this  source  can  perhaps  be  aroused  even  in  situa- 
tions where  the  individual  has  had  no  previous  specific  learning 
experiences.  Certainly  people  do  instruct  themselves  in  these  ways 
in  times  of  stress,  and  the  tendency  to  do  so  is  unquestionably 
learned.  If  such  self-instructions  can  function  as  motivators,  they 
may  play  a  major  role  in  human  behavior  as  secondary  sources  of 
drive. 

One  of  the  interesting  features  of  this  proposal  lies  in  its  possible 
relations  to  the  need-achievement  motive  studied  by  Murray 
(1938)  and  by  McClelland,  Atkinson,  Clark,  and  Lowell  (1953). 
According  to  the  members  of  the  latter  group,  individuals  differ 
importantly  in  the  degree  to  which  they  are  concerned  with  per- 
sonal success  or  are  motivated  to  perform  at  a  high  level  of  pro- 
ficiency in  a  variety  of  situations.  They  differ,  that  is,  in  the 
strength  of  their  need-achievement  motive.  An  individual  is  said 
to  have  an  achievement  motive  when  either  positive  or  negative 
affect  results  from  his  perception  of  his  own  performance  relative 
to  one  or  another  standard  of  excellence. 

McClelland  and  his  collaborators  base  their  estimates  of  the 
strength  of  this  motive  upon  subjects'  imaginative  responses  to 
pictures  like  those  of  the  Thematic  Apperception  Test.  The  sub- 
jects are  told  that  the  test  is  one  of  creative  imagination  and  that 
their  task  is  to  write  vivid  and  dramatic  stories  about  each  of  the 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  185 

pictures.  The  stories  are  scored  for  degree  of  achievement  motiva- 
tion by  noting  whether  affectively  toned  evaluative  statements  are 
made  about  the  performances  of  individuals  in  the  stories.  McClel- 
land has  presented  some  evidence  to  suggest  that  high  need- 
achievers  are  also  those  who  habitually  strive  to  succeed  in  various 
situations.  If  this  is  the  case,  then  these  should  be  the  individuals 
who  have  best  learned  to  make  the  kinds  of  responses  that  are 
consistent  with  their  efforts  to  succeed.  According  to  the  view  we 
are  exploring,  these  motivating  responses  may  be,  in  considerable 
measure,  evoked  by  self-administered  verbal  commands. 

Consider,  for  example,  the  student  who  tries  to  do  well  in  every 
examination  or  classroom  situation.  Let  us  assume  that  whenever 
he  finds  himself  being  tested,  the  cues  accompanying  such  situa- 
tions elicit  learned  verbal  responses  such  as,  "I  must  try  to  do  well, 
for  if  I  fail,  my  family  and  my  sweetheart  will  be  deeply  grieved." 
The  phrase  "I  must  try  to  do  well,"  in  this  example  is  believed 
to  function  as  a  motivator  in  precisely  the  same  way  as  do  parental 
verbal  commands  like  "Hurry!"  or  "Pay  attention!"  In  short,  self- 
administered  "try-hard"  instructions  such  as  these  may  constitute 
the  basic  "acquired  drive"  of  the  high  need-achiever  and  may  be 
used  by  him  in  a  wide  variety  of  circumstances. 

Our  case  for  this  interpretation  would  be  strengthened  if  it 
could  be  demonstrated  that  high  need-achievers  are  more  likely 
than  low  need-achievers  to  provide  themselves  with  instructions 
of  this  general  sort,  that  all  individuals  are  more  likely  to  employ 
these  self-instructions  in  times  of  stress  than  at  other  times,  and 
that  high  need-achievers  tend  to  use  the  "try-hard"  instructions  in 
a  wide  variety  of  different  situations  where  efficient  performance 
is  expected  of  them. 

Although  self-administered  commands  have  been  assumed  to 
operate  motivationally  because  they  evoke  learned  responses,  we 
have  not  yet  considered  what  these  motivating  responses  might 
be  like.  One  possibility  is  that  the  commands  or  exhortations 
elicit  an  over-all  increase  in  bodily  tension.  As  is  well  known  from 
the  experimental  studies  of  Bills  (1927)  and  Courts  (1942),  mod- 
erate degrees  of  muscular  tension  tend  to  facilitate  not  only  per- 
formance in  motor-skills  tasks  but  even  the  learning  of  nonsense 
syllables.  Thus  the  motivating  effects  of  self-instructions  to  "try 


186  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

hard"  or  "to  pay  attention,"  might  be  ascribed  to  increases  in 
general  bodily  tonus.  Presumably,  the  steps  in  the  learning  process 
through  which  such  increases  in  tension  come  to  be  associated 
with  verbal  commands  could  be  outlined  without  great  difficulty. 

A  second  alternative  is  that  the  "try-hard"  types  of  self-instruc- 
tions serve  as  conditioned  stimuli  for  the  arousal  of  motivating 
emotional  states.  Suppose  a  student  says  to  himself  "I  must  study 
hard  for  this  exam,  because  if  I  don't,  I'll  flunk  out  of  school." 
Clearly,  these  self-instructions  could  evoke  anxiety  or  fear  of  fail- 
ure, which  could  have  motivating  effects  of  the  kinds  we  have 
already  considered.  Or,  if  the  verbal  cues  have  become  conditioned 
to  fractional  anticipatory  goal  reactions,  these  expectancies  might 
provide  the  required  motivational  increments. 

While  the  anticipation  of  an  unpleasant  event  (anxiety)  and 
the  anticipation  of  a  pleasant  event  (r^  or  appetite)  are  thus  seen, 
in  addition  to  heightened  tension,  as  possible  sources  of  motivation 
when  aroused  by  self-instructions,  in  any  practical  situation  it  may 
be  diflBcult  to  tell  whether  one  or  all  are  functionally  present. 
Probably  all  are  frequently  involved  in  complex  situations  with 
human  beings.  As  McClelland  and  his  collaborators  have  noted, 
the  anticipation  of  a  reward  for  good  performance  is  often  accom- 
panied by  the  fear  that  failure  will  negate  the  reward,  or  even 
result  in  actual  punishment. 

Are  Primary-need  States  Condltionable? 

Occasionally  people  remark  that  they  sometimes  are  not  hungry 
until  they  find  themselves  in  a  familiar  restaurant,  whereupon 
they  suddenly  become  hungry.  Such  casual  descriptions  cannot  be 
taken  too  seriously,  but  they  suggest  the  possibility  that  a  stimulus 
might  acquire  the  power  to  elicit  hunger  if  it  has  been  present  on 
numerous  occasions  when  an  organism  has  been  hungry.  If  hunger 
can  thus  be  conditioned,  and  if  it  affects  other  responses  in  mo- 
tivational ways,  it  obviously  qualifies  as  a  learned  source  of  drive. 

Although  a  number  of  early  observations  are  consistent  with 
this  notion  of  the  conditionability  of  hunger,  none  is  entirely 
convincing.  Skinner  (1933),  for  example,  believed  that  the  phe- 
nomenon had  been  demonstrated  in  his  studies  of  running-wheel 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  187 

activity  in  the  rat.  He  reports  that  rats,  during  their  initial  expe- 
riences on  the  wheel,  when  tested  for  six-hour  periods  would  run 
at  a  fairly  constant  rate  for  about  the  first  three  hours.  But  during 
the  last  half  of  the  period,  their  rates  of  running  tended  to  decline. 
If  they  were  fed  at  the  end  of  the  six-hour  running  period  for 
several  days,  however,  a  "conditioned  hunger  cycle"  was  said  to 
have  been  developed,  since  the  previously  observed  slowing  down 
now  tended  to  disappear.  Skinner  reports  that  a  number  of  rats 
exhibited  this  effect,  but  the  records  of  only  a  single  animal  are 
presented,  and  apparently  no  suitable  controls  were  run.  The 
phenomenon,  therefore,  though  possibly  genuine,  need  not  be 
interpreted  as  indicating  that  hunger  has  become  conditioned  to 
cues  accompanying  the  passage  of  time.  Skinner's  rats  may  simply 
have  been  acquiring  more  skill  in  running,  or  cyclic  feeding  may 
have  led  to  the  conditioning  of  motivating  fractional  anticipatory 
responses  which  could  counteract  fatigue  during  the  latter  part  of 
the  test  period  (cf.  Birch  et  al.,  1958). 

A  somewhat  similar  phenomenon,  also  suggestive  of  conditioned 
hunger,  has  been  reported  by  Slonaker  (1912)  and  by  Shirley 
( 1928)  in  their  studies  of  spontaneous  activity  in  the  rat.  According 
to  these  investigators,  when  rats  are  fed  at  the  same  hour  every 
day,  they  develop  a  tendency  to  become  increasingly  active  as 
the  feeding  time  approaches,  and  this  activity  rhythm  can  be 
altered  by  changing  the  feeding  schedule.  Again,  however,  these 
observations  do  not  constitute  acceptable  proof  of  the  presence 
of  conditioned  hunger. 

Perhaps  the  first  experiment  designed  specifically  to  demonstrate 
the  conditionability  of  hunger  was  performed  by  Anderson  (1941 ) . 
Since  he  believed  that  hunger  could  become  associated  with 
external  cues  and  aroused  by  them,  he  referred  to  conditioned 
hunger  as  an  "externalized  drive."  He  used  several  groups  of  rats  in 
his  studies,  but  only  two  groups  are  of  special  interest  here.  One  of 
these  was  given  extensive  training  in  running  a  multiple-unit  maze 
for  food  reward  while  hungry.  A  comparable  group,  that  served 
as  a  control,  was  given  no  maze  training  initially.  Both  groups  were 
then  fed  until  satiated  and  were  allowed  to  run  through  a  second 
maze  but  without  food  reward  of  any  kind.  The  animals  in  the 
pretrained  group  performed  better  in  the  second  maze  than  did 


188  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

the  controls.  From  these  results  Anderson  concluded  that  the 
second  maze,  because  of  its  general  similarity  to  the  first,  served 
as  a  stimulus  to  arouse  a  learned  drive  in  the  pretrained  animals 
but  not  in  the  untrained  controls. 

Interpretations  of  the  Anderson  experiment  are  somewhat  haz- 
ardous, since  each  group  consisted  of  only  five  animals  and  no 
statistical  evaluations  of  the  differences  were  presented.  Moreover, 
Siegel  (1943),  using  a  four-unit  linear  maze,  could  not  confirm 
Anderson's  results.  Siegel's  animals  were  given  satiation  trials 
interposed  during  the  learning  series,  but  neither  time  nor  error 
scores  on  these  trials  exhibited  the  progressive  decrement  one 
would  expect  on  the  "externalized  drive"  hypothesis.  As  in  the 
case  of  Skinner's  experiment,  however,  Anderson's  results  may 
be  genuine  and  yet  due  to  factors  other  than  conditioned  hunger 
or  externalized  drive.  For  instance,  the  similarity  of  the  two  mazes 
could  mediate  the  transfer  of  fractional  anticipatory  eating  re- 
sponses for  the  experimental  animals,  and  these  responses,  rather 
than  conditioned  hunger,  could  provide  the  motivation  for  the 
second  learning.  Or  the  control  animals,  since  they  were  not 
handled  as  frequently  as  were  the  experimental  rats,  might  have 
run  less  well  in  the  second  maze  because  they  were  more  emo- 
tional. It  is  also  clear  that  the  experimental  animals,  after  having 
been  repeatedly  rewarded  for  running  in  the  first  maze,  would 
have  a  stronger  generalized  tendency  to  run  in  the  second  maze, 
even  though  satiated.  If  so,  they  would  tend  to  reach  the  goal  box 
sooner  than  the  controls,  as  indeed  they  did,  and  would  thus  be 
more  immediately  rewarded  by  the  secondary  reinforcing  cues  of 
the  goal  box  or  by  being  removed  from  the  maze.  And  finally,  the 
experimental  animals,  who  had  been  on  a  deprivation  schedule 
for  many  more  days  than  the  controls,  might  have  had  a  greater 
bodily  need  for  food.  If  so,  the  laboratory  operation  of  inducing 
satiation  in  both  groups  might  leave  a  greater  residual  hunger  drive 
in  the  experimental  rats  than  in  the  controls.  Differences  in  resid- 
ual hunger  following  apparent  satiation — it  is  rather  difficult, 
incidentally,  to  satiate  rats  completely — might  account  for  the 
results  if  coupled  with  reinforcements  provided  by  the  goal-box 
cues  or  by  removal  from  the  maze. 

Other  attempts  to  demonstrate  the  conditionability  of  hunger 


LEARNED   RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF   DRIVE  189 

have  been  reported  by  Myers  and  Miller  (1954)  and  by  Calvin, 
Bicknell,  and  Sperling  (1953).  In  the  Myers-Miller  experiment, 
hungry  rats  were  placed  in  the  white  side  of  the  same  box  used 
in  Miller's  fear-conditioning  experiments  and  were  allowed  to  run 
into  the  black  side  for  food  when  they  touched  the  guillotine  door. 
This  preliminary  training  was  designed  to  associate  the  cues  of 
the  white  box  with  hunger.  Three  groups  of  rats  were  given  10, 
30,  and  70  food-rewarded  trials  of  this  kind.  A  fourth  group  of 
control  animals  received  no  comparable  training.  To  test  for  the 
presence  of  an  acquired  hunger  drive,  the  animals  were  placed, 
when  thoroughly  satiated,  in  the  white  box,  and  the  operating 
mechanism  was  so  arranged  that  if  the  rats  pressed  a  small  lever 
the  door  would  open,  and  access  to  the  black  box  would  be  per- 
mitted. Thus  the  problem  was  whether  rats  that  had  been  quite 
hungry  in  the  presence  of  certain  stimuli  (white-box  cues)  would, 
when  satiated,  learn  to  perform  a  new  response,  the  only  conse- 
quence of  which  was  the  opportunity  to  escape  from  those  stimuli. 
If  the  white-box  cues  aroused  a  learned  hunger  reaction,  escape 
from  them  should  have  resulted  in  a  decline  in  hunger  that  might 
reinforce  the  learning  of  the  new  response.  Since  all  four  groups 
learned  the  new  response  about  equally  well,  the  results  failed  to 
indicate  that  the  association  of  the  white-box  cues  with  hunger 
had  led  to  the  formation  of  a  learned  hunger  drive.  Through 
additional  experimentation  Myers  and  Miller  were  able  to  conclude 
that  the  learning  was  perhaps  motivated  by  a  tendency  to  explore 
unfamiliar  places,  but  they  rejected  the  notion  that  hunger,  as 
such,  was  conditioned  by  their  procedures. 

There  are  a  number  of  plausible  explanations  for  these  negative 
results.  For  one,  hunger  may  be  a  slowly  changing  state  and,  there- 
fore, unlike  phasic  responses,  simply  cannot  be  readily  conditioned. 
For  another,  the  animals  in  running  from  white  to  black  were 
obviously  exposed  to  both  white  and  black  cues  when  hungry,  and 
hence  the  difference  between  the  tendencies  of  the  two  sides  to 
evoke  hunger  may  have  been  extremely  small.  Or  the  process  of 
satiating  the  animals,  prior  to  testing,  may  be  an  operation  that 
prevents  conditioned  hunger  from  occurring  to  any  detectable 
degree.  If  one  assumes,  for  instance,  that  conditioned  hunger,  if  it 
exists,  might  be  a  response  of  the  contractile  portions  of  the 


190  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

stomach,  it  seems  likely  that  complete  satiation  would  so  tightly 
fill  the  stomach  as  to  inhibit  any  learned  contractions. 

In  the  experiment  of  Calvin,  Bicknell,  and  Sperling,  two  groups 
of  rats  were  given  preliminary  training  in  a  very  distinctive  en- 
vironment, consisting  principally  of  a  triangularly  shaped  box  with 
black-and-white  striped  walls.  The  training  consisted  simply  in 
placing  the  animals  in  the  box  without  food  for  30  minutes  each 
day  for  24  days.  One  group  had  been  deprived  of  food  for  22 
hours  at  the  time  of  these  trials  and  the  other  had  gone  without 
food  for  only  1  hour.  According  to  the  authors,  the  tactual  and 
visual  cues  of  the  box  should  have  acquired  more  of  a  tendency 
to  elicit  conditioned  hunger  in  the  22-hour  group  than  in  the 
1-hour  group.  Tests  for  the  presence  of  acquired  hunger  were 
conducted  by  noting  the  amount  of  food  consumed  by  both  groups 
when  they  were  permitted  to  eat  in  the  same  box  under  an  inter- 
mediate and  identical  level  of  food  deprivation  (approximately  12 
hours).  The  four  eating  periods  were  15  minutes  long  and  were 
spaced  over  a  two-day  period  at  12-hour  intervals.  Under  these 
conditions,  the  formerly  hungry  group  ate  more  in  the  triangular 
box  than  did  the  other  group.  Unfortunately,  certain  control 
groups  necessary  for  an  unambiguous  conditioned-hunger  interpre- 
tation were  not  included  in  the  experiment.  Because  of  this  omis- 
sion it  is  impossible  to  tell  whether  the  22-hour  group's  rate  of 
eating  was  accelerated,  as  a  consequence  of  its  supposed  acquired 
drive,  or  whether  the  1-hour  group's  eating  rate  was  depressed. 
Certainly,  the  possibility  that  the  1-hour  animals  had  learned  to 
lie  down  and  sleep  in  the  box,  and  that  this  response  tended  to 
interfere  with  eating,  cannot  be  dismissed  without  further  experi- 
mentation. It  should  also  be  noted  that  the  major  result  of  the 
experiment,  however  interpreted,  was  not  confirmed  by  Siegel  and 
MacDonnel  (1954)  in  a  careful  repetition  of  the  Calvin  et  al. 
investigation. 

It  would  appear  from  this  brief  review  of  the  principal  literature 
in  this  area  that  only  one  conclusion  is  tenable  at  the  present 
time:  there  is  no  convincing  experimental  evidence  to  support  the 
contention  that  hunger,  like  fear,  can,  after  training,  be  elicited 
as  a  learned  response  to  a  conditioned  stimulus.  Such  evidence  as 
does  exist  is  either  inherently  inconclusive  or  can  be  interpreted 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  191 

with  equal  plausibility  by  other  hypotheses  than  that  of  a  learned 
hunger  drive. 


Summary 

We  have  been  concerned  in  this  chapter  with  motivational  sys- 
tems that  have  traditionally  been  described  by  the  terms  "second- 
ary drives"  or  "learned  drives."  These  phenomena  occupy  a  place 
of  considerable  importance  in  contemporary  theories,  there  being 
many  who  hold  that  human  behavior  is  governed  more  by  these 
acquired  drives  than  by  biogenic  needs.  At  the  outset,  however, 
it  was  suggested  that  the  traditional  terminology  be  discarded  in 
favor  of  the  phrase  "learned  sources  of  drive,"  since  there  appears  ] 
to  be  little  reason  for  supposing  that  the  effects  of  motivation  ^k"*^  ^ 
on  behavior  are  multiple  rather  than  unitary. 

From  a  purely  descriptive  standpoint,  a  learned  source  of  drive 
is  defined  by  the  observation  that  an  associative  variable  affects 
responses  other  than  the  one  being  learned  as  though  a  motiva- 
tional variable  were  present.  Learned  responses  appear  to  have 
motivationlike  effects  upon  other  responses  either  because  an 
increment  is  added  to  a  nonspecific  drive,  or  because  distinctive 
cues  are  produced  that  alter  habit  strengths,  or  for  both  reasons.  In 
any  event,  the  major  tasks  facing  the  student  of  acquired  sources 
of  drive  are  those  of  discovering  which  kinds  of  learned  responses 
function  motivationally,  of  delineating  the  laws  that  govern  the 
acquisition  and  extinction  of  these  motivating  responses,  and  of 
determining  the  breadth  of  influence  of  motivating  responses  and 
the  mechanisms  through  which  the  effects  are  produced. 

A  major  section  of  the  chapter  has  been  devoted  to  the  analysis 
and  discussion  of  studies  purporting  to  show  that  conditioned  fear 
or  anxiety  affects  certain  indicant  responses  as  though  it  were  a 
motivational  variable.  Three  groups  of  investigations  of  this  kind 
have  been  identified.  Those  in  the  first  group  show  that  if  a  refer- 
ence response  is  evoked  while  a  conditioned  stimulus  for  fear  is 
present,  the  reference  activity  tends  to  be  enhanced  or  augmented. 
This  is  consistent  with  the  activation  criterion  of  motivation. 
Studies  in  a  second  group  have  repeatedly  demonstrated  that  fear 
reduction,  defined  in  terms  of  the  cessation  of  a  presumed  fear- 


192  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

arousing  CS,  serves  as  a  reinforcement  for  the  learning  of  new 
reactions.  The  capacity  to  lead  to  new  learning  is  also  one  of  the 
commonly  proposed  criteria  for  the  identification  of  motivational 
variables.  A  third  group  of  experiments  consists  of  those  in  which 
the  evocation  of  conditioned  fear  results  in  the  inhibition  or 
abandonment  of  an  indicant  response.  In  so  far  as  these  studies 
involve  the  procedure  of  arousing  fear  after  the  elicitation  of  the 
indicant  reaction,  they,  too,  are  consistent  with  general  concep- 
tions of  what  constitutes  a  motivational  effect. 

A  summary  of  the  variables  of  which  fear  seems  to  be  a  function 
indicates  that  these  are,  in  many  instances,  associative  variables 
of  demonstrated  significance  for  the  conditioning  of  other  re- 
sponses. For  example,  number  of  conditioning  trials,  intensity  of 
the  UCSy  number  of  extinction  trials,  and  distribution  of  practice 
are  all  known  to  affect  the  strength  of  conditioned  fear. 

Although  a  large  percentage  of  the  experimental  studies  of  fear 
have  been  carried  out  with  animals,  there  are  ample  reasons  for 
the  belief  that  acquired  anxieties  also  play  a  major  role  in  the 
motivational  structure  of  human  subjects.  The  direct  association 
of  neutral  and  painful  stimuli  may  account  for  certain  human 
fears,  but  the  acquisition  of  most  of  them  seems  to  depend  upon 
higher-order  conditioning  involving  verbal  cues  in  the  roles  of  both 
conditioned  and  unconditioned  stimuli. 

The  simple  classical-conditioning  paradigm,  though  moderately 
adequate  for  fear,  cannot  be  applied  directly  to  such  so-called 
acquired  drives  as  those  for  money,  affection,  power,  and  security. 
This  is  because  one  can  neither  identify  the  response  that  is  sup- 
posed to  have  been  learned  in  each  case,  nor  specify  an  originally 
adequate  unconditioned  stimulus  capable  of  eliciting  the  response 
at  the  outset.  It  seems  likely,  however,  that  anxiety  plays  an  im- 
portant role  as  the  motivational  basis  for  several  of  these  alleged 
drives.  In  particular  it  is  suggested  that  cues  indicating  a  lack  of 
affection,  or  of  power,  or  of  money,  can  acquire  tendencies  to 
elicit  conditioned  anxiety.  Moreover,  activities  involved  in  seeking 
money,  power,  and  so  on,  whenever  they  are  successful,  must 
inevitably  counteract  the  anxiety-arousing  cues  occasioned  by  their 
absence,  and  hence  will  be  reinforced  by  anxiety  reduction. 

The  final  sections  of  the  chapter  are  devoted  to  the  question  of 


LEARNED  RESPONSES  AS  SOURCES  OF  DRIVE  193 

whether  learned  responses  other  than  anxiety  can  be  meaningfully 
said  to  have  motivational  effects  upon  reference  activities.  Three 
somewhat  different  answers  to  this  question  are  considered.  The 
first,  a  conception  developed  by  Hull  and  Spence,  assumes  that 
consummatory  goal  responses  become  classically  conditioned  to 
cues  present  at  the  goal,  and  that  fractional  components  of  the 
total  response  complex  can  be  elicited  in  advance  of  goal  attain- 
ment. In  addition  to  providing  distinctive  cues,  these  fractional 
anticipatory  goal  responses  are  assumed  to  add  increments  to  the 
organism's  total  drive  level  and  thereby  to  affect  other  reactions 
motivationally. 

A  second  conception,  McClelland's  affective-arousal  model,  en- 
tails the  fundamental  assumption  that  all  motives  are  learned  and 
function  both  to  guide  and  to  motivate  behavior.  Motives  are 
acquired  as  the  result  of  the  pairing  of  stimulus  cues  with  changes 
in  affect,  the  motive  being  a  conditioned  affectively  toned  expec- 
tation of  the  coming  of  either  pleasant  or  unpleasant  events. 

The  third  conception  of  learned  sources  of  drive,  proposed  by 
the  writer,  emphasizes  the  possibility  that  self-administered  verbal 
commands  might  acquire,  through  a  process  of  conditioning,  the 
power  to  affect  overt  reactions  motivationally.  These  verbal  com- 
mands may  produce  their  effects  by  leading  to  increased  general 
muscular  tonus,  by  evoking  conditioned  emotional  responses,  or 
by  the  production  of  stimuli  to  which  facilitating  responses  have 
been  attached. 

In  the  final  section  of  the  chapter  the  question  is  raised  whether 
a  primary  need  such  as  hunger  can  become  conditioned  to  a 
neutral  stimulus  and  thereby  come  to  qualify  as  a  learned  source 
of  drive.  Experimental  attempts  to  demonstrate  the  phenomenon 
are  reviewed  and  the  conclusion  reached  that  no  convincing  evi- 
dence for  the  conditionability  of  hunger  has  yet  been  presented. 


CHAPTER 


6 


Motivational  Consequences  of 
Frustration  and  Conflict 


In  recent  years  motivational  theorists  have  become  increasingly 
concerned  with  the  possibility  that  the  thwarting  of  an  ongoing 
response  has  behavioral  consequences  resembling  those  produced 
by  the  manipulation  of  motivational  variables.  The  idea  that 
response  interference  may  be  followed  by  emotional  or  motiva- 
tional effects  is  not  new,  however,  and  references  to  the  energizing 
and/or  disorganizing  effects  of  thwarting  abound  in  literary  and 
philosophical  works.  This  same  idea  also  appears  in  the  writings 
of  clinical  psychologists  and  personality  theorists,  where  it  is  com- 
mon to  encounter  the  statement  that  failure  to  achieve  an  expected 
goal  may  lead  to  an  increase  in  emotional  or  other  tension  and 
that  such  tension  may  modify  subsequent  behavior.  In  psycho- 
analytic writings  this  general  position  is  expressed  in  terms  of  the 
thwarting  of  libidinal  energy  and  its  redirection  into  new  chan- 
nels, culminating  in  the  phenomena  of  conversion  and  sublima- 
tion. 

We  shall  not  attempt  to  trace  in  detail  the  history  of  the  more 
technical  formulations  of  this  conception,  but  Lewin  (1931)  ap-l 

194 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  195 

pears  to  have  been  among  the  first  to  present  a  relatively  clear 
statement  of  the  hypothesis.  Thus,  in  his  discussion  of  the  conse- 
quences of  conflict,  he  states  that  the  opposed  field  forces  in  a 
conflict  situation,  especially  when  there  is  an  outer  barrier,  lead 
to  increases  in  total  tension.  Lewin  did  not  refer  specifically  to 
the  motivational  properties  of  this  heightened  tension,  but  some 
such  concept  was  probably  intended,  since  augmented  tension 
was  said  to  produce  restless  behavior  which,  in  conjunction  with 
the  directive  characteristics  (forces)  of  the  specific  situation,  could 
lead  to  affective  outbursts  such  as  fits  of  anger. 

Some  years  later,  Miller  and  Stevenson  (1936)  advanced  a 
similar  hypothesis  in  an  effort  to  explain  some  unexpected  experi- 
mental findings.  In  their  investigation,  hungry  rats  were  first 
trained  to  run  down  a  short  straight  alley  for  food  and  were  then 
given  a  number  of  nonreinforced  (frustrating)  trials.  During  these 
trials,  it  was  observed  that  the  animals  exhibited  an  ".  .  .  appar- 
ent energization  of  certain  acts  such  as  sniffing,  tossing  of  the  head, 
and  cleaning  of  the  whiskers.  These  acts  frequently  occurred  in 
almost  explosive  manner — much  more  vigorously  than  during  the 
first  learning  trials  in  the  alley  or  than  during  the  period  in  the 
cages  immediately  preceding  the  runs"  (p.  227).  In  discussing 
these  observations.  Miller  and  Stevenson  hypothesized  that  non- 
reward  may  have  led  to  a  conflict  between  the  learned  responses 
of  eating  and  the  responses  elicited  by  the  empty  food  dish.  They 
assumed,  moreover,  that  the  conflict-produced,  proprioceptive  stim- 
ulation could  have  facilitated  other  actions  much  as  hand  tension 
was  known  to  facilitate  the  knee  jerk. 

Subsequent  to  this  proposal  by  Miller  and  Stevenson,  somewhat 
similar  hypotheses  were  advanced  by  a  number  of  workers  (e.g., 
French,  1944;  Rohrer,  1949;  Brown  and  Jacobs,  1949;  Sheffield, 
1950;  Amsel,  1951;  Brown  and  Farber,  1951;  Spence,  1951b;  Hull, 
1952;  Amsel  and  Roussel,  1952).  The  precise  wording  varies  from 
writer  to  writer,  but  the  essential  similarity  of  the  several  views 
permits  us  to  state  the  hypothesis  in  the  following  general  form: 
when  stimuli  normally  capable  of  eliciting  a  response  are  present, 
but  the  response  is  prevented  from  running  its  usual  course,  be- 
havior may  be  affected  as  though  a  motivational  variable  had  been 
introduced.  Most  versions  of  the  concept  (cf.,  e.g.,  Lawson  and 


196  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 


Marx,  1958)  include  the  specific  assumption  that  frustration  adds 
an  increment  to  general  drive,  but  as  we  shall  indicate,  the  be- 
havioral consequences  of  thwarting  can  often  be  attributed  with 
equal  justification  to  the  operation  of  associative  mechanisms. 


Methods  of  Producing  Thwarting 

At  first  sight  it  might  seem  as  though  the  simplest  of  procedures 
would  suffice  to  bring  about  response  interference  and  that  its 
occurrence  could  be  easily  and  unambiguously  ascertained.  Unfor- 
tunately, the  process  is  not  always  so  simple,  and  in  any  practical 
experiment,  therefore,  the  frustrating  procedures  must  be  chosen 
and  introduced  with  considerable  care.  Because  of  this  necessity 
it  is  desirable  at  this  point  to  consider  some  of  the  methods  that 
have  been  used  to  prevent  responses  from  running  their  usual 
courses.  Throughout  the  remainder  of  the  chapter  the  term 
thwarting  will  be  used  simply  to  mean  response  interference,  while 
the  term  frustration  will  be  retained  to  denote  the  state,  condition, 
or  response  assumed  to  be  produced  by  thwarting. 

Physical  Barriers  as  Frustrating  Agents.  One  of  the  commonest 
ways  of  producing  thwarting  is  by  the  use  of  physical  restraint  of 
one  kind  or  another.  With  animals  as  subjects,  these  restraints 
may  take  the  form  of  solid  barriers  in  a  maze  path,  restraining 
harnesses,  delay  chambers,  treadmills,  locked  Skinner-box  levers, 
and  locked  food-dish  covers.  Such  restrictive  devices  may  partially 
or  completely  prevent  the  subject's  approach  to  a  goal;  they  may 
be  introduced  at  different  points  in  the  response  sequence;  and 
they  may  be  interposed  for  var}'ing  lengths  of  time.  If  a  response 
is  to  be  thwarted  and  frustration  is  to  result,  blocking  devices 
must  be  introduced  into  situations  where  cues  normallv  capable 
of  eliciting  the  to-be-blocked  response  are  present.  And  from  an 
ideal  point  of  view  the  introduction  of  thwarting  devices  should 
result  in  the  smallest  possible  change  in  the  original  stimulus 
complex.  Thus,  for  example,  it  would  be  preferable  to  lock  a 
formerly  unlocked  food-dish  cover  than  to  prevent  the  animal 
from  having  access  to  it  by  the  interposition  of  an  opaque  door. 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATfON  AND  CONFLICT  197 

With  the  latter  method  many  of  the  originally  present  cues  are 
eliminated  and  new  ones  are  introduced. 

Thwarting  Produced  by  the  Removal  of  Maintaining  Stimuli.  ■ 
A  second  frustration-inducing  method  involves  the  removal  of 
some  of  the  stimulus  objects  that  normally  function  to  support 
the  response  while  leaving  the  remaining  stimuli  unaltered.  For 
example,  food  may  be  removed  from  its  usual  position  in  the  goal 
box  of  a  maze  or  the  lever  may  be  withdrawn  from  the  Skinner 
box.  Under  these  conditions  eating  and  bar  pressing,  respectively, 
are  prevented  from  occurring,  and  thwarting  should  result  since 
the  residual  cues  still  tend  to  elicit  the  response.  This  method  may 
produce  a  more  marked  alteration  of  the  stimulus  complex  than 
the  first  method,  but  in  either  instance  the  response  is  physically 
prevented  from  occurring.  The  two  methods  may  be  regarded  as 
different,  because  they  lead  either  to  the  blocking  of  different 
responses  or  to  the  blocking  of  the  same  response  at  different 
points.  Thus  if  the  cover  of  a  food  dish  is  locked,  all  of  the  re- 
sponses of  lifting  the  cover  and  of  seizing,  chewing,  and  swallowing 
the  food  are  blocked.  But  if  the  cover  is  left  unlatched  and  food 
is  removed,  only  the  responses  of  grasping  and  ingesting  the  food 
are  thwarted. 

Thwarting  by  the  Elicitation  of  Incompatible  Responses.  A  third 
way  of  preventing  the  appearance  of  a  response  is  to  introduce 
new  stimuli  known  to  be  capable  of  eliciting  reactions  incompatible 
with  the  one  to  be  thwarted.  If  an  individual  has  been  trained 
to  lift  his  hand  from  a  key  when  a  red  light  comes  on,  the  re- 
sponse may  be  inhibited  if  a  green  light,  to  which  he  has  previously 
been  told  to  press  downward,  is  presented  simultaneously  with  the 
red.  These  procedures  define  what  is  typically  described  as  a  con- 
flict situation.  It  differs  from  the  frustration  situations  we  have  just 
described  in  that  the  thwarted  response  is  not  inhibited  or  blocked 
by  external  restraints  but  by  a  competitive  tendency  to  make  an 
incompatible  reaction.  Conflict-induced  thwarting  of  this  kind 
could  also  be  achieved  by  first  associating  a  given  response  with 
one  set  of  cues  and  then  training  the  subject  to  perform  an  incom- 
patible reaction  to  the  same  cues.  Since  this  is  what  often  happens 
in  discrimination-learning  situations,  it  serves  to  emphasize  the 


198  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

view  (Melton,  1941)  that  frustration  is  an  almost  inevitable  ac- 
companiment of  all  learning. 

All  of  these  response-interference  methods  may  be  used  with 
either  animal  or  human  subjects.  But  because  of  the  language 
facility  of  human  subjects,  additional  techniques  of  thwarting 
may  be  employed  with  them  that  cannot  be  applied  to  animals. 
For  example,  an  individual  may  be  said  to  be  thwarted  if,  after 
he  has  completed  a  task  given  him  by  the  experimenter,  he  is  told 
that  his  performance  was  very  poor.  In  many  such  situations  the 
subject's  goal  is  to  obtain  the  experimenter's  approval.  To  withhold 
such  approval  or  to  tell  the  subject  that  he  has  performed  poorly 
is  to  prevent  him  from  reaching  his  goal.  Verbal  commands  may 
also  be  used  with  human  subjects  (and  after  special  training,  with 
animals)  to  produce  a  cessation  of  ongoing  behavior,  to  elicit 
conflicting  response  tendencies,  and  the  like.  Most  such  instances 
of  response  blocking  correspond  to  what  has  just  been  described 
as  the  competing-response  method,  and  hence  no  further  discussion 
of  them  is  necessary. 

Criteria  of  Thvs^arting 

The  above  methods  for  preventing  the  initiation,  continuation, 
or  completion  of  a  response  are  commonly  found  in  studies  of 
frustration,  but  the  use  of  one  or  more  of  them  does  not  guarantee 
that  the  response  has  indeed  been  thwarted.  Hence  the  conclusion 
that  blocking  has  actually  taken  place  usually  rests,  though  often 
in  an  implicit  manner,  upon  the  satisfaction  of  one  or  more  specific 
criteria  of  thwarting.  The  need  for  such  criteria  can  be  made  clear 
by  considering  a  specific  example. 

Suppose  a  dog  is  moving  toward  a  bone  on  the  other  side  of  a 
room  and  that  when  we  grasp  him  by  the  collar  he  stops.  From 
such  an  observation  we  might  conclude  that  his  approach  responses 
have  been  frustrated,  but  it  is  also  possible  that  he  was  going  to 
stop  anyway  at  the  instant  we  seized  his  collar.  If  the  second 
alternative  is  true,  then  clearly  the  dog's  approach  behavior  has 
not  in  fact  been  thwarted.  It  is  improbable,  of  course,  that  the 
end  of  a  response  sequence  and  the  thwarting  operation  will  acci- 
dentally coincide  in  this  manner  on  many  occasions.  But  since 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  199 

the  possibility  does  exist,  it  is  desirable  to  have  definite  criteria 
for  deciding  whether  a  response  has  suffered  interference. 

Repetitive,  Partial  Responses  as  an  Index  of  Thwarting.  Perhaps 
the  best  basis  for  concluding  that  a  response  has  been  thwarted 
is  the  observation  that  the  subject  continues  to  make  responses  of 
the  kind  that  were  exhibited  just  prior  to  the  introduction  of  the 
conditions  designed  to  be  thwarting.  Thus  if  the  dog  in  the  pre- 
ceding example  lunges  repeatedly  against  the  restraint  imposed 
on  its  collar,  his  behavior  serves  as  an  index  of  response  inter- 
ference. Although  the  lunges  are  truncated  or  fractional  parts  of 
the  original  approach  behavior  they  provide  support  for  the  belief 
that  if  the  restraint  had  not  been  imposed,  the  approach  would 
have  continued  beyond  the  point  of  blocking. 

Response  Resumption  as  a  Criterion  of  Thwarting.  A  second 
criterion  of  response  interference  involves  the  observation  that 
the  subject  resumes  his  original  behavior  following  the  removal 
of  the  supposedly  thwarting  conditions.  We  might,  for  example, 
train  a  cat  to  approach  a  white  square  at  the  end  of  a  short 
straight  alley  and  then  teach  it,  in  a  different  situation,  to  avoid 
a  black  circle.  If  the  black  circle  is  now  put  into  the  straight  alley 
beside  the  white  square,  the  cat  may  not  approach  to  the  end 
as  it  did  formerly.  This  change  in  behavior  is  suggestive  of  block- 
ing due  to  a  competing  (avoidance)  tendency.  But  we  can  be  much 
more  certain  that  the  approach  response  was  actually  blocked  by 
the  competing  response  and  was  not  momentarily  weakened  by 
other  factors,  if  the  approach  behavior  reappears  upon  removal  of 
the  black  circle.  Resumption  of  the  original  behavior  thus  seems 
to  indicate  blocking.  But  a  failure  to  resume  the  expected  response 
cannot  be  interpreted  to  mean  the  absence  of  thwarting.  Inter- 
ference might  have  occurred  when  the  black  circle  was  first  intro- 
duced, but  if  the  approach  tendency  were  weak  it  might  have  been 
extinguished  by  even  a  relatively  short  exposure  to  the  negative 
cue.  In  such  a  case  approach  would  not  reappear  following  the 
removal  of  the  black  circle. 

Response  Failure  as  a  Sign  of  Thwarting.  Still  a  third  criterion 
is  often  used  in  practical  experiments  on  frustration.  Though  less 
rigorous  than  the  first  two,  it  is  easier  to  apply.  Specifically,  if  a 
subject  has  always,  or  nearly  always,  exhibited  a  concrete  bit  of 


200  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

behavior  in  a  given  situation,  and  if  we  have  observed  this  on  a 
relatively  large  number  of  occasions,  a  sudden  failure  to  perform 
in  the  expected  manner  suggests  that  thwarting  may  have  occurred. 
The  degree  of  confidence  we  may  have  in  reaching  this  conclusion 
depends  upon  several  factors.  If  we  have  observed  the  behavior 
on  each  of  100  different  occasions  prior  to  the  critical  frustration 
trial,  we  can  be  more  confident  that  blocking  has  actually  occurred 
than  if  we  have  seen  the  response  on  only  five  previous  occasions. 
The  higher  the  probability  of  response  evocation,  therefore,  the 
stronger  the  conviction  that  response  failure  denotes  thwarting. 
But  it  must  be  remembered  that  response  failure,  due  to  the 
removal  of  most  or  all  of  the  original  conditioned  stimuli,  is  not 
a  legitimate  instance  of  thwarting.  If  the  appropriate  stimuli  are 
eliminated,  the  tendency  for  the  response  to  occur  will  be  negli- 
gible, and  by  definition,  neither  thwarting  nor  frustration  can  be 
produced.  Thus,  for  example,  a  hungry  person  who  has  been  for- 
bidden to  eat  should  be  far  less  frustrated  in  a  bare  room  than  in  a 
food-filled  restaurant.  Presumably  frustration  will  be  maximal  if 
a  response  is  blocked  in  the  presence  of  all  the  original  stimuli 
with  which  it  has  been  associated. 


Associative  Interpretations  of  Behavior 
in   Frustrating  Situations 

Although  motivational  theorists  favor  the  view  that  response 
interference  leads  to  a  state  of  frustration  that  functions,  in  turn, 
to  increase  level  of  drive,  the  behavioral  consequences  of  thwarting 
can  often  be  explained  by  associative  rather  than  by  motivational 
principles.  The  kinds  of  behavior  requiring  interpretation  are 
usually  said  to  include  the  following:  trial-and-error  reactions  ap- 
parently directed  toward  the  circumvention  of  obstacles,  aggres- 
sive responses,  escape  or  withdrawal  responses,  disorganized  actions, 
anticipations  of  thwarting,  and  more  vigorous  or  more  persistent 
versions  of  the  originally  thwarted  reactions.  In  broad  outline, 
associative  interpretations  of  these  phenomena  are  identical  with 
associative  formulations  of  the  kinds  we  have  already  evaluated  in 
Chapter  4.  Only  a  few  comments  are  needed  at  this  point,  there- 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  201 

fore,  to  clarify  the  application  of  associative  theory  to  thwarting- 
induced  behavior. 

To  reiterate,  the  conceptual  core  of  any  associative  interpreta- 
tion is  the  notion  that  behavioral  changes  are  due  to  modified 
associative  strengths  resulting  from  changes  in  the  stimulus  situa- 
tion. That  such  a  conception  can  be  applied  to  behavior  in  frus- 
trating situations  becomes  clear  when  it  is  realized  that  response 
thwarting  must  inevitably  alter  external  and/or  internal  stimuli  to 
some  degree.  Existing  cues  to  which  the  thwarted  response  is  con- 
ditioned may  be  weakened  or  strengthened;  new  stimulus  com- 
ponents may  be  introduced,  bringing  with  them  previously  learned 
responses;  and  currently  effective  stimulus  elements  may  be  elim- 
inated. 

To  take  a  specific  example,  consider  Finch's  (1942)  observation 
that  chimpanzees,  who  customarily  obtain  water  from  a  spigot 
by  depressing  a  plunger,  tend  to  operate  the  plunger  with  aug- 
mented vigor  when  the  water  supply  is  turned  off.  As  Brown  and 
Farber  (1951)  have  noted,  several  different  versions  of  an  asso- 
ciative theory  can  be  applied  to  the  interpretation  of  these  observa- 
tions. First,  the  chimpanzees  may  have  learned  from  previous 
experiences  with  the  same  spigot  or  with  similar  ones  that  if 
water  is  not  forthcoming  after  a  gentle  push,  it  will  be  produced 
by  a  strong  push.  On  this  view,  vigorous  responses  are  simply 
transferred  from  old  to  new  situations  because  of  the  similarity 
of  the  stimuli  in  the  two  situations.  Second,  even  when  the  ex- 
ternal stimuli  of  the  frustration  situation  appear  to  differ  substan- 
tially from  those  which  the  subject  has  previously  experienced, 
the  transfer  of  learned  responses  to  the  frustrating  situation  could 
be  mediated  by  internal  cues  characteristic  of  the  state  or  condi- 
tion of  frustration.  This  mechanism  may  provide  an  explanation 
of  the  appearance  of  responses  that  seem  to  be  maladaptive  or 
inappropriate  to  the  frustration-inducing  situation.  Moreover,  in- 
ternal cues  uniquely  characteristic  of  frustration  could  underlie 
one's  ability  to  learn  to  differentiate  between  emotional  states  due 
to  thwarting  and  other  states  such  as  fear  or  worry.  Third,  within 
the  limitations  of  the  frustration  situation  itself,  behavior-modify- 
ing processes  are  at  work,  that  may  lead  to  the  appearance  of 
more  vigorous  movements.  That  is,  the  tendency  to  press  the 


202  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

plunger  gently  may  be  the  dominant  reaction  at  first.  But  if  water 
does  not  appear,  the  gentle  reaction  tends  to  become  extinguished 
and  may  be  replaced  by  responses  having  initially  weaker  asso- 
ciative strengths  but  greater  inherent  vigor. 

Concerning  other  reactions  to  thwarting,  such  as  trial-and-error 
behavior,  and  escape  or  withdrawal  responses,  there  is  little  doubt 
but  that  many  of  these  activities  can  also  be  explained  without 
reference  to  special-purpose  motivational  conceptions.  Generally 
speaking,  these  reactions  fall  within  the  province  of  the  student 
of  learning  and  have  usually  been  interpreted  in  the  light  of  the 
principles  of  transfer  of  training,  reinforcement  and  extinction, 
stimulus  generalization,  and  response  competition  or  augmenta- 
tion. Still  other  responses,  however,  are  often  described  by  such 
phrases  as  "persistent  maladaptive  reactions,"  "fixated  responses," 
or  by  other  terms  carrying  an  "abnormal"  flavor.  Thus  if  the 
behavior  is  identical  with,  or  resembles  strongly,  activities  exhibited 
at  an  earlier  stage  of  development  or  learning,  it  may  be  labeled 
"regressive."  But  even  in  these  instances  explanatory  concepts 
other  than  those  used  by  students  of  learning  and  problem  solving 
may  not  be  needed.  Some  apparent  instances  of  regression,  if  not 
all,  can  be  ascribed  to  the  weakening  effects  of  nonreinforcement 
upon  initially  dominant  responses  and  to  the  subsequent  appear- 
ance of  weaker,  previously  learned,  activities.  Clearly,  therefore, 
whenever  an  increase  in  drive  appears  to  have  been  produced  by 
blocking,  serious  attention  should  be  given  to  the  possibility  that 
the  observed  behavioral  changes  are  nothing  more  than  instances 
of  altered  associative  strengths.  A  paper  by  Holder,  Marx,  Holder, 
and  Collier  (1957)  provides  numerous  additional  examples  of  the 
application  of  associative  principles  to  the  interpretation  of  frus- 
tration behavior. 

Motivational  Theories  of  Frustration-situation 
Behavior 

Purely  associative  conceptions  may  provide  satisfactory  accounts 
of  many  instances  of  frustration  behavior,  but  the  alternative  view 
that  thwarting  leads  to  enhanced  motivation  as  well  as  to  altered 
habit  strengths  continues  to  be  widely  supported.  It  is  appropriate, 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT 


203 


therefore,  before  discussing  experiments  purporting  to  have  demon- 
strated the  motivational  effects  of  frustration,  to  review,  for  illus- 
trative purposes,  two  rather  representative  motivational  theories 
of  frustration-situation  behavior. 

Brown  and  Farber's  Formulation.  The  principal  elements  and 
relations  comprising  the  Brown-Farber  (1951)  conception,  which 
incorporates  many  of  the  basic  assumptions  of  Hull's  (1943)  more 
general  behavior  theory,  are  summarized  in  the  diagram  of  Fig.  6:1. 
Beginning  with  the  intervening  variables  at  the  center  of  the  dia- 
gram, we  note  that  frustration  (F),  which  is  regarded  as  a  hypo- 
thetical (defined)  state  or  condition  of  an  organism,  is  assumed 
to  be  produced  when  either  an  inhibitory  tendency  (I)  or  a  com- 
petitive excitatory  tendency  (Ec)  is  aroused  simultaneously  with 
an  ongoing  excitatory  tendency  (£<,).  Thus,  on  this  view,  either 


Antecedent 

manipulatable 

conditions 


Intervening 
variables 


Observable 
response 


Blocking 

Nonreinforcement- 

Amount  of  work 


No.  of 
reinforcements >■//, 


Deprivation 
Noxious  stimulation" 


No.  of 
reinforcements ^jj 


Fig.  6:1.  This  diagram  summarizes  the  antecedent  conditions  and  hypothetical 
variables  of  the  frustration  theory  of  Brown  and  Farber  (1951).  The  state  of 
frustration  (F)  is  assumed  to  be  produced  by  competition  (indicated  by 
double-headed  arrows)  between  an  ongoing  excitatory  tendency  (£»)  and 
either  an  inhibitory  tendency  (J)  or  a  competitive  excitatory  tendency  (Ec). 
These  interacting  tendencies  are  shown  to  depend  upon  their  respective  habit 
strengths  {Ho  and  He),  drive  (D),  and  upon  the  indicated  antecedent  condi- 
tions. The  consequences  of  frustration  are  shown  as  either  an  increment  in 
general  drive  (AD),  or  frustration-specific  stimuH  {Sf),  or  both.  These  factors 
are  assumed  to  have,  respectively,  the  same  kinds  of  motivational  and  associa- 
tive functions  assigned  to  them  in  Hull's  behavior  theory. 


204  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

a  negative  tendency  to  discontinue  reacting  or  a  positive  tendency 
to  perform  an  incompatible  act  produces  frustration.  The  elements 
at  the  left  of  the  diagram  indicate  that  both  the  initially  dominant 
ongoing  tendency  and  the  incompatible  competitive  one  are  func- 
tions of  their  respective  habit  strengths  {Ho  and  He)  and  of  non- 
specific drive  (D).  Drive  and  the  habit  strengths  are  in  turn  as- 
sumed to  depend  upon  the  antecedent  manipulatable  conditions 
of  deprivation  and  noxious  stimulation,  and  upon  number  of 
reinforcements,  respectively.  Likewise,  the  strength  of  the  inter- 
fering inhibitory  tendency  is  shown  as  varying  with  degree  of 
response  blocking  or  interference,  with  nonreinforcement,  and 
with  the  amount  of  work  involved  in  the  execution  of  the  re- 
sponses. In  this  theory  physical  thwarting,  prior  to  the  develop- 
ment of  learned  tendencies  to  avoid  the  barrier,  leads  to  a  state 
of  frustration  because  of  the  growth  of  inhibition  which  competes 
with  the  ongoing  (thwarted)  tendency.  Thwarting  characteristic 
of  conflict  situations  is  also  assumed  to  produce  frustration,  since 
a  competitive  positive  tendency  can  presumably  be  as  effective  as 
an  inhibitory  potential  in  negating  an  ongoing  excitatory  tendency. 

The  behavior-modifying  consequences  of  frustration  are  shown 
at  the  right-hand  side  of  Fig.  6:1.  Frustration  (F)  is  regarded  as 
having  two  primary  effects :  ( 1 )  it  results  in  an  increment  to  gen- 
eral drive  (aD),  and  (2)  it  provides  distinctive  internal  stimuli 
{Sf).  Within  the  theory,  the  increment  to  drive  is  assumed  to 
have  no  new  functions.  It  serves  simply  as  another  source  of  drive 
and  thus  combines  multiplicatively  with  associative  tendencies, 
whether  learned  or  unlearned,  to  yield  enhanced  excitatory  poten- 
tials. The  frustration-generated  stimuli,  likewise,  are  assigned  no 
special  functions  other  than  those  commonly  attributed  to  internal 
or  external  stimuli  of  any  kind.  Thus,  as  the  diagram  indicates, 
unlearned  tendencies  ( Us )  to  react  to  the  frustration  stimuli  may 
exist  from  birth,  and/or  new  habit  strengths  can  be  built  up  to 
these  internal  stimuli  by  conditioning.  The  final  elements  of  the 
diagram  suggest  that  overt  action  will  be  a  function  of  the  relative 
strengths  of  the  several  excitatory  tendencies  aroused  in  the  specific 
frustrating  situation. 

It  should  be  clear  from  the  preceding  discussion  that  the  Brown- 
Farber  conception  is  neither  purely  motivational  nor  purely  asso- 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  205 

ciative.  It  provides  a  place  for  both  motivational  increments  and 
associative  changes.  In  this  respect  it  resembles  other,  more  gen- 
eral, motivational  theories  of  behavior. 

Amsel's  Frustration  Theory.  Much  of  this  conception  was 
presented  originally  by  Amsel  in  1951,  but  the  most  highly  devel- 
oped version  appeared  in  1958.  For  Amsel,  the  major  source  of 
frustration  is  nonreward  in  situations  where  the  organism  has 
learned  to  expect  a  reward.  Thus,  when  a  rat  enters  a  goal  box 
where  it  has  been  previously  fed  and  finds  no  food  in  a  customary 
location,  the  animal  will  be  thwarted,  and  frustration  will  result. 
Frustration  is  described  at  one  point  as  a  "motivational  condi- 
tion," but  it  would  appear  from  Amsel's  development  that  frustra- 
tion is  essentially  an  implicit  reaction. 

In  dealing  with  frustration  as  a  behavior  determinant,  Amsel 
has  stressed  two  major  points  that,  while  superficially  somewhat 
different,  are  nonetheless  related.  First,  the  primary  reaction  of 
frustration  resulting  from  nonreward  is  assumed  to  lead  both  to  an 
increment  in  general  drive  and  to  frustration-specific  internal  cues. 
Moreover,  if  the  enhanced  drive  persists  for  a  period  of  time  fol- 
lowing frustration,  whatever  actions  are  elicited  within  that  period 
should  show  augmentation,  save  when  strongly  competitive  re- 
sponses are  evoked  by  frustration  (or  other)  stimuli.  As  we  shall 
note  below,  Amsel  and  his  associates  have  devised  a  number  of 
ingenious  experiments,  the  results  of  which  lend  substantial  sup- 
port to  this  expectation. 

Tlie  second  major  facet  of  Amsel's  theory  consists  in  the  as- 
sumption that  frustration,  like  other  responses,  can  be  condi- 
tioned, and  that  an  organism  may,  therefore,  after  a  series  of  non- 
rewarded  trials,  come  to  anticipate  frustration.  Seward  (1951) 
has  made  a  similar  proposal,  and  Holder,  Marx,  Holder,  and 
Collier  (1957)  ha\"e  reported  experimental  evidence  for  the  con- 
ditionability  of  frustration.  The  specific  mechanism  underlying 
this  effect  parallels  Hull's  rg-Sy  mechanism  rather  closely.  On  the 
first  nonrewarded  trial,  the  primary  frustration  reaction  (F)  is 
elicited  in  the  goal  box,  and  through  the  operation  of  classical 
conditioning  it  becomes  associated  with  the  stimulus  complex 
present  in  the  goal  box.  On  subsequent  trials,  fractional  compo- 
nents of  the  primarv  frustration  reaction  can  be  elicited  in  the 


206  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

alley  (or  elsewhere)  by  cues  that  are  similar  (stimulus  generali- 
zation) to  those  that  were  present  in  the  goal  box.  These  anti- 
cipatory frustration  reactions  (r/)  are  thus  analogous  to  the  an- 
ticipatory consummatory  responses  (r^s)  posited  by  Hull.  More- 
over, the  r/S,  like  the  VgS,  are  assumed  to  be  accompanied  by  their 
own  characteristic  internal  stimuli  (s/s). 

Although  Amsel  does  not  deny  that  the  arousal  of  the  Tf-Sf  se- 
quence may  lead  to  an  increment  in  drive,  as  Hull  and  Spence 
have  supposed  to  be  true  of  the  Tg-Sg  sequence,  the  behavior-deter- 
mining functions  of  the  r/^Sf  mechanism  are  viewed  primarily  as 
the  capacity  of  Sf  to  elicit  specific  inhibitory  responses.  For  exam- 
ple, in  dealing  with  behavior  in  partial  reinforcement  situations, 
Amsel  assumes  that  frustration  is  inherently  aversive  and  that 
tendencies  to  avoid  a  nonrewarding  goal  box  can  become  asso- 
ciated with  the  frustration-response-produced  stimuli  (s/s).  On 
relatively  early  trials,  therefore,  performance  tends  to  be  poorer 
when  the  response  is  not  rewarded  on  every  occasion,  because  the 
S/-elicited  avoidance  tendencies  interfere  with  tendencies  to  ap- 
proach. On  laier  trials,  however,  since  the  animal  usually  does  keep 
on  running,  the  approach  tendencies  become  more  and  more 
strongly  attached  to  the  frustration  stimuli.  When  all  reinforce- 
ment is  omitted  during  extinction,  partially  reinforced  animals 
perform  more  efficiently  than  continuously  rewarded  controls 
because  the  former  subjects  have  associated  the  frustration  stimuli 
with  running,  but  the  latter  have  not. 

Incidentally,  Amsel's  assumption  that  frustration  is  both  motivat- 
ing and  aversive  is  quite  in  accord  with  the  views  expressed  here. 
Specifically,  to  assert  that  an  animal  tends  to  avoid  a  situation 
where  frustration  has  been  produced  and  drive  has  been  increased 
is  consistent  with  our  third  criterion  for  identifying  motivational 
variables  (Chapter  2).  On  this  criterion  a  variable  is  identified  as 
motivational  if  behavior  antedating  its  introduction  tends  to  be 
weakened  or  abandoned.  It  is  not  paradoxical,  therefore,  to  say 
that  an  organism  can  learn  to  anticipate  and  to  avoid  frustration 
and  yet  exhibit  response  augmentation  immediately  following 
thwarting. 

A  detailed  comparison  of  the  Amsel  and  Brown-Farber  the- 
ories would  take  us  beyond  the  intended  scope  of  this  book,  but  it 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  207 

is  interesting  to  observe  that  the  appearance  of  anticipatory  frustra- 
tion can  be  explained  by  the  latter  theory  without  the  added  as- 
sumption that  frustration  is  directly  conditionable.  On  this  view 
the  introduction  of  nonrewarded  trials  after  an  animal  has  been 
repeatedly  reinforced  for  approaching  a  goal  would  be  expected 
to  lead  to  the  development  of  avoidance  tendencies.  Through  the 
operation  of  stimulus  generalization,  these  tendencies  could  be 
elicited,  along  with  approach  tendencies,  in  the  alley  leading  to 
the  goal  box.  Since  frustration  is  assumed  to  arise  from  the  com- 
petition between  one  excitatory  tendency  and  another,  it  follows 
that  frustration  could  thus  be  generated  prior  to  reaching  a  goal. 
Apparent  instances  of  conditioned  frustration  could  in  this  way 
be  explained  in  terms  of  conditioned  and  generalized  response 
tendencies  which  produce  frustration  through  their  competitive 
interaction. 

Evaluating  the  Motivational  Effects  of  Thv/arting 

Should  one  proceed  on  the  assumption  that  thwarting  does,  in 
fact,  result  in  drive  enhancement  it  becomes  necessary  to  consider 
the  practical  question  of  how  this  phenomenon  can  be  unam- 
biguously demonstrated.  In  principle,  of  course,  an  experiment 
designed  to  reveal  the  presence  of  frustration-produced  drive  must 
be  essentially  the  same  as  all  other  investigations  purporting  to 
show  that  variables  are  functioning  motivationally.  In  terms  of  the 
position  taken  here,  this  means  that  frustration  can  be  said  to 
have  led  to  an  increment  in  drive  when  at  least  one  of  the  basic 
criteria  for  the  identification  of  a  motivational  variable  has  been 
met  and  when  there  is  little  reason  to  suppose  that  the  observa- 
tions are  attributable  solely  to  altered  associative  strengths. 

Frustration  Drive  as  a  General  Energizer.  The  large  majority  of 
experiments  to  be  considered  in  the  following  pages  have  been 
designed  on  the  assumption  that  intensified  behavior  should  be 
exhibited  at  or  near  the  time  of  thwarting.  Implicitly,  therefore,  if 
not  explicitly,  most  investigators  have  adopted  a  criterion  for 
identifying  frustration  or  frustration  effects  that  is  identical  with 
our  first  criterion  suggested  in  Chapter  2. 

Prior  to  about  1950  the  only  evidence  favoring  the  hypothesis  of 


208  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

frustration-induced  drive  ^^'as  casual  and  nonsystematic.  Early 
workers  in  the  field  of  learning  frequently  noted  that  when  moti- 
vated subjects  encountered  obstructions  in  problem-solving  and 
trial-and-error  situations,  highly  energetic  activity  was  the  result. 
Thorndike  (1898),  for  example,  reported  that  cats  in  attempting 
to  escape  from  the  confinement  of  a  problem  box  struggled  with 
"extraordinary  vigor."  Likewise,  Hamilton  (1916),  during  his 
extensive  comparative  studies  of  reactions  to  insoluble  problems, 
often  observed  that  his  subjects  exhibited  excited,  emotional  be- 
havior. Moreover,  an  increase  in  response  strength  during  the 
first  few  extinction  trials  has  been  reported  for  classically  condi- 
tioned responses  by  Switzer,  1930,  Hilgard  and  Marquis,  1935, 
and  Hovland,  1936.  Whether  this  phenomenon  constitutes  a 
legitimate  instance  of  frustration  drive  is  uncertain,  although 
omitting  the  UCS  may  strengthen  competitive  inhibitory  tend- 
encies and  thereby  induce  some  measure  of  frustration. 

Observations  of  increased  response  vigor  following  the  thwarting 
of  a  well-learned  response  appear  in  increasing  numbers  during 
the  third  and  fourth  decades  of  the  present  century.  For  example. 
Skinner  (1932)  found  the  rat's  rate  of  eating  to  be  higher  after  a 
temporary  period  of  enforced  waiting  than  immediately  prior  to 
the  beginning  of  the  frustration  period.  Skinner  used  the  term 
"emotional"  in  describing  this  effect,  but  he  seems  not  to  have 
considered  the  heightened  rate  to  be  a  frustration-drive  phe- 
nomenon. Miller  and  Stevenson  (1936)  and  Finch  (1942),  whose 
studies  we  have  already  mentioned,  reported  a  marked  intensifica- 
tion of  certain  responses  following  nonreward  in  a  situation  where 
reward  had  formerly  been  consistently  obtained.  Others,  such  as 
Crespi  (1944),  had  also  observed  intensified  activity  following 
both  nonreward  and  a  shift  from  large  to  small  reward,  and  Brown 
and  Gentry  (1948)  reported  numerous  instances  in  which  periods 
of  delay  wer^  preceded  by  heightened  emotional  behavior. 

Perhaps  the  earliest  experimental  study  directed  specifically 
toward  demonstrating  the  presence  of  frustration  drive  and  toward 
the  discovery  of  the  variables  on  which  it  depends  is  that  by 
Marzocco  (1951).  Basing  his  theorizing,  in  part,  upon  the  sugges- 
tions of  Brown  and  Farber  (1951),  Marzocco  reasoned  that  the 
hypothetical  state  resulting  from  thwarting  would  function  as  an 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  209 

irrelevant  drive  to  raise  the  organism's  total  effective  drive  level. 
Moreover,  this  heightened  drive  would  be  expected  to  increase 
the  amplitude  of  any  response  evoked  during  thwarting,  provided 
stimuli  accompanying  frustration  did  not  lead  to  excessively 
strong  competing  responses.  He  also  hypothesized  that  frustration 
would  increase  with  degree  of  hunger  and  with  amount  of  practice 
in  making  the  frustrated  response.  And  since  the  frustration  state 
might  be  relatively  transient,  increasing  the  length  of  the  interval 
between  successive  frustrated  responses  should  weaken  the  effect 
of  a  previous  frustration  upon  a  subsequent  reaction. 

To  test  these  predictions,  Marzocco  trained  81  rats  in  a  modified 
Skinner  box  in  which  measures  could  be  obtained  of  the  force  with 
which  the  rats  depressed  the  bar.  The  general  procedure  involved 
a  number  of  days  devoted  to  habituation  and  taming  followed  by 
one  day  of  training  in  bar-pressing  and  by  a  second  day  of  testing 
for  frustration-drive  effects.  On  the  frustration  day,  all  animals 
were  given  three  rewarded  trials  followed  by  a  series  of  con- 
sistently nonrewarded  (frustrating)  trials.  Three  subjects  were 
assigned  at  random  to  each  of  the  cells  of  a  3  X  3  X  3  factorial 
design.  The  variables  of  the  design  and  their  levels  were:  (1 )  hours 
without  food  at  the  time  of  frustration:  1,  16,  and  22;  (2)  number 
of  rewarded  bar-pressing  trials  on  the  acquisition  day:  8,  24,  and 
72;  and  (3)  time  (in  seconds)  between  successive  nonrewarded 
trials  on  the  frustration  day:  10,  20,  and  40.  Marzocco's  measure  of 
frustration-drive  effects  was  a  difference  score  obtained  for  each 
rat  by  subtracting  the  mean  force  it  exerted  on  the  bar  during  the 
first  four  trials  of  the  frustration  day  from  the  mean  force  exerted 
on  the  next  four.  When  the  responses  for  all  81  rats  were  grouped 
together,  the  rise  in  force  due  to  thwarting  proved  to  be  very 
striking  and  highly  significant.  Figure  6:2  shows  this  effect  quite 
clearly.  Here  it  will  be  seen  that  immediately  following  the  fourth 
trial  (the  first  nonrewarded  one)  the  average  force  rises  from  28 
to  35.9  grams.  Moreover,  if  28  grams  is  taken  as  a  reference  level, 
it  is  apparent  that  in  spite  of  continued  nonreward  the  rats  con- 
tinued to  press  the  lever  with  "supernormal"  vigor  until  about  the 
seventeenth  trial. 

When  the  data  for  the  differently  treated  groups  were  analyzed, 
Marzocco  found  the  frustration  effect  to  be  significantly  related  to 


210 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

40 


0      4       8      12     16     20    24     28     32     36     40     44 
Trials 

Fig.  6:2.  Mean  force  in  grams  exerted  on  a  lever  by  rats  during  a  series  of 
trials  in  which  the  first  three  trials  were  followed  by  food  reward  and  the  re- 
mainder were  not.  The  marked  increase  in  vigor  of  response  after  the  first 
nonrewarded  trial  (trial  4)  provides  a  clear  example  of  the  energizing  effects 
of  thwarting  upon  subsequent  responses.  {From  Marzocco,  1951.) 

hours  of  food  deprivation  at  the  time  of  frustration,  with  the 
frustration-produced  increase  in  bar-pressing  force  rising  with  de- 
gree of  hunger.  He  also  found  an  increasing  frustration  effect  as 
the  intertrial  interval  was  shortened,  though  the  trend  was  not 
statistically  significant.  This  relation  had  been  predicted  on  the 
ground  that  the  frustration  generated  on  one  nonrewarded  trial 
should  have  a  greater  effect  on  the  vigor  of  the  following  response 
when  the  interval  between  them  was  short.  The  frustration  effect 
was  also  expected  to  increase  directly  with  number  of  rein- 
forced trials.  Both  the  24-  and  72-reinforcement  groups  showed 
a  greater  increase  in  force  than  did  the  8-reinforcement  group, 
but  the  72-trial  group  showed  less  of  the  effect  than  did  the  24-trial 
animals. 

Taken  as  a  whole,  Marzocco's  study  provides  clear  evidence  for 
increased  response  vigor  following  thwarting.  But  his  study  does 
not  prove  that  thwarting  leads  to  an  increment  in  drive.  During 
their  preexperimental  history  his  animals  could  have  learned  in  a 
variety  of  situations  to  exert  more  vigorous  responses  in  order  to 
circumvent  barriers  or  to  overcome  resistance  to  the  completion 
of  a  response.  If  so,  and  if  the  bar-pressing  situation  could  be  re- 
garded as  sufficiently  similar  to  the  situations  in  which  such  re- 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  211 

sponses  had  been  learned,  the  transfer  of  the  learned  reactions 
to  the  new  situation  could  be  explained.  Alternatively,  the  animals 
might  have  learned  during  their  bar-pressing  acquisition  trials  that 
if  no  reward  followed  a  weak  response,  a  more  vigorous  press 
would  successfully  activate  the  food-release  mechanism.  Conse- 
quently, when  no  food  appeared  during  extinction  trials,  its  ab- 
sence would  provide  cues  tending  to  evoke  more  vigorous  responses. 
If  this  were  the  correct  interpretation,  however,  the  experimental 
variable  of  number  of  reinforcements  should  have  been  more 
clearly  related  to  the  frustration  effect.  Finally,  one  might  even 
look  upon  Marzocco's  results  as  an  instance  of  regression.  His  data 
show  that  the  mean  force  exerted  on  the  bar  by  a  group  of  27  rats 
during  acquisition  was  33.5  grams  for  the  first  10  rewarded  trials 
and  20.6  grams  for  the  last  10  (of  72)  trials.  Thus  the  animals  were 
apparently  learning,  during  their  bar-pressing  trials,  to  exert  less 
and  less  force  on  the  bar.  If  pressing  the  bar  vigorously  is  regarded 
as  the  "earher  habit"  and  weaker  pressing  as  the  "later  habit," 
then  the  animals'  frustration  behavior  might  reasonably  be  de- 
scribed as  "regression"  to  an  earlier  form  of  activity.  These  various 
interpretations  of  Marzocco's  results  reemphasize  the  point  that 
experiments  purporting  to  demonstrate  the  frustration-drive  effect 
must  be  done  with  great  care  if  the  credibility  of  associative  con- 
ceptions is  to  be  minimized.  That  this  is  rather  difficult  to  accom- 
plish will  become  clearer  as  we  examine  additional  studies  of  the 
frustration-drive  phenomenon. 

Amsel  and  Roussel's  (1952)  experiment  constitutes  an  ingenious 
attempt  to  demonstrate  the  energizing  effects  of  nonreward  upon 
locomotor  behavior  in  the  rat.  Initially,  these  investigators  trained 
their  rats  to  run  down  a  short  straight  alley  into  a  goal  box  for 
food  and  then  out  into  a  second  connecting  alley  and  to  a  second 
goal  box  for  a  second  bit  of  food.  Preliminary  training  consisted  of 
84  trials,  on  each  of  which  the  rats  obtained  food  in  both  goal 
boxes.  During  an  additional  36  trials,  food  was  omitted  from  the 
first  goal  box  on  a  randomly  selected  half  of  the  runs.  These  18 
nonrewarded  trials  constituted  the  frustrating  trials.  The  effects  of 
thwarting  were  evaluated  by  measuring  the  rats'  speed  of  running 
in  the  second  section  and  comparing  the  values  obtained  on  frus- 
trating (nonrewarded)  trials  with  those  obtained  on  rewarded  trials. 


212 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


On  all  trials  food  was  present  in  the  second  goal  box.  Tlie  results 
of  these  manipulations  upon  the  median  running  times  of  the  18 
subjects  in  the  second  alley  are  summarized  in  Fig.  6:3.  Here  it 
will  be  seen  that  the  rats'  running  time,  when  reward  was  provided 
in  both  goal  boxes,  had  reached  a  stable  level  at  the  end  of  the  28 
days  (3  trials  daily)  of  preliminary  training.  Shortly  after  the  in- 
troduction of  the  frustration  trials,  however,  running  time  on  those 
trials  dropped  to  a  new  level,  which  proved  to  be  significantly  lower 
than  the  level  maintained  on  further  reward  trials.  Amsel  and 
Roussel  concluded  from  these  data  that  frustration  due  to  non- 
reward  in  the  first  goal  box  produced  an  addition  to  the  motiva- 
tional complex,  which  resulted  in  the  establishment  of  a  new 
and  higher  maximum  speed  of  running. 

Taken  at  face  value,  this  finding  supports  the  frustration-drive 
hypothesis,  but  as  Amsel  and  Roussel  point  out,  other  interpreta- 
tions are  possible.  For  example,  they  note  that  the  difference  in 
the  performance  of  the  animals  on  the  rewarded  and  frustration 


.i  100 


■319 


Reward 


25 

0 


I        I I I I L. 


I      ' I u 


I        I        r        I        [ 


8       12       16      20 

Preliminary  reward 

days 


24      28        123456789 
Reward-frustration 

test  trials 
Two-trial  blocks 


Fig.  6:3.  Data  indicating  that  rats  tend  to  run  faster  on  nonrewarded  (frustrat- 
ing) trials  than  on  rewarded  trials  when  the  two  kinds  of  trials  are  admin- 
istered alternately  following  a  long  period  of  training  during  which  every  trial 
has  been  rewarded.  [Adapted  from  Amsel  and  Roussel,  J 952.) 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  213 

test  trials  could  mean  either  a  depression  of  performance  on  re- 
warded trials  or  heightened  performance  on  nonreward  trials. 
Speed  of  running  during  the  preliminary  reward  days  and  on  the 
rewarded  test  trials  might  have  been  reduced  because  the  animals 
had  eaten  food  in  the  first  goal  box  just  before  entering  the  sec- 
ond alley.  If  this  were  correct,  the  frustration-drive  hypothesis 
would  not  be  needed  to  explain  faster  running  on  nonrewarded 
trials. 

Amsel  and  Roussel  suggest,  however,  that  two  factors  support 
the  argument  against  this  performance-depression  hypothesis.  First, 
the  omission  of  customary  reward  in  the  first  goal  box  should  have 
altered  the  stimulus  complex  (taste  of  food  in  the  mouth,  for  ex- 
ample) to  which  running  had  been  conditioned,  and  this  would 
function  to  reduce  running  speed  on  nonrewarded  trials.  Second, 
experimental  evidence  from  other  studies  shows  that  a  small 
amount  of  prefeeding  may  increase  the  level  of  performance.  Since 
both  of  these  factors  would  have  an  effect  opposite  to  that  de- 
scribed by  the  performance-depression  explanation,  Amsel  and 
Roussel  do  not  consider  that  interpretation  the  only  reasonable 
one. 

Support  for  the  wisdom  of  their  view  has  recently  been  obtained 
by  Wagner  (1959) .  In  a  similar  experiment,  where  the  frustration- 
drive  effect  was  clearly  demonstrated,  he  ran  an  additional  control 
group,  whose  members  were  detained  for  a  few  seconds  in  the  first 
goal  box  but  were  never  fed  therein.  On  the  response-depression 
hypothesis,  these  animals,  whose  hunger  had  not  been  reduced 
just  prior  to  running  in  the  second  alley,  should  have  run  faster 
in  that  alley  than  rats  that  had  been  fed  in  the  first  goal  box. 
However,  these  control  subjects  of  Wagner's  ran  at  about  the 
same  speed  in  the  second  alley  as  did  the  animals  that  consumed 
a  pellet  in  the  first  goal  box. 

Before  turning  to  other  types  of  studies  purporting  to  demon- 
strate the  frustration-drive  effect,  we  should  note  that  Amsel  and 
his  associates  (e.g.,  Roussel,  1952)  have  confirmed  the  main  find- 
ing of  the  Amsel  and  Roussel  study  on  a  number  of  occasions. 
Moreover,  they  have  also  shown  (Amsel  and  Hancock,  1957)  that 
the  frustration  effect  is  more  marked  if  the  first  alley  is  similar  to 
the  first  goal  box  than  if  it  is  different.  This  observation  is  consist- 


214  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

ent  with  their  assumption  that  frustration  is  a  consequence  of  the 
thwarting  of  an  expectancy  (rg-Sg)  for  a  goal  object.  If  the  first 
alley  is  the  same  color  as  the  first  goal  box  it  should  elicit  a  stronger 
anticipation  of  food  than  if  the  two  are  different,  and  the  frustra- 
tion of  the  stronger  expectancy  should  lead  to  a  bigger  increment 
in  drive  with  a  greater  enhancement  of  running  speed  in  the  sec- 
ond alley. 

Experimental  attempts  to  demonstrate  the  presence  of  frustra- 
tion-drive effects  on  human  subjects,  particularly  children,  have 
been  reported  quite  frequently  in  recent  times.  It  is  impossible 
here  to  review  each  of  these  studies  in  detail,  but  those  by  Haner 
and  Brown  (1955)  and  by  Holton  (1956)  serve  as  excellent  repre- 
sentative examples. 

One  of  the  purposes  of  the  Haner-Brown  study  was  to  try  to 
extend  and  clarify  the  frustration-aggression  hypothesis  of  Dollard, 
Doob,  Miller,  Mowrer,  and  Sears  (1939).  According  to  these  lat- 
ter writers,  aggression  is  a  function  of,  among  other  things,  degree 
of  instigation  to  action.  But  Haner  and  Brown  regard  instigation 
to  action  as  being  equivalent  to  Hull's  excitatory  potential,  which 
includes  both  habit  and  drive,  and  hold  that  Dollard  et  al.  fail, 
in  their  handling  of  this  concept,  to  recognize  the  importance  of 
the  habit  strength  component.  They  make  the  prediction,  there- 
fore, that  if  behavior  is  frustrated  near  the  goal,  where  habit 
strength  is  presumed  to  be  stronger,  the  "amount  of  disturbance 
experienced"  will  be  greater  than  if  the  sequence  is  interrupted  at 
some  point  farther  from  the  goal.  Moreover,  intensity  of  aggressive 
action  should  vary  directly  with  "amount  of  disturbance  experi- 
enced." In  the  terminology  of  this  chapter,  Haner  and  Brown  are 
asserting  that  degree  of  frustration  is  directly  related  to  habit 
strength  at  the  time  of  thwarting  and  that  the  motivational  incre- 
ment is,  in  turn,  a  direct  function  of  degree  of  frustration.  This, 
it  will  be  recalled,  was  essentially  the  position  taken  by  Marzocco. 

In  attempting  to  test  this  assertion,  Haner  and  Brown  gave  ele- 
mentary school  children  a  serial  task  in  which  they  had  to  place 
36  marbles,  one  at  a  time,  into  36  holes  in  a  board.  They  were 
told  that  four  successful  completions  of  the  task  would  bring  a 
prize  but  that  the  time  allotted  to  each  trial  would  be  limited  and 
variable.  On  certain  trials  the  experimenter  operated  a  mechanism 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT 


215 


which  caused  whatever  marbles  had  been  placed  on  the  board  to 
drop  though  the  holes  into  a  box  below.  On  these  frustration  trials 
a  buzzer  would  sound  and  the  subjects  had  to  depress  a  spring- 
loaded  plunger  to  turn  off  the  buzzer  and  initiate  a  new  trial.  De- 
gree of  frustration-induced  drive  was  inferred  from  the  amount  of 
downward  movement  of  the  plunger.  On  various  trials  all  subjects 
were  frustrated  at  four  points  of  proximity  to  the  goal,  that  is, 
after  9,  18,  27,  or  32  marbles  had  been  placed  in  the  holes  on  the 
board.  The  buzzer  was  also  sounded  after  all  36  marbles  had  been 
used.  But  this,  by  definition,  was  not  a  frustration  trial,  since  the 
goal  (or  a  subgoal,  at  least)  had  been  reached. 

The  results  of  the  plunger-pushing  measurements  obtained  by 
Haner  and  Brown  are  shown  in  Fig.  6:4.  As  this  figure  shows, 
when  the  point  of  frustration  was  moved  closer  and  closer  to  the 
goal,  as  expressed  by  the  number  of  marbles  placed  on  the  board, 
the  mean  amount  of  plunger  depression  increased  progressively, 
reaching  a  peak  at  the  32-marble  point,  which  was  eight-ninths  of 
the  distance  to  the  goal.  But  the  displacement  of  the  plunger 
dropped  markedly  when  all  36  marbles  had  been  placed  and  the 
goal  had  been  reached.  According  to  the  authors,  the  increase 
in  plunger  force  from  the  9-marble  point  of  interruption  to  the 
32-marble  point  was  highly  significant  statistically.  Consequently, 
their  hypothesis  concerning  the  increase  in  motivational  effects  of 
frustration  with  increasing  habit  strength  tended  to  be  supported. 

One  of  the  noteworthy  features  of  the  Haner-Brown  study  is 


Fig.  6:4.  Mean  amplitude 
of  plunger-depressing  re- 
sponses made  by  children 
following  the  induction  of 
frustration  at  varying  dis- 
tances from  a  goal.  Since 
the  task  was  to  place  36 
marbles  in  holes  in  a 
board,  the  distance  from 
the  goal  decreased  with  in- 
creasing numbers  of  mar- 
bles placed.  {Adapted 
from  Haner  and  Brown, 
J955.) 


18  27        32 

Marbles  placed  in  board 


35 


216  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

that  the  response  of  plunger  pressing,  from  which  motivational 
eflfects  were  inferred,  was  clearly  different  from  the  thwarted  instru- 
mental response  of  marble  placing.  Because  of  this,  an  interpreta- 
tion involving  transfer  of  training  rather  than  increased  motiva- 
tion does  not  seem  highly  plausible.  On  such  a  view,  one  would 
have  to  suppose  that  the  children  had  learned  in  very  similar  situa- 
tions that  vigorous  plunger-pressing  responses  or  closely  similar 
ones  would  enable  them  to  circumvent  or  remove  a  thwarting 
agent  more  quickly  than  weak  plunger  presses.  Some  children,  of 
course,  might  have  had  an  opportunity  to  acquire  such  habits. 
But  generally  speaking,  when  an  explanation  rests  upon  the  prin- 
ciples of  stimulus  generalization,  regression,  and  the  like,  its  plau- 
sibility is  reduced  if  the  indicator  response  differs  from  the 
thwarted  instrumental  response  and  if  the  indicator  response  is 
causally  unrelated  to  the  removal  or  circumvention  of  the  barrier. 

Holton  (1956)  has  also  obtained  evidence  favoring  the  hy- 
pothesis that  frustration-drive  effects  become  greater  with  in- 
creased nearness  to  a  goal  and  with  increasing  numbers  of  rein- 
forcements of  the  thwarted  response.  In  the  initial  phase  of  her 
experiment,  three  groups  of  preschool  children  were  taught  to 
make  a  simple  spatial  discrimination.  Two  identical  orange-colored 
stimulus  patches  were  presented  against  a  black  background,  and 
the  child's  task  was  to  push  against  one  of  the  patches.  A  correct 
response  was  followed  by  a  marble  reward,  and  a  prize  could  be 
won  by  accumulating  a  stated  number  of  marbles.  Thwarting  was 
induced  by  failure  to  reinforce  the  panel-pressing  response  with 
a  marble.  The  apparatus  was  constructed  so  that  accurate  measure- 
ments could  be  made  of  the  force  with  which  each  of  the  stimulus 
panels  was  pushed  by  the  subjects  during  both  rewarded  and 
frustration  trials. 

Three  groups  of  subjects  were  used  by  Holton.  The  members  of 
one  were  permitted  to  make  only  1 3  correct  responses  before  being 
thwarted  near  the  goal.  A  second  group  was  also  frustrated  near 
the  goal,  but  after  making  26  correct  responses.  The  third  group 
was  given  26  reinforced  trials,  but  nonreward  was  introduced  at 
a  greater  distance  from  the  goal  than  in  the  case  of  the  first  two 
groups. 

To  evaluate  the  frustration-drive  effects,  Holton  compared  the 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT 


217 


mean  force  exerted  on  the  four  trials  preceding  nonreward  with 
the  mean  force  on  the  four  trials  following  nonreward.  The  values 
obtained  from  these  measurements  for  the  three  groups  are 
plotted  in  Fig.  6:5. 

As  this  figure  shows,  all  three  groups  pushed  harder  on  the 
stimulus  panels  on  the  first  four  nonrewarded  trials  than  they  did 
on  the  preceding  rewarded  trials.  Actually,  only  one  of  the  45  sub- 
jects in  the  three  groups  failed  to  exhibit  a  higher  mean  score  for 
the  nonrewarded  trials  than  for  the  rewarded  ones.  Thus  the 
finding  that  nonreward  leads  to  more  vigorous  responses  receives 
further  confirmation.  Holton  also  found,  as  the  figure  indicates, 
that  of  the  two  groups  blocked  near  the  goal,  the  one  given  26 
reinforcements  prior  to  blocking  exhibited  a  significantly  greater 
increase  in  response  amplitude  than  the  13-trial  group.  In  addition, 
the  group  blocked  near  the  goal  ( 26-N )  showed  a  greater  increase 
in  force  than  the  comparably  trained  group  (26-F)  that  was 
blocked  farther  from  the  goal.  This  is  consistent  with  the  results 


Pre-thwarting 
tests 


Post-thwarting 
tests 


Fig.  6:5.  Mean  force  exerted  on  response  panels  by  children  before  and  after 
thwarting.  The  curve  marked  26-F  denotes  the  responses  of  a  group  given  26 
reinforcements  and  blocked  far  from  the  goal.  The  curves  labeled  26-N  and 
13-N  apply  to  groups  blocked  near  the  goal  after  26  and  13  reinforcements, 
respectively.  {Adapted  from  Holton,  J 956.) 


218  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

of  the  Haner-Brown  experiment  and  with  theoretical  expectations. 

Reduction  in  Frustration  Drive  as  Reinforcement.  The  investi- 
gations reviewed  in  the  preceding  section  all  point  to  the  conclu- 
sion that  response  enhancement  at  or  near  the  time  of  thwarting 
fits  the  view  of  thwarting  as  a  source  of  drive.  It  is  also  reasonable 
to  suppose,  if  we  bear  in  mind  our  second  criterion  for  the  identifi- 
cation of  a  motivational  variable  (Chapter  2),  that  a  reduction  in 
frustration  drive  should  be  reinforcing.  Thus  one  would  expect 
that  the  strength  of  a  response  would  increase  if  that  response  were 
followed  by  a  reduction  in  frustration. 

As  is  sometimes  the  case  with  ideas  such  as  this,  the  supporting 
evidence,  though  plentiful,  is  almost  entirely  anecdotal.  In  the 
typical  trial-and-error  situation,  for  instance,  an  organism  tends  to 
learn  whatever  response  is  successful  in  leading  to  the  circumven- 
tion of  the  thwarting  circumstances  or  to  the  correct  solution  of 
the  problem.  Such  learning  may  be  due,  in  part,  to  a  reduction  in 
frustration-produced  drive  following  the  performance  of  the  cor- 
rect reaction.  But  in  these  situations  the  problem-solving  response 
nearly  always  leads  to  the  receipt  of  food  or  to  other  reinforcers. 
This  makes  it  difficult  to  decide  whether  the  escape  reaction  is 
being  reinforced  by  a  reduction  in  frustration  drive  or  by  some 
quite  different  agent.  There  are  instances,  however,  such  as  that 
reported  by  Guthrie  and  Horton  (1946),  in  which  animals  learn 
to  escape  from  a  problem  box  by  performing  a  specific  act,  yet  do 
not  consume  the  reward  when  they  get  out.  In  such  cases  the  rein- 
forcement may  be  provided  by  a  decrease  in  frustration  drive  since 
hunger  remains  unaffected. 

^^Negative  Effects  of  Increases  in  Frustration  Drive.  Our  third 
criterion  for  the  identification  of  a  motivational  variable  leads  to 
the  expectation  that  reactions  followed  by  increased  drive  due  to 
thwarting  should  tend  to  be  weakened.  As  noted  above,  Amsel's 
supposition  that  frustration  is  an  aversive  condition  is  consistent 
with  this  view. 

Probably  the  clearest  evidence  for  the  negative  effects  of  thwart- 
ing upon  prefrustration  behavior  is  provided  by  an  experiment  of 
Holder,  Marx,  Holder,  and  Collier  (1957).  These  investigators 
trained  hungry  rats  to  run  down  a  90-inch  straight  alley  for  food 
reward.  During  a  series  of  25  such  training  trials,  administered  one 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  219 

per  day,  the  rats  were  detained  for  1  second  in  a  delay  chamber  at 
the  middle  of  the  runway.  On  subsequent  test  trials,  one-third  of 
the  subjects  continued  to  run  under  the  same  conditions  as  during 
training,  another  third  were  detained  for  15  seconds  in  the  delay 
box,  and  the  remaining  third  were  delayed  for  45  seconds.  Both 
running-  and  starting-time  measures  revealed  that  the  increased 
delay  led  to  better  performance  in  the  post-delay-box  section  of 
the  alley — this  supports  the  concept  of  frustration  drive  as  an 
energizer — but  to  poorer  performance  in  the  pre-delay-box  seg- 
ment. Granting  the  plausibility  of  our  third  motivation-variable 
criterion,  we  may  conclude  that  this  latter  effect,  like  the  former, 
supports  the  assumption  that  thwarting  serves  as  a  source  of  drive. 
As  Holder  et  al.  point  out,  the  reduction  in  response  strength 
in  the  pre-delay  segment  can  be  explained,  within  Amsel's  theory, 
as  due  to  the  growth  of  an  anticipatory  frustration  reaction  or, 
following  Brown  and  Farber,  as  a  consequence  of  the  conditioning 
of  avoidance  responses  to  the  noxious  cues  accompanying  frustra- 
tion. Further  experimental  evidence,  indicating  that  delays  lead  to 
the  weakening  of  pre-delay  responses  can  be  found  in  the  studies 
of  Cooper  (1938),  Gilhousen  (1938),  Brown  and  Gentry  (1948), 
and  Holder  (1951). 

Conflict  as  a  Source  of  Drive.  Throughout  the  foregoing  pages 
we  have  proceeded  on  the  assumption  that  frustrating  conditions 
such  as  physical  blocks,  delays,  and  removal  of  rewards  may  all 
involve  the  development  of  tendencies  that  are  antagonistic  to  the 
tendency  being  thwarted.  And  since  the  simultaneous  arousal  of 
competitive  tendencies  is  also  the  definitive  feature  of  conflict  situa- 
tions, no  attempt  has  been  made  to  distinguish  between  frustra- 
tion and  conflict.  In  so  far  as  conflict  and  frustration  cannot  be 
differentiated,  experiments  purporting  to  have  demonstrated  that 
conflict  leads  to  an  increment  in  drive  would  necessarily  be  of  the 
same  general  sort  as  those  designed  to  detect  frustration-generated 
drive.  Studies  by  Hollenberg  and  Sperry  (1951),  and  by  Lowell 
(1952cz),  which  rest  on  unpublished  theoretical  developments  of 
J.  W.  M.  Whiting,  serve  as  examples  of  such  research. 

In  concluding  this  chapter,  we  find  it  interesting  to  note  that 
the  conflict-drive  hypothesis  has  been  extended  from  individual 
behavior  situations  to  social  and  cultural  phenomena  by  Whiting 


220  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

and  Child  (1953).  These  authors  tabulated  the  child-rearing  prac- 
tices of  75  primitive  societies  and  then  obtained  ratings  of  "initial 
satisfaction"  and  "socialization  anxiety."  The  term  initial  satisfac- 
tion refers  to  the  positive  (pleasant  or  rewarding)  consequences 
of  the  socialization  process  at  the  individual  level.  Socialization 
anxiety,  however,  is  the  consequence  of  severity  of  discipline  during 
child  training  and  is  approximately  equivalent  to  an  acquired-fear 
reaction.  Ratings  on  each  of  these  two  variables  were  obtained  for 
each  culture  in  a  number  of  different  areas  of  parent-child  interac- 
tion such  as  aggression,  weaning,  and  toilet  training.  The  ratings 
of  initial  satisfaction  and  socialization  anxiety  were  then  used  by 
Whiting  and  Child  to  test  a  number  of  hypotheses  about  relations 
between  child-rearing  practices  and  various  aspects  of  adult  per- 
sonality patterns. 

The  concept  of  conflict-produced  drive  is  introduced  in  Whiting 
and  Child's  treatment  of  the  origins  of  the  fear  of  others.  Here  it 
is  suggested  that  fears  of  human  and  animal  spirits  derive  in  con- 
siderable measure  from  anxieties  about  the  expression  of  aggres- 
sion. Individuals  acquire  anxieties  concerning  aggressive  acts  to- 
ward their  parents  during  childhood  as  a  result  of  the  parents' 
punitive  role  in  the  socialization  process.  These  fears  of  parents 
and  near  relatives,  primarily,  are  assumed  to  generalize  to  other 
people  and/or  spirits  (human  or  animal)  to  the  degree  that  the 
generalized  stimulus  patterns  resemble  the  persons  originally  re- 
sponsible for  frustration  and  punishment.  From  hypotheses  such  as 
these  Whiting  and  Child  predict,  and  confirm  their  prediction 
from  child-rearing  and  other  data,  that  members  of  primitive  socie- 
ties should  exhibit  a  greater  fear  of  human  spirits  than  of  animal 
spirits.  Moreover,  by  the  use  of  the  conflict-drive  hypothesis,  they 
successfully  predict  that  societies  with  high  aggression  anxiety  will 
have  more  nearly  equal  tendencies  to  fear  human  and  animal 
spirits  than  will  societies  with  low  aggression  anxiety.  The  precise 
steps  in  this  and  in  other  deductions  made  by  Whiting  and  Child 
are  too  detailed  for  presentation  here;  but  it  is  significant  that 
their  conflict-drive  concept  leads  to  reasonably  clear-cut,  testable 
predictions,  which  apparently  could  not  have  been  made  without 
its  use. 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  221 

Summary 

The  problem  of  whether  an  increase  in  general  drive  is  produced 
by  frustrating  or  conflictful  situations  serves  as  the  focal  point  for 
the  discussions  of  this  chapter.  When  recast  into  a  form  con- 
sistent with  the  conceptual  framework  of  earlier  chapters,  this  is 
the  problem  of  whether  a  reference  reaction,  if  it  is  elicited  at 
about  the  time  some  other  activity  is  thwarted,  will  be  affected  as 
though  a  motivational  variable  had  been  introduced.  Throughout 
the  chapter  the  terms  thwarting  and  frustration  are  used,  respec- 
tively, to  designate  the  fact  of  response  interference  and  the  state 
or  condition  produced  by  interference. 

A  variety  of  methods  may  be  employed  to  prevent  the  initiation, 
continuation,  or  completion  of  a  response.  In  frustration  experi- 
ments with  animal  subjects,  physically  restrictive  devices  are  com- 
monly used.  These  may  take  the  form  of  solid  barriers  in  a  maze 
pathway,  delay  chambers,  restraining  harnesses,  and  locked  food- 
dish  covers.  Thwarting  may  also  be  produced  by  removing  some 
of  the  stimulus  objects  upon  which  the  to-be-thwarted  response 
depends  or  by  introducing  new  stimuli  to  which  incompatible  reac- 
tions have  been,  or  may  become,  conditioned.  With  human  sub- 
jects, thwarting  can  be  produced  by  verbal  instructions  to  the  effect 
that  the  subject  has  failed  or  has  performed  at  an  unsatisfactory 
level.  In  general,  the  ideal  method  for  producing  thwarting  would 
seem  to  be  one  that  interferes  with  a  response  or  response  chain 
while  producing  the  least  possible  alteration  of  the  normal,  re- 
sponse-eliciting stimulus  complex. 

The  introduction  of  experimental  conditions  believed  to  be 
thwarting  is  not  alone  sufficient  to  insure  that  the  to-be-blocked 
response  will  indeed  suffer  interference.  Typically,  therefore,  the 
success  of  a  blocking  operation  is  inferred  from  one  or  more  overt 
behavioral  changes.  The  observation  that  a  subject  repeatedly 
makes  partial  responses  resembling  his  prethwarted  reactions 
serves  as  one  criterion  for  evaluating  the  success  of  thwarting 
operations.  Abrupt  response  failure  following  the  introduction  of  a 
frustrating  condition  and  response  resumption  upon  the  removal 
of  that  condition  may  also  indicate  successful  response  blocking. 


222  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Motivational  theorists,  for  the  most  part,  are  partial  to  the  view 
that  thwarting  induces  a  state  (sometimes  a  response)  of  frustra- 
tion, which  in  turn  raises  the  subject's  level  of  drive.  Nevertheless, 
interpretations  containing  no  reference  to  drive  as  such  may 
also  provide  satisfactory  accounts  of  certain  phenomena  charac- 
teristic of  thwarting.  In  general,  such  explanations  of  frustration- 
situation  behavior  rely  on  the  view  that  thwarting  must  necessarily 
modify  stimulus  conditions  and  hence  associative  strengths.  In- 
creased vigor  of  responding,  persistent  trial-and-error  behavior,  and 
other  activities  typical  of  frustrating  situations  are  thus  seen  as 
instances  of  transfer  of  training,  stimulus  generalization,  and  the 
learning  of  new  responses  to  cues  attending  thwarting. 

Writers  favoring  motivational  views  generally  concur  in  as- 
suming that  frustration  leads  both  to  an  increment  in  drive  and 
to  the  production  of  frustration-specific  stimuli.  For  some  authors, 
however,  frustration  assumes  the  systematic  status  of  a  response. 
This  leads  to  the  conclusion  that  frustration  can  be  conditioned 
and  can  therefore  be  elicited  in  complete  or  in  fragmentary  form 
by  appropriate  stimuli.  The  weakening  of  instrumental  reactions 
antedating  frustration  is  explained  on  this  view  as  an  instance  of 
the  occurrence  of  fractional  anticipatory  frustration  reactions  hav- 
ing inhibitory  properties. 

In  the  majority  of  experiments  designed  to  reveal  the  motivat- 
ing properties  of  frustration,  an  increase  in  the  strength  of  an 
indicant  response  has  been  taken  as  the  criterion  of  heightened 
drive.  Thus,  enhanced  running  speed  following  nonreward  or  delay, 
heightened  vigor  of  lever  pressing  following  extinction  trials,  and 
excited  or  exaggerated  movements  have  all  provided  support  for 
the  frustration-drive  conception.  The  weakening  or  abandonment 
of  responses  antedating  an  increase  in  drive  is  also  a  potentially 
useful  criterion  for  the  identification  of  motivational  variables. 
Experimental  data  from  studies  in  which  delays  are  introduced 
in  runways  or  mazes  are  coordinate  with  this  criterion,  since  delay 
typically  leads  to  poorer  performance  in  pre-delay  portions  of  a 
maze.  Systematic  data  supporting  the  supposition  that  a  reduction 
in  frustration  drive  functions  as  reinforcement  for  the  learning  of 
new  responses  are  conspicuously  absent. 

Thwarting  may  usually,  if  not  always,  give  rise  to  the  appearance 


MOTIVATIONAL  EFFECTS  OF  FRUSTRATION  AND  CONFLICT  223 

of  competitive  reaction  tendencies,  and  since  conflict  is  commonly 
defined  by  reference  to  response  competition,  no  attempt  has  been 
made  here  to  differentiate  between  frustration  and  conflict.  Some 
experimental  findings  suggest  that  situations  labeled  "conflictful," 
like  those  termed  "frustrating,"  may  generate  increases  in  level 
of  motivation. 


CHAPTER 


7 


Motivational  Variables  and 
Hunnan  Perfornnance 

In  the  preceding  chapters  the  major  portion  of  the  experimental 
and  illustrative  material  was  drawn  from  investigations  of  animal 
behavior.  This  procedure  can  be  justified  on  the  ground  that  in 
large  measure  the  problems  and  theoretical  issues  under  examina- 
tion arose  from  basic  experiments  with  animal  subjects  and  that 
these  investigations  have  been  more  extensive  and  precise  than 
studies  of  human  motivation.  Significant  contributions  have  been 
made,  of  course,  to  our  knowledge  of  motivation  by  research 
workers  who  have  been  concerned  exclusively  with  human  be- 
havior. But  human  beings,  probably  because  of  the  extensive  role 
that  language  plays  in  their  activities,  present  us  with  unique 
motivational  problems  requiring  special  consideration.  This  and 
the  following  chapter,  therefore,  are  exclusively  devoted  to  the 
analysis  of  these  problems.  Although  a  sharp  distinction  probably 
cannot  be  drawn  between  behavior  that  is  perceptual  and  behavior 
that  is  not,  material  bearing  on  the  relations  of  motivational  vari- 
ables to  performance  in  perceptual  tasks  has  been  treated  sep- 
arately in  Chapter  8. 

224 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  225 

In  its  organizational  structure,  this  chapter  parallels  our  earlier 
discussion  of  methods  of  defining  drive.  Thus,  in  Chapter  2,  the 
assertion  was  made  that  drive  can  be  independently  defined  by 
reference  to  antecedent  conditions,  to  stimulus  conditions,  to  or- 
ganic states,  or  to  subjects'  responses  in  standardized  test  situa- 
tions. Here,  therefore,  we  shall  consider  some  of  the  effects  on  hu- 
man performance  of  drive-level  variations  believed  to  result  from 
deprivation  and  from  the  administration  of  strong  stimuli,  as  well 
as  the  effects  of  drive  differences  defined  in  terms  of  individual 
differences  in  test-situation  behavior. 


Deprivation-induced  Motivation 

Because  of  practical  difficulties  attending  the  induction  of 
severe  deprivation  states  in  human  subjects,  research  studies  of  the 
effects  of  such  deprivations  on  performance  are  rare.  Moreover,  of 
relevant  experiments,  a  majority  have  involved  behavior  that  is 
typically  termed  "perceptual"  and  hence  are  discussed  in  the  fol- 
lowing chapter. 

On  purely  theoretical  grounds,  whether  of  the  motivational  or 
associative  variety,  one  would  anticipate  that  specific  behavioral 
changes  would  be  exhibited  when  human  subjects  are  deprived  of 
food.  For  example,  from  the  multiplicative-drive  theory  it  would 
be  predicted  that  food  deprivation  would  lead  to  an  increase  in  D 
and  hence  to  an  increase  in  the  strengths  of  all  excitatory  tend- 
encies. Performance  level  in  a  variety  of  situations  should  be  im- 
proved by  hunger,  therefore,  provided  only  that  the  tendencies  to 
perform  the  correct  responses  are  the  dominant  ones  in  the  hier- 
archy of  reactive  tendencies.  However,  increased  drive  should  lead 
to  poorer  performance  whenever  incorrect  tendencies  are  stronger 
than  correct  ones.  Coupled  with  the  effects  of  increases  in  D  are 
effects  attributable  to  changes  in  internal  stimuli  {Smvs),  includ- 
ing self-administered  verbal  commands  or  instructions.  With  ex- 
tended periods  of  deprivation,  these  cues  may  increase  in  intensity, 
numerosity,  or  persistence,  and  since  specific  correct  or  incorrect 
response  tendencies  may  be  associated  with  these  stimuli,  marked 
changes  in  the  relative  strengths  of  all  reactive  tendencies  could 
accompany  severe  deprivation.  As  a  consequence,  definite  predic- 


226  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

tions  can  be  made  only  when  knowledge  of  the  comparative 
strengths  of  task-relevant  and  task-irrelevant  tendencies  is  avail- 
able. Behavior  is  jointly  determined  by  external  and  internal 
stimuli,  however,  and  hence  the  effects  of  deprivation  should  also 
depend,  to  a  considerable  degree,  on  the  kinds  of  stimuli  provided 
by  the  behavior-testing  situation  and  on  their  relations  to  the 
subjects'  learning  history.  Thus  a  stimulus  such  as  a  picture  of 
spaghetti  would  presumably  be  more  likely  to  elicit  food-related 
responses  from  a  hungry  Italian  child  than  from  a  child  who  has 
had  fewer  opportunities  to  associate  such  responses  with  both 
internal  hunger  stimuli  and  the  visual  cues  of  spaghetti. 

The  view  that  hunger  should,  as  a  consequence  of  intensified 
internal  cues,  lead  to  an  increase  in  food-related  verbal  responses  is 
supported  in  some  degree  by  both  anecdotal  and  experimental  evi- 
dence. Historical  reports  of  personal  experiences  during  periods  of 
famine  or  extended  deprivation  (Sorokin,  1942)  indicate  that  at 
such  times  concern  with  food  becomes  a  topic  of  overwhelming 
importance,  toward  which  the  individual's  thoughts  and  activities 
are  entirely  and  unceasingly  directed.  For  the  person  who  is  starv- 
ing food  becomes  the  central  focus  of  daydreams  and  conversa- 
tions. 

Of  especial  interest  in  this  connection  is  a  report  by  Brozek, 
Guetzkow,  and  Baldwin  (1951)  of  a  study  of  semistarvation  con- 
ducted during  the  year  1944-1945.  The  subjects  of  this  experi- 
ment, who  were  conscientious  objectors,  volunteered  to  undergo 
a  period  of  greatly  reduced  food  intake  for  a  period  of  24  weeks. 
Consistent  with  the  reports  of  ill-fated  expeditions  by  explorers 
and  others,  the  36  semistarved  subjects  gave  clear  evidence  that 
much  of  their  waking  thoughts  centered  on  food  and  on  related 
matters  such  as  cooking  and  agriculture.  "They  talked  and  read 
about  food.  Their  attention  was  attracted  by  the  scenes  of  food 
and  eating  in  the  movies.  .  .  .  Almost  any  discussion  was  likely 
to  end  by  talking  about  food.  Cook  books,  menus,  even  such  dry 
information  as  reading  bulletins  on  food  production  became 
fascinating  subjects  to  men  who,  a  few  months  earlier,  gave  little 
thought  to  the  fine  points  of  the  culinary  art  or  the  intricacies  of 
agricultural  statistics"  (p.  250).  But  these  men,  when  examined 
by  psychological  instruments  such  as  a  free-association  test,  the 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  227 

Rorschach  test,  and  Rosenzweig's  Picture  Frustration  Test,  gave 
almost  no  indication  of  enhanced  food-related  responses.  The  only 
positive  result  was  that  they  made  significantly  more  uncommon 
(idiosyncratic)  responses  to  the  food  words  of  the  free-association 
test  than  did  a  group  of  nonhungry  control  subjects.  The  finding 
that  a  greater  total  number  of  responses  was  given  to  the  Rorschach 
test  after  six  months  of  starvation  than  during  an  initial  control 
period  is  consistent  with  the  idea  that  the  drive  due  to  hunger 
should  enhance  all  responses.  But  similar  increases  were  not  found 
in  the  case  of  other  measures,  and  it  may  be  that  this  was  simply 
a  retest  phenomenon,  as  Brozek  et  al.  suggest. 

Just  why  the  psychological  tests  yielded  negative  results  is  un- 
clear, but  positive  evidence  for  the  effects  of  hunger  on  behavior 
might  have  been  obtained  had  different  tests  been  used.  It  is 
difficult,  on  intuitive  grounds,  to  believe  that  either  the  Rorschach 
test  or  the  Rosenzweig  Picture  Frustration  Test  provide  stimuli 
capable  of  eliciting  differential  responses  from  hungry  and  non- 
hungry  subjects.  This  is  indicated  by  the  fact  that  seven  subjects 
never  gave  a  food  response  to  the  Rorschach  test,  and  only 
eight  of  the  100  stimulus  words  used  in  the  free-association 
test  were  clearly  related  to  food  and  eating.  Perhaps,  therefore,  a 
closer  relationship  between  the  psychological-test  data  and  other 
behavioral  criteria  would  have  been  obtained  had  the  tests  con- 
tained a  larger  proportion  of  hunger-related  stimulus  items. 

The  investigation  of  Brozek  et  al.  involved  a  more  protracted 
and  severe  deprivation  state  than  that  of  any  other  experimental 
study.  Short-term  deprivation  effects,  however,  have  been  studied 
in  a  few  instances.  For  example,  Sanford  (1936),  in  what  may 
have  been  the  first  attempt  to  investigate  the  influence  of  hunger 
on  imaginal  processes,  administered  word-association  and  picture- 
interpretation  tests  to  school  children  both  before  and  after  lunch. 
More  than  twice  as  many  food-related  responses  were  elicited  by 
the  prelunch  tests  as  by  the  postlunch  tests.  In  a  subsequent  study, 
using  college  students,  Sanford  (1937)  found  a  progressively  in- 
creasing tendency  for  food-relevant  responses  to  occur  on  a  battery 
of  tests  as  deprivation  was  increased  up  to  24  hours. 

In  an  experiment  on  food  deprivation  and  imaginative  processes, 
Atkinson  and  McClelland  (1948)  asked  subjects  who  had  been 


228  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

without  food  for  1,  4,  and  16  hours  to  write  short  stories  about 
pictures  drawn  principally  from  Murray's  Thematic  Apperception 
Test.  The  specific  pictures  were  chosen  to  represent  a  variety  of 
aspects  of  situations  related  to  hunger,  such  as  satiation,  depriva- 
tion, food,  and  an  eating  place.  The  writers  were  asked  to  make 
their  stories  as  imaginative  and  interesting  as  possible,  and  the 
results  were  scored  by  noting  the  percentage  of  writers  whose  stories 
exhibited  certain  characteristics.  These  characteristics  or  categories 
were,  for  example,  story  plots  about  food,  statements  about  food 
deprivation,  about  activity  instrumental  to  the  securing  of  food, 
and  about  consummatory  activity.  Tabulations  of  responses  in 
these  categories  revealed  that  as  hunger  increased,  there  was  no 
over-all  increase  in  the  percentage  of  subjects  who  used  food 
imagery  or  food  themes  (plots)  in  their  stories.  Moreover,  there 
was  a  decided  decrease  in  the  number  of  references  to  the  goal 
activity  of  eating  as  a  function  of  deprivation  time.  Hunger  was 
accompanied,  however,  by  an  increase  in  the  percentage  of  stories 
in  which  food-deprivation  plots  and  deprivation-overcoming  in- 
strumental activity  appeared.  The  over-all  findings  were  thus  am- 
biguous, since  the  hypothesized  relation  between  need  and  need- 
related  imaginative  responses  was  supported  by  the  data  from  some 
scoring  categories  but  not  by  the  data  from  others. 

The  significance  of  the  particular  stimulus  items  used  in  tests 
designed  to  evaluate  the  effects  of  deprivation  on  performance  is 
underscored  by  the  results  of  the  Postman-Crutchfield  (1952)  ex- 
periment. These  investigators  varied  not  only  degree  of  hunger 
but  also  the  probability  that  a  stimulus  would  elicit  a  food  re- 
sponse as  well  as  the  strength  of  the  subject's  set  to  make  food 
responses.  The  stimuli  were  skeleton  words,  with  blank  spaces  to 
be  filled  in  by  the  subjects.  Different  types  of  lists  having  low, 
moderate,  and  high  probabilities  of  eliciting  food  responses  were 
used  in  conjunction  with  levels  of  hunger  ranging  from  0  to  6 
hours.  The  degree  of  selective  set  to  give  food  responses  was  varied 
by  arranging  the  first  few  words  of  the  lists  so  that  0,  1,  2,  or  5  food 
responses  would  be  elicited  from  different  groups  of  subjects  prior 
to  their  being  presented  with  the  principal  items  of  the  list. 

Analyses  of  data  from  rather  large  numbers  of  subjects  showed 
that  when  degree  of  food  set  and  type  of  list  (food-response  prob- 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  229 

ability)  were  held  constant,  no  simple  relation  existed  between 
intensity  of  need  and  frequency  of  need-related  responses.  Degree 
of  set,  however,  as  induced  by  increasing  numbers  of  prelist 
food  responses  did  lead  to  progressively  more  frequent  food  solu- 
tions to  the  skeleton  words.  The  only  way  in  which  hunger  affected 
performance  was  to  produce  slight  changes  in  the  relative  effec- 
tiveness of  the  different  levels  of  set.  That  is,  for  hungry  subjects 
(4  to  6  hours  of  deprivation)  the  function  relating  degree  of  set 
to  number  of  food  responses  was  positively  accelerated,  whereas 
for  nonhungry  individuals  (0  to  1  hour)  the  function  was  nega- 
tively accelerated.  It  was  also  found  that  the  effect  of  set  on  fre- 
quency of  word  solutions  was  greater  for  skeleton  items  having  a 
moderate  probability  of  eliciting  food  words  than  for  items  with 
either  a  very  low  or  a  very  high  probability.  Nonselective  energiz- 
ing effects  of  hunger  could  not,  of  course,  be  revealed  by  this  ex- 
periment since  every  subject  was  required  to  complete  the  same 
total  number  of  skeleton  words. 

Generally  speaking,  it  is  clear  from  the  Postman-Crutchfield 
study  that  the  selective  effects  of  mild  degrees  of  deprivation  are 
slight  and  can  be  demonstrated  only  by  carefully  designed  experi- 
ments in  which  a  delicate  balance  is  maintained  among  such  vari- 
ables as  set  and  initial  response  probability.  Quite  certainly,  if  all 
skeleton  words  elicited  food  responses,  or  if  none  did,  it  would  be 
impossible  to  demonstrate  that  variously  deprived  groups  of  sub- 
jects differ  with  respect  to  food-response  output.  The  test  items 
must  be  carefully  chosen  if  group  or  individual  differences  are  not 
to  be  obscured  by  either  "ceiling"  or  "floor"  effects.  This  is  not, 
incidentally,  a  problem  unique  to  the  measurement  of  deprivation 
effects.  It  is  characteristic  of  all  measurement  situations.  It  would 
be  impossible,  for  example,  to  find  out  how  well  children  solve 
arithmetic  problems  if  the  problems  are  either  so  easy  that  all 
children  obtain  scores  of  100,  or  so  difficult  that  none  can  be  solved 
by  any  student. 

In  only  one  experiment,  apparently,  has  the  relation  of  hunger 
to  eyelid  conditioning  been  explored.  Franks  (1957)  studied  the 
acquisition  and  extinction  of  eyelid  responses  in  nondeprived  sub- 
jects and  in  subjects  who  had  gone  without  food,  water,  and 
tobacco  for  approximately  22  hours.  Since  the  two  groups  did  not 


230  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

differ  significantly  in  number  of  conditioned  responses,  the  results 
failed  to  support  the  predictions  of  a  multiplicative-drive  theory. 
However,  the  procedures  followed  by  Franks  (massed  acquisition 
trials,  partial  reinforcement,  few  reinforced  trials)  were  rather  un- 
conventional, and  the  asymptotic  conditioning  levels  for  both 
groups  were  unusually  low.  A  replication  of  this  experiment  under 
conditions  more  favorable  to  the  development  of  conditioned  re- 
sponses is  clearly  indicated. 

The  possibility  that  hunger  might  selectively  affect  the  reten- 
tion of  previously  learned  materials  has  been  investigated  by  Wil- 
liams (1950).  In  his  studies  hunger,  which  was  introduced  after 
original  learning  had  been  completed,  had  no  effect  upon  the 
retention  either  of  words  that  were  directly  related  to  the  need 
or  of  neutral  words  that  had  been  associated  with  need-related 
words. 

By  way  of  summary  we  are  led  to  conclude  that  exceptionally 
little  is  known  of  the  effects  of  deprivation  on  human  performance 
in  nonperceptual  tasks.  We  do  not  know,  for  example,  whether 
hunger  tends  to  facilitate  a  broad  diversity  of  responses,  as  a  mul- 
tiplicative-drive theory  would  predict,  since  most  investigations 
have  not  been  designed  to  reveal  such  effects.  Nor  can  we  assert 
with  confidence  that  hunger  always  functions  selectively.  More- 
over, experiments  involving  deprivation  conditions  other  than  hun- 
ger are  practically  nonexistent,  and  we  possess  neither  reliable 
data  on  the  learning  of  various  tasks  under  different  drive  levels 
nor  information  on  the  effects  of  a  reduction  in  a  primary  need 
following  the  performance  of  successful  responses.  The  sum  and 
substance  of  our  current  knowledge  seems  to  be  that  under  rather 
restricted  conditions  hunger  sometimes  exerts  a  mildly  facilitative 
effect  upon  the  tendency  to  give  verbal  responses  related  in  one 
way  or  another  to  food  and  to  the  activities  connected  with  its 
procurement  and  consumption.  Under  other  experimental  circum- 
stances, however,  no  relation  between  hunger  and  performance 
has  been  observed. 


Motivating  Effects  of  Strong  Stimuli 

With  human  beings,  as  with  other  organisms,  it  has  long  been 
supposed  that  the  intense  stimulation  provided  by  electric  shocks. 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN   PERFORMANCE  231 

bright  lights,  loud  noises,  blasts  of  air,  and  internal  tensions  may 
function  as  a  motivational  variable. 

Electric  Shock.  Probably  because  of  the  ease  with  which  it  can 
be  administered,  electric  shock  has  been  used  with  a  wide  variety 
of  organisms  and  in  almost  every  conceivable  laboratory  situation. 
In  spite  of  its  widespread  use,  however,  standardized  techniques 
are  still  not  available  for  administering  and  measuring  shock,  and 
the  results  of  different  experiments,  even  when  they  purport  to 
be  investigating  the  same  problem,  are  seldom  in  agreement. 

Overt  changes  in  behavior  produced  by  electric  shock  are  quite 
diverse,  and  depend  not  only  on  shock  intensity  but  also  upon  its 
time  of  presentation  with  respect  to  a  response  or  response  se- 
quence. Obviously  shock  can  be  administered  consistently  either 
before,  during,  or  after  a  response  has  been  elicited  by  other 
stimuli.  Or  it  can  be  introduced  at  random  intervals  bearing  no 
systematic  temporal  relation  to  any  specific  response.  Let  us  con- 
sider these  two  modes  of  shock  presentation  in  turn. 

If  one  were  to  try  to  simulate,  with  electric  shock,  the  motivat- 
ing characteristics  of  hunger,  it  would  probably  be  necessary  to  use 
a  relatively  mild  continuous  shock  which  would  become  progres- 
sively stronger  over  a  period  of  hours.  One  might  then  study 
behavior  in  standardized  situations  with  different  initial  and/or 
terminal  levels  of  shock  and  with  partial  or  complete  shock  reduc- 
tion following  the  performance  of  specific  responses.  But  since 
most  human  subjects  object  to  such  treatment,  experimenters  have 
typically  used  rather  brief  shocks,  the  interval  between  response 
and  shock  being  held  constant.  On  theoretical  grounds  we  would 
anticipate  that  shock  administered  following  a  response  would 
have  a  different  effect  on  behavior  than  would  shock  presented 
while  a  response  is  in  progress  or  prior  to  its  appearance. 

The  consistent  administration  of  shock  following  a  particular 
response  presents  us  with  the  typical  paradigm  of  the  punishment 
situation,  and  the  observation  that  response  strength  is  thereby 
weakened  supports  the  belief  that  shock  is  functioning  as  a  moti- 
vational variable,  since  one  criterion  (Chapter  2)  for  the  identifi- 
cation of  such  variables  is  thereby  met.  The  literature  in  this  area 
is  voluminous,  but  the  experimental  results  are  by  no  means  uni- 
form. Probably  the  most  reasonable  general  conclusion  one  can 
draw  from  these  studies  is  that  behavior  consistently  preceding 


232  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

very  strong  shocks  tends  to  be  abandoned  (cf.  Postman,  1947), 
but  there  are  numerous  exceptions  to  this  rule. 

The  weakening  of  a  response  as  a  consequence  of  subsequent 
punishment  can  be  interpreted  in  several  ways.  For  example,  if 
shock  regularly  follows  a  response,  the  environmental  cues  eliciting 
that  reaction,  as  well  as  internal  response-produced  cues,  should 
acquire  the  capacity  to  evoke  conditioned  fear  reactions  (cf.  Chap- 
ter 5 ) .  Initially,  fear-produced  increments  in  drive  might  augment 
the  strength  of  the  punished  response,  but  subsequently,  with 
extremely  strong  fear,  competing  responses  might  be  aroused  and 
their  appearance  in  lieu  of  the  punished  response  might  be  rein- 
forced by  a  reduction  in  fear.  Alternatively,  postresponse  shocks 
could  elicit  escape  or  withdrawal  reactions  that  might  be  reinforced 
by  shock  cessation  and  might  competitively  interfere  with  the  prin- 
cipal to-be-punished  reaction.  For  instance,  a  subject  may  be 
shocked  on  the  fingers  each  time  he  enters  a  blind  alley  in  a  finger 
maze.  If  the  shock  is  terminated  whenever  he  moves  his  hand 
away  from  the  end  of  the  alley,  such  escape  movements  may  be 
reinforced;  and  since  these  newly  acquired  movements  are  op- 
positely directed  to  those  involved  in  entering  the  blind,  the  latter 
may  be  overridden  or  weakened. 

The  administration  of  rather  mild  shocks  after  the  occurrence 
of  particular  responses  may  serve  simply  to  inform  the  subject  as 
to  the  correctness  or  incorrectness  of  his  reactions.  Thus  it  has 
been  shown,  by  Tolman,  Hall,  and  Bretnall  (1932),  and  by  Muen- 
zinger  (1934),  for  example,  that  shocks  following  correct  responses 
in  a  maze  are  sometimes  as  effective  in  producing  learning  as  are 
shocks  following  errors.  Shocks  administered  in  this  way  may  or 
may  not  have  significant  motivational  effects,  but  they  clearly 
qualify  as  associative  variables  since  they  provide  specific  knowledge 
of  results.  Weak  shocks  probably  lead  neither  to  escape  reactions 
nor  to  increments  in  drive,  and  conditioned  emotional  reactions 
should  seldom  develop  from  their  being  paired  with  neutral  cues. 

The  introduction  of  shock  prior  to  the  occurrence  of  a  response 
might  be  expected  to  have  motivational  consequences  if  shock- 
induced  emotionality  or  other  processes  persist  until  the  response 
is  evoked.  Or  if  shock  precedes  a  response  by  only  a  very  brief 
interval,  shock-elicited  skeletal  responses  might  perseverate  for  a 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  233 

time  and  interfere  with  the  subsequently  ehcited  criterion  reaction. 
In  this  case,  of  course,  the  dechne  in  response  strength  would 
qualify  as  an  instance  of  competitive  interaction  among  responses 
and  hence  as  an  example  of  an  associative  effect. 

Precisely  similar  analyses  would  appear  to  be  applicable  to 
situations  in  which  shock  is  administered  coincidentally  with  an 
ongoing  reaction.  On  a  multiplicative-drive  theory  any  shock 
should  intensify  whatever  behavior  is  in  progress  and  thereby  fulfill 
the  energizing  criterion  of  motivational  variables.  But  the  more 
intense  the  shock,  the  higher  the  probability  that  it  will  elicit 
strenuous  responses  of  vocalization  or  escape  and  thereby  lead  to 
a  decline  in  the  efficiency  of  overt  performance.  In  every  instance 
shock  can  apparently  function  both  as  a  source  of  drive  and  as  a 
specific  stimulus  capable  of  arousing  a  variety  of  defensive  reac- 
tions. When  behavior  is  facilitated  by  shock,  the  effect  can  be 
ascribed  either  to  an  increase  in  drive  (motivational  theory)  or 
to  the  appearance  of  a  facilitative  response  (associative  theory). 
Likewise,  performance  degradation  can  be  attributed  to  the  ap- 
pearance of  shock-induced  competing  reactions,  or  to  an  initial 
superiority  of  task-irrelevant  reaction  tendencies  in  comparison 
with  the  correct  ones. 

If  electric  shocks  are  presented  at  random  intervals  they  cannot 
provide  reliable  task-specific  information  to  the  subject  nor  is  it 
likely  that  stable,  stimulus-specific  conditioned  fear  reactions  will 
develop.  Nonetheless,  behavior  might  be  affected  either  positively 
or  negatively,  since  the  subject's  general  drive  level  might  be  in- 
creased and/or  competing  responses  might  be  evoked.  Experi- 
mental evidence  indicating  that  random  shocks  sometimes  lead  to 
improved  performance  has  been  reported  by  several  investigators 
(e.g.,  Gilbert,  1936,  1937;  Rosenbaum,  1953;  Spence,  Farber,  and 
Taylor,  1954),  but  such  shocks  also  have  been  found  to  disrupt 
the  performance  of  some  subjects  (Deese,  Lazarus,  and  Keenan, 
1953).  In  so  far  as  random  shocks  function  facilitatively,  support 
is  provided  for  the  multiplicative-drive  view,  since  these  shocks 
do  not  provide  cues  appropriate  to  the  solution  of  a  problem. 

Unconditioned  Stimuli  as  Sources  of  Drive.  In  the  experiments 
we  have  just  reviewed,  the  reference  responses  being  studied  were 
typically  not  elicited  by  shock.  However,  when  shock  is  used  as 


234  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

the  UCS  in  human  conditioning  studies,  it  probably  functions  both 
as  an  ehcitor  of  the  to-be-conditioned  reaction  and  as  a  source  of 
drive.  In  a  typical  experiment  (e.g.,  eyelid  conditioning),  if  a 
response  is  to  be  counted  as  "conditioned,"  it  must  occur  after 
the  onset  of  the  CS  and,  generally  speaking,  before  the  onset  of 
the  UCS.  Consequently,  on  any  one  conditioning  trial,  the  drive 
produced  by  the  UCS  cannot  affect  the  latency,  and  perhaps  not 
even  the  magnitude,  of  a  foregoing,  anticipatory  CR.  Both  latency 
and  amplitude  could  be  affected,  however,  by  residual  drive  from 
UCS  presentations  on  earlier  trials.  Thus,  as  Spence  (1958)  has 
surmised,  if  one  group  of  subjects  is  conditioned  v^ith  a  strong  air 
puff  and  another  with  a  weak  air  puff,  the  former  should  have  a 
higher  average  drive  level  than  the  latter.  Because  of  this  the  fre- 
quency of  CRs  should  be  directly  related  to  the  intensity  of  the 
puff,  or  more  generally,  to  UCS  intensity. 

Available  experimental  data,  though  surprisingly  sparse,  support 
these  expectations.  In  what  may  have  been  the  first  study  of  this 
kind,  Passey  (1948)  reports  that  mean  frequency  of  conditioned 
eyelid  responses  increases  in  an  approximately  linear  manner  as 
a  function  of  the  logarithm  of  air-puff  intensity.  Subsequently, 
Spence  (1956,  1958)  and  his  associates  have  repeatedly  shown 
that  conditioned  eyelid  responses  are  more  frequent  when  strong 
rather  than  weak  puffs  are  used.  The  dashed-line  curve  of  Fig.  7:4, 
which  appears  in  another  context  later  on  in  this  chapter,  clearly 
shows  this  effect.  In  addition,  acquisition  curves  obtained  with 
different  UCS  intensities  tend  to  diverge  during  the  course  of 
training.  This  finding  is  consistent  with  the  assumption  that  the 
habit  strengths  for  the  groups  under  comparison  are  multiplied 
by  different  magnitudes  of  drive  (D).  Also  relevant  here  is  Mc- 
Allister's (1953)  study  in  which  it  was  shown  that  the  eyebhnk 
response  is  extinguished  far  more  rapidly  when  the  UCS  is  omitted 
entirely,  and  hence  drive  level  is  lowered,  than  when  the  UCS 
continues  to  be  presented,  though  separated  from  the  CS  by  an 
interval  too  long  to  produce  conditioning. 

Unfortunately,  no  UCSs  other  than  air  puffs  have  apparently 
been  systematically  manipulated  in  classical  conditioning  experi- 
ments with  human  subjects.  It  remains  to  be  seen,  therefore, 
whether  the  consistent  results  obtained  in  the  eyelid  situation 
can  be  reproduced  with  other  aversive  stimuli  and  other  responses. 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  235 

It  is  also  evident  that  other  interpretations  are  possible  beside  that 
which  attributes  drive-arousing  properties  to  the  UCS.  Variations 
in  UCS  level  might  affect  performance  not  only  by  changing  drive, 
but  also  by  altering  habit  strength  or  by  evoking  different  classes 
of  unconditioned  responses. 

Noise.  Industrial  psychologists  have  long  been  concerned  with 
the  problem  of  how  a  worker's  efEciency  is  affected  by  the  loud 
noises  that  often  accompany  manufacturing  processes.  Experi- 
mental attempts  to  investigate  this  problem  have  not,  however, 
pointed  unambiguously  to  any  one  general  conclusion.  In  some 
cases  noise  seems  to  have  a  facilitative,  dynamogenic  effect  on 
performance,  though  marked  increases  in  energy  output  and  in 
fatigue  are  typical  accompaniments  of  such  effects.  In  other  cases, 
especially  where  the  noise,  because  of  its  intermittency  or  other 
special  characteristics,  appears  to  elicit  competing  reactions,  per- 
formance declines.  By  and  large,  however,  the  most  extensive 
studies  of  performance  under  noise,  such  as  those  of  Stevens  and 
his  collaborators  (1946),  indicate  that  performance  on  a  variety 
of  psychomotor  and  intelligence  tests  is  not  significantly  changed 
by  prolonged  exposure  to  noise.  This  may  or  may  not  mean  that 
noise  has  no  motivational  effects.  Quite  possibly,  noises  of  certain 
kinds  may  produce  increments  in  drive  strength,  and  yet,  at  the 
same  time,  elicit  interfering  responses.  To  date  there  are  few 
experiments  on  performance  under  noise  in  which  adequate  num- 
bers of  subjects  have  been  tested  and  in  which  irrelevant  factors 
of  suggestion  and  the  like  have  been  adequately  controlled  (cf. 
Chapanis,  Garner,  and  Morgan,  1949).  We  must  conclude,  there- 
fore, that  while  noise  may  function  as  a  motivational  variable,  its 
effects  are  in  marked  degree  a  function  of  its  specific  characteristics, 
especially  as  these  relate  to  the  rhythm  or  other  aspects  of  the 
task,  to  the  operator's  level  of  proficiency,  and  to  numerous  other 
variables. 


Motivating  Effects  of  Instructions 

Verbal  instructions,  whether  administered  before,  during,  or 
after  a  bit  of  behavior  has  been  exhibited,  are  stimuli,  which,  like 
electric  shock  and  noise,  may  have  motivational  consequences.  As 
we  have  already  remarked  in  discussing  acquired  sources  of  drive, 


236  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

nonspecific  "hurry-up"  instructions  seem  to  function  motivationally 
to  facilitate  whatever  behavior  is  taking  place  or  is  about  to  take 
place.  Besides,  individuals  seem  to  learn  to  motivate  their  own 
activities  by  administering  similar  "try-hard"  instructions  to  them- 
selves. The  laboratory  psychologist  is  well  aware  that  performance 
levels  can  be  changed  if  subjects  are  told  that  the  task  is  impor- 
tant (or  unimportant),  that  the  test  is  a  measure  of  intelligence, 
that  the  results  will  affect  their  standing  in  class,  or  that  they  have 
failed  or  succeeded.  As  with  all  variables  alleged  to  have  motiva- 
tional effects,  however,  instructions  may  modify  performance  either 
by  virtue  of  their  cue  properties  and  the  resulting  changes  in  asso- 
ciative strengths  or  through  a  change  in  drive  strength,  or  in  both 
ways. 

When  verbal  instructions  contain  specific  cues  appropriate  to 
the  responses  being  scored  as  correct,  improvement  in  performance 
is  expected  and  is  seldom  considered  to  be  a  motivational  outcome. 
For  example,  if  a  subject  were  told  which  way  to  go  at  each  choice 
point  of  a  maze  in  order  to  stay  on  the  true  path,  his  improved 
performance  in  comparison  with  that  of  noninstructed  subjects 
would  not  qualify  as  a  motivational  effect.  But  if  he  were  simply 
told  to  do  his  best,  and  if  this  instruction  were  followed  by  superior 
performance,  we  would  be  more  likely  to  conclude  that  a  change 
in  drive  had  been  produced.  Instructions  to  "do  your  best"  provide 
no  specific  response-directing  cues,  and  if  improved  performance 
follows  it  may  be  due  to  nonassociative  processes.  This  is  not  to 
say,  however,  that  a  nonmotivational  interpretation  of  such  results 
could  not  be  defended.  One  could  always  argue,  for  instance,  that 
alleged  motivation-inducing  instructions  augment  performance  not 
because  they  add  an  increment  to  drive,  but  because  they  arouse 
a  whole  family  of  learned  facilitative  responses  such  as  sitting 
erect,  concentrating  on  the  task  at  hand,  and  suppressing  inclina- 
tions to  daydream. 

Instructions  to  subjects  to  the  effect  that  they  have  either  failed 
or  succeeded  in  the  performance  of  an  assigned  task  are  commonly 
held  to  exert  motivational  influences  on  subsequent  tasks.  But 
here  again,  as  Lazarus,  Deese,  and  Osier  (1952)  and  Farber  (1955) 
have  observed,  it  is  desirable  to  distinguish  between  the  purely 
motivational  effects  of  such  instructions  and  their  associative  (in- 
formative) consequences.  For  the  most  part,  the  kinds  of  instruc- 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  237 

tions  described  by  the  terms  success  and  failure  tend  to  be  unre- 
lated to  the  particular  responses  involved  in  performing  a  just- 
completed  task.  They  tend,  that  is,  to  be  relatively  general  state- 
ments such  as  "You  have  done  better  (or  worse)  than  most  people 
do  on  this  task."  The  nonspecific  nature  of  such  instructions 
minimizes,  though  it  does  not  eliminate,  the  likelihood  that  sub- 
sequent behavior  will  be  affected  through  associative  channels.  The 
most  general  finding  of  studies  of  instruction-induced  failure  seems 
to  be  that  subsequent  performance  is  impaired  (cf.  Farber,  1955), 
but  this  effect  could  be  interpreted  equally  well  by  either  a  motiva- 
tional or  an  associative  theory.  As  Farber  notes,  "...  the  impair- 
ment of  performance  by  failure  does  not  necessarily  demonstrate 
its  associative  effects,  nor  does  the  improvement  of  performance 
by  failure  demonstrate  its  drive  effects.  Just  as  the  associative  mech- 
anism attending  failure  may  either  benefit  or  harm  performance, 
so  might  an  increase  in  drive,  in  and  of  itself,  affect  behavior 
either  favorably  or  adversely,  depending  on  the  specific  nature  of 
the  task  and  the  experimental  conditions  involved"  (p.  317). 

Because  of  the  conflicting  nature  of  experiments  designed  to 
manipulate  human  motivational  level  by  means  of  verbal  instruc- 
tions, and  because  none  seems  to  have  been  designed  so  that  the 
separate  contributions  of  drive  and  associations  can  be  evaluated, 
we  have  chosen  not  to  review  them  in  detail.  Praise  or  reproof 
may  lead  either  to  better  or  poorer  performance,  depending  upon 
the  nature  of  the  experimental  conditions,  which  are  as  yet  poorly 
understood,  and  upon  the  characteristic  ways  in  which  individual 
subjects  react  to  those  conditions,  to  the  experimenter,  and  to 
his  comments  concerning  the  subject's  performance.  About  all  one 
can  say  with  assurance  is  that  associative  factors  probably  play  a 
dominant  role  when  the  instructions  are  related  to  the  correctness 
or  incorrectness  of  specific  responses  and  that  a  concept  of  a 
nonspecific  drive  may  be  useful  when  success-failure  statements 
are  very  general. 

Response-defined  Motivational  Level 

In  the  preceding  sections  of  this  chapter  we  have  dealt  briefly 
with  some  theoretical  and  experimental  aspects  of  human  mo- 
tivational differences  as  defined  by  amount  of  deprivation  and 


238  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

intensity  of  stimulation.  The  remainder  of  the  chapter  is  devoted 
to  studies  in  which  degree  of  drive  or  motivation  is  defined,  not  by 
the  manipulation  of  an  external  variable,  but  in  terms  of  individual 
differences  in  responses  to  standardized  tests.  In  the  studies  to  be 
considered,  motivation  is  said  to  differ  among  individuals  who 
respond  differently  to  the  stimuli  provided  by  projective  or  ques- 
tionnaire tests. 

As  the  reader  may  recall  from  Chapter  2,  drive  level  can  be 
operationally  defined,  independently  of  the  behavior  to  be  ex- 
plained, by  noting  how  different  subjects  react  in  a  given  situation. 
The  finding  of  stable  individual  differences  in  reactivity  permits 
us  to  rank-order  our  subjects  with  respect  to  test  performance,  and 
if  we  choose  to  define  drive  in  terms  of  test  scores,  we  can  then 
rank-order  our  subjects  with  respect  to  drive.  Drive  differences  thus 
defined  may  never,  of  course,  turn  out  to  be  significantly  related 
to  performance  in  any  other  situation  or  to  other  theoretical  con- 
cepts. If  not,  then  other  ways  of  defining  drive  may  be  tried  and 
the  most  useful  definition  provisionally  adopted. 

Psychologists  have  sometimes  claimed  that  the  use  of  response- 
defined  drive  levels  is  to  be  avoided  as  not  "truly  experimental," 
since  drive  is  not  being  manipulated  directly.  That  this  objection 
is  unfounded  can  be  made  clear  by  the  following  example.  Suppose 
we  desire  to  vary  the  intensity  of  a  stimulus  light  in  our  laboratory. 
We  can  achieve  this  variation  either  by  adjusting  the  amount  of 
electric  current  that  is  allowed  to  flow  through  the  filament  of  a 
single  lamp,  or  by  selecting  several  different  lamps  from  an  avail- 
able population  of  lamps.  The  first  method  parallels  that  in  which 
drive  is  "manipulated"  by,  say,  changing  the  strength  of  shock 
administered  prior  to  a  behavioral  test.  The  second  is  like  that  in 
which  individuals  having  specific  degrees  of  the  property  in  ques- 
tion, i.e.,  strength  of  drive,  are  chosen  from  a  large  population 
by  means  of  a  test.  Since  standardized  instruments  for  measuring 
light  intensity  have  been  developed  by  the  physicist,  the  readings 
of  such  instruments  can  be  used  to  support  the  contention  that 
selective  and  manipulative  procedures  can  lead  to  the  same  out- 
come. In  principle,  the  selective  and  manipulative  methods  of 
varying  drive  can  also  be  equated,  but  until  practical  instruments 
for  assessing  drive  strength  have  been  developed  and  standard- 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  239 

ized,  any  assertion  to  the  effect  that  a  particular  level  of  test-de- 
fined drive  is  identical  with  one  produced  experimentally  must 
remain  open  to  question. 

Critics  of  the  selective  procedure  have  argued  further  that 
individuals  who  differ  with  respect  to  their  responses  on  an  al- 
leged test  of  drive  may  also  differ  in  a  variety  of  other  ways,  thus 
confounding  other  variables  with  drive.  The  comment,  though 
legitimate,  is  not  a  criticism  uniquely  relevant  to  the  selective  pro- 
cedure. It  applies  with  equal  cogency  to  the  manipulative  methods 
as  well.  Thus  when  we  try  to  change  drive  by  experimentally  alter- 
ing deprivation  time  or  by  administering  different  strengths  of 
shock,  we  may  also  be  altering  associative  strengths,  hormonal 
levels,  and  many  other  factors.  Likewise,  in  manipulating  the 
intensity  of  light  from  a  single  bulb,  changes  in  the  color  of  the 
light  may  be  produced,  just  as  bulb  diameter  may  fluctuate  when 
intensity  is  varied  by  the  selection  of  particular  lamps.  However, 
if  our  standard  light-measuring  device  is  insensitive  to  color  and 
to  bulb  diameter,  then  the  presence  of  these  confounding  variables 
is  of  no  consequence.  And  in  the  case  of  drive,  if  there  is  reason 
to  believe  that  the  behavior  being  studied  is  insensitive  to  the  pres- 
ence of  known  or  suspected  confounding  variables,  then  changes 
in  such  ancillary  factors,  whether  produced  by  manipulative  or 
selective  methods,  can  be  ignored.  In  principle,  therefore,  there  is 
as  much  justification  for  trying  to  vary  drive  by  a  process  of  selec- 
tion as  by  seemingly  more  direct  experimental  manipulations.  No 
one  can  predict,  at  present,  which  of  the  many  varieties  of  each 
method  will  ultimately  yield  the  most  useful  and  significant  esti- 
mate of  drive,  nor  whether  one  of  the  methods  will  ultimately 
prove  to  be  better  than  the  other. 

Motivation  Defined  by  Imaginative  Responses 

One  of  the  most  extensive  research  programs  directed  toward 
evaluating  human  motivation  by  means  of  subjects'  responses  is 
that  of  McClelland  and  his  principal  associates,  Atkinson,  Clark, 
and  Lowell  (1953). 

As  we  have  already  seen  (Chapter  5),  these  authors  use  the 
word  motive  to  designate  learned,  and  only  learned,  anticipations 


240  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

(expectations)  of  rewards  or  punishments.  An  individual  has  a  fear 
motive  or  an  anxiety  motive  if,  when  exposed  to  cues  that  have 
previously  been  followed  by  punishment,  he  experiences  an  affec- 
tive (emotional)  arousal  similar  to,  or  representative  of,  the  arousal 
produced  by  pain  or  punishment.  An  organism  has  a  hunger 
motive  when,  as  a  consequence  of  repeated  eating  experiences,  the 
internal  cues  accompanying  deprivation  or  external  cues  (or  both) 
arouse  an  affectively  toned  expectancy  of  the  pleasurable  conse- 
quences of  eating.  We  have  previously  noted  that  these  negative 
and  positive  motives  are  essentially  identical,  in  their  origins  and 
affective  aspects,  with  conditioned  anticipatory  fear  reactions  and 
anticipatory  fractional  goal  responses,  respectively.  The  achieve- 
ment motive,  which  has  been  studied  most  extensively,  is  defined 
as  a  learned,  affective  anticipation  of  the  pleasurable  consequences 
of  success  in  situations  where  the  quality  or  efficiency  of  one's 
performance  is  to  be  evaluated.  Overt  behavior  is  assumed  to  be 
affected  "motivationally,"  though  in  ways  that  are  never  clearly 
specified,  by  the  arousal  of  one  or  more  motives  such  as  these. 

Measuring  Human  Motive  Strength.  In  attempting  to  develop 
an  adequate  definition  of  human  motive  strength,  McClelland 
and  his  coworkers  have  concentrated  their  attention  upon  the 
content  of  imaginative  responses  given  by  subjects  to  a  standardized 
test.  Specifically,  subjects  are  presented  with  a  series  of  relatively 
uninformative  pictures  resembling  those  in  the  Thematic  Apper- 
ception Test,  and  are  asked  to  tell  an  imaginary  story  about  each. 
The  stories  are  then  scored  by  counting,  according  to  certain  rules, 
the  number  of  ideational  items  believed  to  be  diagnostic  of  the 
presence  of  a  specific  motive.  Individuals  or  groups  can  thus  be 
rank-ordered  with  respect  to  the  strength  of  a  given  motive  as 
defined  by  the  frequency  of  their  motive-relevant  reactions  to  the 
pictures.  The  performance  of  the  same  individuals  under  other 
conditions  can  then  be  studied  to  see  whether  it  is  meaningfully 
related  to  fantasy-defined  motive  strength. 

This  technique  of  defining  individual  differences  in  motive 
strength  in  terms  of  subjects'  reactions  to  one  situation  (story 
telling)  and  of  using  such  differences  to  explain  performance 
variation  in  a  second  situation  exemplifies  the  response-based 
method  (Chapter  2)  of  independently  defining  drive.  The  proce- 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  241 

dure  entails  the  working  out  of  an  R-R  relation,  and  involves  the 
assumption  that  the  motive  governs  both  imaginative  reactions 
and  test-situation  performance. 

In  principle,  any  set  of  reactions  to  a  standardized  test  can  be 
used  to  define  motive  strength,  but  McClelland  et  al.  regard  the 
fantasy  content  of  stories  as  uniquely  suitable.  Their  preference 
for  this  method  rests  upon  the  traditional  psychoanalytic  view 
that  unguarded  free  associations  provide  the  richest  material  for 
studying  human  motives,  upon  their  belief  in  the  fruitfulness  of 
the  method,  and  upon  the  questionable  assumption  that  fantasies 
are  not  affected  by  a  subject's  specific  knowledge  or  factual  in- 
formation. 

Experimentally  Aroused  Motive  Strength.  One  of  the  first  ex- 
periments in  this  area,  one  we  have  already  briefly  discussed,  was 
performed  by  Atkinson  and  McClelland  (1948).  These  investiga- 
tors reasoned  that  if  the  content  of  imaginative  thought  reflects 
motive  strength,  changes  in  that  content  should  follow  from  ex- 
perimentally induced  variations  in  the  intensity  of  a  motive.  An 
adult  human  being  who  has  been  deprived  of  food  should  possess 
a  hunger  motive,  and  the  presence  and  strength  of  this  motive 
should  be  revealed  through  imaginative  stories  by  an  increase  in 
the  frequency  of  food-  and/or  eating-related  items.  As  we  have 
seen,  Atkinson  and  McClelland's  expectations  were  not  borne  out 
in  the  case  of  food-related  responses,  though  increased  hunger  was 
accompanied  by  more  frequent  references  to  food  deprivation. 
Nevertheless,  this  minimally  satisfying  relation  was  taken  as  con- 
firming the  hypothesis  that  with  lengthened  deprivation  the  hun- 
ger motive  was  aroused  more  vigorously  by  the  combined  action 
of  deprivation  and  picture  cues,  and  that  the  intensified  motive 
enhanced  the  probability  of  occurrence  of  food-related  imagina- 
tive responses. 

By  means  of  additional  experiments  McClelland  and  his  col- 
laborators have  tried  to  show  that  conditions  designed  to  induce 
the  arousal  of  the  motives  of  sex,  fear,  affiliation,  and  achievement 
also  lead  to  corresponding  increases  in  the  motive-related  content 
of  imaginative  stories.  With  the  exception  of  Clark's  (1952)  ex- 
periment on  the  sex  motive,  stories  produced  under  conditions 
regarded  as  motivating  ".  .  .  contained  more  imaginative  responses 


242  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

dealing  with  thoughts,  feehngs,  and  actions  related  to  the  goal- 
directed  sequence  of  the  motive  in  question"  (Atkinson,  1954, 
p.  66).  For  reasons  not  yet  well  understood,  however,  these  results, 
obtained  with  male  subjects,  could  not  be  replicated  with  women, 
Wlien  the  same  procedures  were  tried  with  female  subjects,  as 
many  motive-related  imaginative  responses  were  obtained  when 
the  motives  were  supposedly  aroused  as  in  nonaroused  control  con- 
ditions. 

With  these  experiments  as  a  foundation,  the  conclusion  was 
reached  that  the  strength  of  almost  any  motive  could  be  estimated 
from  the  frequency  with  which  certain  types  of  imagery  appeared 
in  subjects'  stories  about  pictures.  Thus  if  one  person  gives  more 
food-related  responses  to  pictures  suggesting  eating  than  does 
another,  the  inference  is  drawn  that  the  former  is  hungrier,  has  a 
stronger  motive  to  eat,  than  the  latter.  And  the  person  whose 
imaginative  stories  contain  frequent  references  to  success  and 
achievement  is  presumed  to  have  a  stronger  motive  to  achieve 
than  one  whose  imaginative  output  is  less  rich  in  words  connoting 
goal  attainment. 

The  Achievement  Motive  and  Overt  Behavior.  Much  of  the 
research  effort  of  the  McClelland  group  has  been  directed  toward 
determining  the  ways  in  which  motives,  especially  the  need  for 
achievement,  influence  overt  behavior  other  than  that  involved  in 
the  telling  of  imaginative  stories.  They  have  sought  to  determine 
whether  groups  of  individuals  defined  as  having  strong  need  for 
achievement  will  perform  more  effectively  on  various  tests  or  tasks 
than  low-achievement  groups. 

That  need  for  achievement  apparently  does  not  function  as  a 
nonspecific  energizer  after  the  manner  of  Hull's  D  is  suggested  by 
the  data  from  several  investigations.  Thus  Zatzkis  (1949)  failed 
to  find  a  clear  or  significant  relation  between  the  mean  number 
of  words  written  in  a  class  essay  and  the  need-achievement  scores 
of  the  student  writers.  Moreover,  McClelland  et  al.  (1953)  re- 
ported that  subjects  with  low  need-achievement  scores  gave  a 
greater  mean  number  of  responses  to  the  10  cards  of  the  Rorschach 
test  than  did  the  high  scorers,  with  moderate  need-achievers  giving 
more  responses  than  either  high  or  low.  And  finally,  Atkinson 
(1950),  in  a  study  preparatory  to  one  on  the  recall  of  completed 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE 


243 


and  uncompleted  tasks,  found  that  with  a  Hmited  number  of 
tasks  subjects  who  scored  high  on  the  need-achievement  test  never 
completed  significantly  more  tasks  than  did  subjects  with  low 
need-achievement  scores.  In  fact,  under  instructions  designed 
to  be  relaxing  rather  than  motivating,  the  high  need-achievers  per- 
formed significantly  fewer  tasks  than  the  low  need-achievers. 

Inasmuch  as  McClelland  and  his  collaborators  have  never  speci- 
fied precisely  what  it  is  that  a  motive  does  when  functioning  as  a 
motivator,  considerable  uncertainty  remains  as  to  how  overt  be- 
havior should  be  affected  by  a  motive  such  as  the  need  for  achieve- 
ment. Generally  speaking,  however,  these  investigators  appear  to 
hold  that  increased  motive  strength  should  lead  to  faster  perform- 
ance and  greater  work  output,  or,  under  unspecified  conditions, 
to  more  efficient  performance. 

Perhaps  the  best  support  for  the  expectation  that  high  need- 
achievers  should  perform  better  than  those  with  low  scores  is 
provided  by  Lowell's  (1952Z?)  experiment.  His  college  student  sub- 
jects were  required  to  perform  a  simple  arithmetic  task  for  a  period 
of  ten  minutes.  Tabulations  of  the  number  of  addition  problems 
solved  during  each  two-minute  period  showed  that  subjects  high 
on  the  achievement  scale  performed  more  efficiently  during  each 
practice  period  than  subjects  who  were  low  on  the  scale.  These 
data,  which  are  presented  graphically  in  Fig.  7:1,  are  cited  by 
Atkinson  (1954)  as  the  kind  of  relation  that  "has  often  been  used 


Fig.  7:1.  Performance 
levels  obtained  on  a  sim- 
ple addition  task  by  in- 
dividuals v^fho  had  at- 
tained high  and  low 
scores  on  a  need-for- 
achievement  test.  {From 
Lowell,  19S2b.) 


30 


'?;28 


26 


24 


High  need-achievement 
A' =  19 


Low  need-achievement 
N  =  2l 


S  y' 


.T. 


2  3  4 

Two-minute  periods 


244 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


to  illustrate  the  so-called  'energizing'  function  of  motives"  (p.  71). 

Of  special  interest  in  connection  with  this  experiment  is  the 
reported  fact  that  the  subjects  of  the  two  groups  did  not  differ 
significantly  in  respect  to  their  basic  numerical  skills  as  measured 
by  the  quantitative  score  on  the  ACE  Psychological  Examination. 
This  would  seem  to  imply  that  achievement  motivation  was  func- 
tioning as  a  nonselective  energizer  to  enhance  performance,  since 
it  indicates  that  the  basic  skills  (associative  factors)  of  the  two 
groups  were  equal.  But  from  another  point  of  view  this  is  puzzling. 
On  the  basis  of  published  statements  concerning  the  nature  of  the 
achievement  motive,  one  would  expect  the  motive  to  be  aroused 
during  the  taking  of  the  ACE  test  to  an  even  greater  degree  than 
during  an  experiment  requiring  the  performance  of  simple  addi- 
tions. Consequently,  it  may  be  appropriate  to  ask  why  the  high 
need-achievement  group  differed  from  the  low  group  on  the  simple 
addition  tests  but  not  on  the  quantitative  portion  of  the  intelli- 
gence test.  Performance  on  an  intelligence  test  involves  the  efficient 
utilization  of  knowledge  and  conceptual  skills  as  well  as  basic 
capacity,  and  highly  motivated  individuals  should  perhaps  perform 
more  efficiently  on  such  tests. 

In  another  part  of  Lowell's  experiment,  high  and  low  need- 
achievers  were  required  to  reconstruct  common  words  from  scram- 
bled arrangements  of  the  letters.  On  this  task,  as  Fig.  7:2  shows, 


Eo 


14 


13 


12 


11 


10 


High  need- 
achievement 


-Low  need- 
achievement 


3       4        5       6        7 

Two-minute  periods 


10 


Fig.  7:2.  These  data  indicate  that  subjects  with  high  need-achievement  scores 
tend  to  improve  during  the  course  of  an  anagrams  task,  whereas  subjects  with 
low  scores  do  not.  (Adapted  from  Lowell,  1952b.) 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   HUMAN   PERFORMANCE  245 

the  two  groups  did  not  differ  greatly  at  first,  but  the  high  need- 
achievement  group  showed  a  progressive  increase  in  facihty  with 
practice  while  the  other  group  did  not.  The  difference  between 
the  over-all  means  for  the  two  groups  was  not  statistically  signifi- 
cant, but  the  divergence  of  the  two  curves  was  said  to  be  highly 
reliable.  This  finding  has  been  interpreted  (McClelland  et  al., 
1953)  to  mean  that  where  learning  is  possible,  as  in  this  scrambled- 
words  task,  subjects  with  strong  achievement  motivation  learn  as 
the  task  progresses,  and  the  skills  thus  acquired  are  facilitated  by 
the  achievement  motive.  Moreover,  the  occurrence  of  learning  is 
said  to  strengthen  the  view  that  need-achievement  scores  do  indeed 
reflect  level  of  motivation.  The  view  is  based  on  the  supposition 
that  the  mere  occurrence  of  learning  constitutes  a  decisive  criterion 
for  evaluating  the  presence  of  a  motive.  Here  the  authors  have 
failed  to  see  that  for  most  theorists  learning  provides  an  adequate 
criterion  of  motivation  only  when  a  reduction  in  motivation  has 
clearly  been  involved. 

Lowell's  finding  that  the  so-called  highly  motivated  group  per- 
formed more  poorly  than  the  low  group  during  the  first  two  min- 
utes of  the  test  is  also  rather  puzzling.  Assuming  equal  skills  in 
unscrambling  the  mixed-up  words,  we  should  expect  a  more  highly 
motivated  group  to  do  better  initially  than  a  poorly  motivated 
one.  The  failure  to  find  an  initial  difference  is  even  more  disturb- 
ing when  we  realize  that  relevant  skills  were  probably  not  equal 
at  the  outset,  since  the  group  with  high  achievement  scores  was 
significantly  superior  to  the  low  group  on  the  linguistic  score  of 
the  ACE  test.  The  divergence  of  the  curves  probably  can't  be 
explained,  however,  in  terms  of  differences  in  linguistic  ability 
alone.  When  this  "intelligence"  factor  was  held  constant  by  the 
technique  of  partial  correlation,  there  was  still  a  significant  correla- 
tion (r  =  .44)  between  achievement  motivation  and  output  of 
scrambled  words. 

Additional  evidence  purporting  to  show  that  performance  in 
certain  situations  is  enhanced  by  high  achievement  motivation 
has  been  reported  by  McClelland  and  Liberman  (1949).  Accord- 
ing to  these  investigators,  subjects  with  high  achievement  motiva- 
tion exhibit  lower  recognition  thresholds  for  words  denoting  sue- 


246  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

cess  than  do  subjects  with  low  achievement  motivation.  This  may 
or  may  not  be  a  motivational  phenomenon,  however,  since  the  two 
groups  might  not  have  been  equally  familiar  with  the  critical 
stimulus  words.  Moreover,  Veroff,  Wilcox,  and  Atkinson  (1953) 
showed  that  women  with  high  achievement-motivation  scores  did 
better  than  those  with  low  scores  during  the  middle  portion  of  an 
anagrams  test  when  the  general  level  of  performance  tended  to  lag. 
Hedlund  (1953),  however,  was  unable  to  replicate  this  finding. 
Evidently  we  cannot  yet  accept  the  conclusion  that  performance 
in  a  variety  of  situations  is  enhanced  by  high  achievement  mo- 
tivation. Furthermore,  as  Atkinson  (1954)  has  noted,  a  number 
of  the  supportive  experiments  involve  behavioral  measures  con- 
cerning which  the  theoretical  expectations  are  not  especially  clear. 
How  Motives  Affect  Behavior.  In  their  early  publications  Mc- 
Clelland and  his  associates  failed  to  indicate  how  motives,  as 
defined  by  them,  function  as  determinants  of  verbal  fantasy  re- 
sponses or  of  responses  in  problem  solving  and  other  task  situations. 
Atkinson  (1954)  has  tried  to  fill  this  gap  by  relating  the  concept 
of  motives  to  the  expectancy  theories  of  MacCorquodale  and 
Meehl  (1953)  and  of  Tolman  and  Postman  (1954).  Considering 
first  the  question  of  how  motives  might  affect  imaginative  responses 
to  TAT-like  pictures,  it  is  clear  that  here  Atkinson  has  adopted 
a  straightforward  associative  view.  Thus  he  maintains  that  while 
motives  are  being  learned  many  additional  reactive  tendencies 
(response  predispositions)  are  also  becoming  associated  with  the 
same  cues.  The  internal  stimuli  of  hunger,  for  example,  tend  to 
arouse  not  only  the  anticipation  of  food  (the  hunger  motive)  but 
also  verbal  and  other  responses  that  are  related  to  eating,  to  a 
wide  variety  of  different  foods,  and  to  the  situations  in  which 
eating  has  frequently  taken  place.  Consequently,  when  pictures 
containing  food-related  cues  are  presented  to  hungry  subjects,  the 
combination  of  internal  and  picture-provided  cues  tends  to  elicit 
food-related  imaginative  responses.  In  essence,  the  stronger  the 
hunger  motive,  the  stronger  the  learned  predisposition  to  use  words 
related  to  eating,  and  the  greater  the  likelihood  that  such  words 
will  be  evoked  by  the  joint  action  of  picture  cues  and  the  com- 
bination  of   hunger-produced   and   anticipation-of-food-produced 
cues.  Similarly,  a  high  achievement  motive  should  be  accompanied 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  247 

by  strong  predispositions  to  perform  certain  kinds  of  responses 
(including  words),  and  in  telling  imaginative  stories,  therefore, 
subjects  so  motivated  should  be  more  likely  to  use  words  related 
to  achievement.  It  is  thus  evident  that  a  motive,  defined  as  a 
learned,  affective,  anticipatory  process  does  not  function,  with 
respect  to  fantasy  responses,  as  a  drivelike  energizer,  but  only  as 
a  source  of  stimuli  to  which  specific  kinds  of  associations  have 
been  developed.  Only  the  single  principle  of  interactions  among 
families  of  associative  tendencies  is  involved  in  the  theoretical 
explication  of  the  alleged  motivationlike  effects  of  motives  upon 
imaginative  verbal  responses. 

In  dealing  with  behavior  in  problem-solving  and  learning  situa- 
tions, Atkinson  appeals  to  two  different  kinds  of  expectancies. 
One  of  these,  the  motive,  is  the  affectively  toned  expectation  of 
either  good  or  bad  things  to  come.  The  second  kind  of  expectancy 
is  described  as  cognitive  or  perceptual  rather  than  affective.  Such 
an  expectancy  is  a  consequence  of  the  organism's  repeated  expe- 
riences with  environmental  objects  and  their  interrelations.  It  is 
approximately  equivalent  to  Tolman's  (1948)  notion  of  a  "cogni- 
tive map"  and  to  Hull's  construct  of  habit  strength.  This  cognitive 
expectancy,  much  like  Hull's  habit  strength,  is  apparently  in- 
capable, when  acting  in  isolation,  of  leading  to  overt  behavior.  A 
person  may  know  that  food  can  be  obtained  from  a  neighborhood 
store  and  precisely  how  to  get  there  (cognitive  expectancy),  but 
he  will  not  travel  to  the  store  to  get  food  unless  he  has  a  desire 
to  eat  (motive-type  expectancy).  According  to  Atkinson,  the  final 
tendency  to  respond  overtly  depends  jointly  upon  these  two  kinds 
of  expectancies. 

Atkinson's  treatment  still  leaves  us  in  doubt,  however,  as  to  the 
"motivating"  role  of  the  motive-type  expectancy.  In  one  of  his 
diagrams  the  motive  is  shown  as  multiplying  the  environmentally 
cued  performance  expectancy,  but  in  the  accompanying  text  we 
are  told  only  that  "mutual  facilitation"  increases  the  strength  of 
the  disposition  to  respond.  Apparently,  the  use  of  the  multiplicative 
sign  in  this  diagram  was  not  intended  to  parallel  Hull's  use  of 
the  same  symbol,  since  Atkinson  holds  that  a  motive  facilitates 
only  those  instrumental  reactive  tendencies  that  have  a  terminal 
member,  the  goal  concept,  in  common  with  the  motive.  This  sort 


248  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

of  selective  enhancement  is  evidently  more  representative  of  an 
associative  than  of  a  motivational  interpretation.  On  this  view,  if 
an  animal  is  made  hungry  and  is  then  placed  into  an  alley  where 
it  has  previously  received  only  water  when  thirsty,  the  two  ex- 
pectancies would  not  have  a  common  goal  member.  The  environ- 
mental cues  would  arouse  the  expectation  of  obtaining  water  in 
the  goal  box,  but  the  hunger  motive  would  arouse  the  anticipation 
of  eating  food.  Hence,  this  theory  would  seem  to  predict  that  the 
hungry  animal's  instrumental  responses  of  running  down  the  alley 
and  especially  his  responses  of  drinking  water  would  not  be  en- 
hanced by  the  presence  of  the  hunger  motive.  However,  as  we  have 
seen  in  our  review  of  Miller's  (1948b)  experiments  (Chapter  3), 
hunger  does  seem  to  facilitate  responses  previously  learned  under 
thirst. 

In  summary,  it  appears  that  a  motive,  as  defined  by  McClelland 
and  his  associates,  always  functions  as  a  selective  facilitator,  capa- 
ble of  enhancing  only  restricted  sets  or  classes  of  responses.  In  this 
respect  a  motive  differs  markedly  from  a  motivational  concept 
such  as  Hull's  drive,  which  is  assumed  to  multiply  all  learned  and 
unlearned  reactive  tendencies.  The  two  conceptions  also  differ,  in- 
cidentally, in  that  Hull's  theory  predicts  that  increased  drive  will 
lead  to  poorer  performance  under  certain  conditions,  whereas  the 
motive  theory  always  seems  to  predict  enhanced  performance.  In 
addition,  the  mechanisms  through  which  motives  exert  their  selec- 
tive effects  either  upon  imaginative  responses  or  upon  behavior 
in  learning  and  problem-solving  situations  seem  to  involve  no  prin- 
ciples other  than  those  of  conventional  associative  learning  theory. 
This  may  be  a  virtue,  but  it  has  naturally  led  certain  critics  (e.g., 
Farber,  1954b)  to  wonder  whether  the  term  motivational  is, 
strictly  speaking,  appropriate  to  either  the  theory  or  the  research 
of  McClelland  and  his  coworkers. 

Selective  Response  Facilitation.  Tlie  view  that  a  motive  func- 
tions selectively  to  enhance  motive-related  responses  presents  an 
interesting  problem  for  theoretical  analysis.  Let  us  suppose  we 
were  to  perform  an  experiment  like  that  of  Atkinson  and  McClel- 
land (1948),  and  that  our  subjects  tended,  as  time  of  food  depriva- 
tion increased,  to  give  greater  numbers  of  imaginative  responses 
related  to  food  and  eating.  If  our  pictures  had  been  appropriately 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  249 

chosen,  the  cues  they  provided  might  have  aroused  learned  asso- 
ciative tendencies  to  emit  food  responses  which  were  equal  in 
strength  to  the  tendencies  to  give  nonfood  reactions.  If  hunger 
were  functioning  as  a  generalized  drive  (D),  the  excitatory  tend- 
encies to  make  both  food-related  and  non-food-related  responses 
should  be  strengthened  equally  as  deprivation  time  increased. 
This  would  mean  that  although  the  proportion  of  food-related  to 
non-food-related  reactions  would  be  the  same  for  all  our  groups, 
the  total  number  of  responses  of  each  kind  would  increase  with 
hunger.  Hence,  if  between-group  comparisons  were  made  on  the 
basis  of  food-related  words  only,  hunger  would  appear  to  have  a 
selectively  energizing  effect,  when  in  fact  it  had  not.  On  the 
other  hand,  if  our  pictures  elicited  more  food-relevant  than  non- 
food-relevant words,  we  should  expect,  from  a  multiplicative-drive 
theory,  that  the  absolute  difference  between  the  number  of  food 
and  nonfood  responses  would  increase  across  groups  with  intensi- 
fied hunger.  In  this  case,  increases  both  in  the  absolute  number  of 
food-related  words  and  in  their  frequency  compared  with  non- 
food-related words  would  be  predicted  as  deprivation  was  length- 
ened. Apparently  then,  what  seems  to  be  a  selective  energizing 
effect  can,  in  theory,  be  produced  by  an  increase  in  generalized 
drive  level.  In  one  case  this  results  from  a  comparison  between 
groups  when  deprivation-relevant  and  deprivation-irrelevant  re- 
sponse tendencies  are  equally  strong,  and  in  the  other,  from  com- 
parisons either  between  or  within  groups  when  deprivation-related 
tendencies  are  initially  dominant. 

Selective  sensitization  of  food-related  responses  could  also  be 
produced,  however,  by  the  presence  of  specific  associative  tend- 
encies established  through  prior  learning  to  the  cues  accompanying 
hunger  (cf.  Brown,  1953a).  Thus  intensified  hunger  should  lead  to 
more  food  responses,  provided  food  responses  have  been  associated 
with  the  internal  stimuli  of  deprivation.  Were  such  a  mechanism 
as  this  operating  effectively,  one  would  predict  that  the  difference 
favoring  food-related  over  non-food-related  words  would  increase 
either  within  a  single  group  or  across  groups  as  deprivation  was 
extended.  Moreover,  the  effect  should  be  obtainable  even  when 
the  external  cues  provided  by  test  pictures  tend  to  elicit  initially  as 
many  food-related  as  non-food-related  responses.  Obviously  this  is 


250  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

an  associative  view,  since  selective  sensitization  is  explained  with- 
out invoking  either  a  multiplicative  drive  or  a  motive. 

One  might  maintain,  of  course,  that  increased  deprivation  leads, 
as  in  the  above  interpretation,  to  stronger  internal  cues  and  hence 
to  stronger  habits  but  that  these  habits  are  reflected  in  overt  be- 
havior via  their  effect  upon  other  habits.  Thus  the  tendencies  to 
make  food-related  responses  that  are  associated  with  deprivation 
stimuli  might  combine  with  the  reactive  tendencies  incited  by 
picture  cues  to  increase  relevant  response  frequency.  This  might  be 
treated  conceptually  as  a  matter  of  stimulus  summation  or  in 
terms  of  the  facilitative  effects  of  one  habit  set  upon  another.  In 
either  event,  the  interpretation,  which  closely  parallels  that  pro- 
posed by  Atkinson,  would  once  again  be  associative  rather  than 
motivational. 

Alternative  Proposals  for  Measuring  Achievement  Motivation. 
According  to  McClelland  (1956),  he  and  his  associates  have  in- 
vestigated a  variety  of  methods  of  measuring  achievement  motiva- 
tion that  do  not  involve  imaginative  stories.  However,  none  of  the 
substitute  methods  proved  to  be  successful,  the  criterion  of  success 
being  an  appreciable  correlation  with  achievement  scores  derived 
from  the  content  analysis  of  fantasy.  Among  the  methods  tried 
were:  {a)  story  alternatives  to  the  pictures,  presented  in  multiple- 
choice  form;  (b)  word  stems  to  be  completed  with  achievement 
and  nonachievement  alternatives;  and  (c)  agreement  with  achieve- 
ment sentiments  on  a  questionnaire.  The  only  promising  tech- 
nique, one  developed  by  Aronson  (1956),  is  also  a  kind  of  projec- 
tive or  expressive  test.  This  investigator  finds  that  content  analyses 
of  spontaneous  doodles  yield  consistent  significant  correlations 
with  need-achievement  scores  over  several  samples  of  college  stu- 
dents. It  is  McClelland's  (1956)  belief  that  this  method  is  poten- 
tially valuable  because  it  presumably  can  be  used  for  children  too 
young  to  tell  stories,  for  civilizations  without  written  records,  for 
persons  who  are  apparently  too  anxious  about  achievement  to  write 
of  it  fluently,  and  for  groups  who  speak  entirely  different  languages. 

In  spite  of  these  failures  to  find  other  useful  techniques  for  meas- 
uring the  need  for  achievement,  some  progress  has  been  reported 
by  investigators  outside  of  the  McClelland  group,  Elizabeth 
French  (1956),  for  example,  reports  some  success  in  developing 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  251 

a  measure  of  complex  motives  that  does  not  involve  the  use  of 
pictures.  In  her  test,  which  is  disguised  as  a  test  of  insight,  the 
subjects  are  presented  with  ten  single-sentence  descriptions  of  the 
behavior  of  hypothetical  individuals.  A  sample  sentence  is  "Ray 
works  much  harder  than  other  people,"  and  the  subjects  are  asked 
to  "explain"  the  behavior  described  therein.  The  rationale  of  the 
test  is  that  subjects  who  have,  say,  high  achievement  motivation, 
will  tend  to  project  that  motivation  into  their  explanations  of  the 
hypothetical  instances  of  behavior.  Some  of  the  test  items  were 
adapted  from  those  used  by  Sheriffs  (1948),  and  the  method  of 
scoring  the  subjects'  answers  was  similar  to  that  used  by  McClel- 
land. By  altering  the  nature  of  the  scoring  categories,  estimates  of 
either  the  achievement  motive  or  the  affiliation  motive  were  said 
to  be  obtainable.  It  is  too  early  to  know  how  this  type  of  test  will 
compare  with  the  more  traditional  method  of  measuring  achieve- 
ment motivation,  but  French  has  reported  a  significant  correlation 
of  .48  between  performance  on  a  digit-letter  substitution  test  and 
test-defined  achievement  motivation  under  task-orienting  instruc- 
tional conditions. 

After  prolonged  practice  in  the  scoring  of  TAT  stories  following 
the  procedure  of  McClelland  and  his  associates,  a  satisfactory  de- 
gree of  interscorer  agreement  can  apparently  be  obtained.  Never- 
theless, many  workers  have  found  that  even  after  considerable 
training  scoring  reliabilities  remain  low.  To  circumvent  this  dif- 
ficulty an  objective  form  of  the  TAT  called  the  Iowa  Picture 
Interpretation  Test  (IPIT)  was  developed  at  the  State  University 
of  Iowa.  In  this  test,  TAT  pictures  are  presented  singly,  each  one 
accompanied  by  a  set  of  four  verbal  statements.  Within  each  set 
of  statements,  one  is  designed  to  reflect  achievement  motivation 
and  the  other  three  to  reflect  insecurity,  blandness,  and  hostihty. 
The  statements  were  selected  as  relevant  to  each  of  these  four 
categories  on  the  basis  of  judgments  by  clinical  psychologists.  The 
subjects'  task  is  to  look  at  each  picture  and  indicate  the  degree  to 
which  the  accompanying  statements  are  appropriate  to  the  pic- 
ture by  arranging  them  in  rank  order.  Scores  are  computed  by 
obtaining  the  sum  of  the  ranks  for  each  category. 

Preliminary  administrations  of  the  test  for  standardization  pur- 
poses revealed  that  the  test-retest  reliability  of  the  achievement 


252  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

scores,  though  discouragingly  low,  was  about  the  same  as  that  of 
the  standard  story  form  of  the  TAT  when  scored  by  skilled  raters. 
However,  achievement  imagery  scores  from  the  IPIT  (Hurley, 
1955)  failed  to  correlate  significantly  (r  =  .12,  N  =  45)  with 
scores  obtained  by  means  of  McClelland's  system  of  scoring.  Never- 
theless, Williams  (1955)  has  reported  that  subjects  with  high 
achievement  scores  (IPIT-defined)  worked  significantly  faster  on 
a  simple  test  of  addition  than  subjects  with  low  scores.  This  find- 
ing is  similar  to  that  reported  by  Lowell  (1952b),  using  the 
McClelland  method  of  scoring,  and  is  supported  further  by  John- 
ston's (1957)  data  showing  that  high  achievement-imagery  sub- 
jects of  both  sexes  attempted  significantly  more  simple  addition 
problems  over  10  two-minute  trials  than  did  subjects  with  low 
achievement  ratings.  In  addition,  Johnston  (1955)  found  that 
high  achievement  subjects  perform  more  efficiently  on  an  elec- 
trical maze  task,  and  Hurley  (1957)  reports  a  positive  relation 
between  IPIT  achievement  scores  and  the  frequency  of  both  cor- 
rect and  incorrect  responses  in  a  verbal  learning  task.  It  would 
seem,  therefore,  that  IPIT  achievement  ratings  may  reflect,  in 
part,  individual  differences  in  level  of  motivation.  Nevertheless, 
considerable  research  remains  to  be  done  before  it  can  be  con- 
cluded that  the  IPIT  is  measuring  a  motivational  variable  rather 
than  something  else  or  that  extensive  similarities  exist  between 
whatever  variable  it  does  measure  and  other  purported  measures  of 
achievement  motivation.  Encouraging  evidence  for  the  view  that 
a  good  objective  scoring  method  may  eventually  be  developed  has 
recently  been  presented  by  Johnston  (1957),  who  showed  that  the 
test-retest  reliability  of  the  IPIT  could  be  substantially  improved 
by  lengthening  the  test. 

Finally,  it  is  worth  noting  that  Hedlund  (1953)  has  made  a 
serious  effort  to  objectify  the  categories  by  which  achievement 
scores  are  obtained  from  subjects  who  are  exposed  to  achievement- 
type  TAT  pictures.  He  designed  an  objective  multiple-choice 
test,  called  the  Iowa  Multiple-choice  Achievement  Imagery  Test, 
which  consisted  of  70  three-foil  items.  One  foil  of  the  three  was  an 
achievement-related  statement  and  the  other  two  were  unrelated. 
Ten  such  items  were  constructed  for  each  of  seven  achievement- 
motive-arousing  pictures.  The  result  of  parallel  experimental  ad- 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  253 

ministrations  of  both  the  objective  test  and  of  the  standard  story 
form  was  that  the  internal  consistency  of  both  tests  over  pictures 
was  extremely  low.  That  is,  individual  pictures  did  not  tend  in  a 
consistent  manner  to  yield  comparable  estimates  of  the  relative 
need  for  achievement  of  different  individuals.  Moreover,  neither 
Hedlund's  objective  test  nor  the  standard  story  form  was  related 
in  any  clear-cut  manner  to  several  aspects  of  classroom  perform- 
ance or  to  performance  on  an  anagrams  test.  In  this  latter  respect 
Hedlund's  results  failed  to  corroborate  the  relationship  between 
achievement  scores  and  anagrams  performance  previously  reported 
by  Clark  and  McClelland  (1950).  Hedlund  concluded,  therefore, 
that  neither  the  objective  form  nor  the  story  form  of  the  need- 
achievement  test  had  predictive  utility  for  the  specific  performance 
criteria  he  chose  to  investigate. 

Motivational  Differences  Defined  in  Terms  of  Scores 
on  a  Scale  of  Manifest  Anxiety 

In  this  section  we  shall  consider  theory  and  evidence  relating 
to  the  view  that  individual  differences  in  level  of  general  drive  can 
be  usefully  defined  in  terms  of  the  responses  of  subjects  to  ques- 
tionnaire items  purporting  to  reflect  manifest  anxiety.  This  con- 
ception, developed  originally  by  Janet  Taylor  (1951),  and  by 
Spence  and  Taylor  (1951),  has  led  to  an  extensive  amount  of 
discussion  and  research,  and  only  the  barest  outline  of  its  many 
details  and  ramifications  can  be  presented  here. 

Taylor's  method  of  defining  human  drive  level  by  means  of  an 
anxiety  scale  was  grounded  upon  Hull's  multiplicative-drive  theory 
and  upon  the  results  of  studies  of  the  acquired  drive  of  fear  in 
animals  (see  Chapter  5).  The  extension  of  these  principles  and 
relations  to  human  behavior  suggests  that  those  who  differ  in 
degree  of  fearfulness  or  anxiety  should  also  differ  correspondingly 
in  general  level  of  drive.  And  if  drive  strengths  differ,  then  be- 
havior in  diverse  situations  should  be  affected  in  a  manner  con- 
sistent with  the  assumption  that  drive  (D)  is  a  nonspecific  factor 
affecting  all  reactive  tendencies.  Those  who  have  studied  the  rela- 
tion between  questionnaire-defined  anxiety  and  performance  have 
addressed  themselves  essentially  to  these  problems. 


254  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Taylor's  manifest  anxiety  scale  (referred  to  hereafter  simply  as 
the  MAS)  was  constructed  in  the  form  of  a  questionnaire-type 
personality  inventory.  Its  component  items,  many  of  which  were 
adapted  from  the  Minnesota  Multiphasic  Personality  Inventory, 
posed  questions  that  clinical  psychologists  judged  would  elicit 
answers  reflecting  manifest  emotionality  or  anxiety.  Few  if  any 
of  the  individuals  who  have  worked  with  the  MAS,  at  least  among 
those  in  the  Iowa  group,  have  ever  been  concerned  with  the  prob- 
lem of  whether  the  test  measures  "true  anxiety,"  whatever  that 
may  mean.  Nevertheless,  as  Taylor  (1956cz)  has  shown,  MAS 
scores  correlate  about  as  well  with  psychiatrists'  judgments  of 
manifest  anxiety  and  with  other  criteria  as  do  other  tests  purport- 
ing to  measure  anxiety.  But  these  correlations  are  irrelevant  to  the 
central  aim  of  most  of  the  studies  involving  the  MAS.  The  mem- 
bers of  the  Iowa  group  have  simply  assumed  that  it  may  be  useful 
to  define  drive  level  (D)  in  terms  of  MAS  scores.  They  have  then 
proceeded  to  explore  the  utility  of  this  definition  by  determining 
whether  performance  in  a  variety  of  situations  is  affected  in  ways 
that  are  consistent  with  the  theoretical  implications  of  this  defini- 
tion and  of  the  system  from  which  it  springs. 

Empirical  Findings  of  MAS  Studies.  The  first  and  still  one  of 
the  most  striking  findings  in  the  MAS  literature  is  that  reported  in 
Taylor's  original  paper.  She  administered  her  test  to  members  of 
an  undergraduate  class  and  on  the  basis  of  their  answers  picked 
out  a  high-drive  (high  anxiety)  and  a  low-drive  (low  anxiety) 
group.  The  high-drive  group  consisted  of  those  who  fell  in  the 
upper  12  per  cent  of  the  distribution  of  MAS  scores,  and  the  low- 
drive  group  was  made  up  of  those  in  the  lower  9  per  cent.  When 
both  groups  were  run  under  identical  conditions  in  an  eyelid-con- 
ditioning situation,  it  was  found  that  the  high-drive  subjects  con- 
ditioned more  rapidly  than  did  the  low-drive  subjects.  As  the  con- 
ditioning curves  (Fig.  7:3)  for  these  subjects  show,  the  anxious 
subjects  conditioned  much  more  rapidly  than  did  those  in  the 
nonanxious  group.  Presumably  the  habit  strengths  of  the  two 
groups  were  equal  since  both  were  given  the  same  number  of  condi- 
tioning trials.  The  difference  between  the  performance  levels  of 
the  two  groups  is  highly  significant  and  is  entirely  consistent  with 
the  hypothesis  that  the  groups  differed  in  general  drive  strength. 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN   PERFORMANCE 


255 


10 


Nonanxious  Ss  / 
/ 

— ^ 


11-20    21-30  31-40   41-50   51-60  61-70  71-80 
Trials 

Fig.  7:3.  Eyelid-conditioning  curves  for  subjects  with  high  (anxious)  and  low 
(nonanxious)  scores  on  a  questionnaire  designed  to  measure  degree  of  mani- 
fest anxiety.  {From  Taylor,  19 SI.) 


Since  the  appearance  of  Taylor's  paper,  her  principal  finding  that 
eyelid  conditioning  is  better  with  high-anxious  subjects  has  been 
confirmed  in  eight  independent  experiments  (see  Taylor,  1956d; 
Spence,  1956;  Spence  and  Ross,  1957).  In  all  but  one  of  these 
studies  the  differences  were  statistically  significant. 

In  a  summary  of  experimental  evidence  bearing  on  the  relation 
of  anxiety  to  performance  level  in  eyelid  conditioning,  Spence  and 
Ross  (1957)  and  Spence  (1958)  have  pointed  out  that  the  agree- 
ment among  studies  from  the  Iowa  laboratory  has  been  supris- 
ingly  good.  Not  only  has  the  anxiety-level  variable  yielded  rather 
uniform  results,  but  degree  of  conditioning  has  also  been  shown 
to  vary  with  the  strength  of  the  UCS,  a  variable  which,  as  we 
have  noted  above,  is  also  presumed  to  affect  drive  level.  Fig.  7:4, 
reproduced  from  Spence  (1958),  illustrates  these  rather  remark- 
able interexperiment  consistencies.  The  four  points  on  the  curve 
labeled  "random  subjects"  are  from  four  independent  experiments 
in  which  randomly  selected  subjects  were  employed.  As  would  be 
expected  from  the  theory,  these  points  define  a  curve  falling  be- 
tween the  curves  for  high  and  for  low  anxiety.  The  data-points  on 


256 


THE  MOTrVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


the  high-  and  low-anxious  curves  corresponding  to  puff  intensities 
of  0.25  and  1.5  pounds  per  square  inch  are  from  an  unpublished 
experiment  by  Spence  and  Haggard,  and  the  remaining  four  points 
are  from  the  Spence  and  Taylor  (1951)  investigation.  Especially 
impressive  is  the  fact  that  although  the  three  functions  were  ob- 
tained by  combining  the  results  of  six  different  experiments,  the 
functions  all  exhibit  the  same  general  negatively  accelerated  form. 
The  evidence  from  studies  of  classical  defense  conditioning, 
then,  is  rather  consistent  in  showing  that  high-drive  subjects  ac- 
quire conditioned  reactions  more  quickly  than  do  low-drive  sub- 
jects. At  least  two  experiments,  however,  one  by  Hilgard,  Jones, 
and  Kaplan  (1951)  and  one  by  Bitterman  and  Holtzman  (1952) 
have  failed  to  support  the  expectations  of  the  anxiety-drive  theory 
with  respect  to  performance  in  classical  conditioning  situations. 
In  the  former,  although  the  high-anxious  subjects  gave  more  con- 
ditioned eyelid  responses  than  the  low-anxious  subjects,  the  dif- 
ference was  not  statistically  significant.  And  in  the  second  study, 
in  which  the  galvanic  skin  response  rather  than  the  eyelid  re- 


70 


60 


50 


5  40 


30 


■      0       0.25  0.6  1.0  1.5  2.0 

Intensity  of  unconditioned  stimulus -Ibs/sq  in. 

Fig.  7:4.  These  data,  assembled  from  a  number  of  different  experiments,  in- 
dicate primarily  that  the  strength  of  conditioning  increases  with  the  intensity 
of  the  unconditioned  stimulus.  Also  to  be  seen  are  unusually  consistent  differ- 
ences attributable  to  level  of  manifest  anxiety.  {From  Spence,  1958.) 


High 

anxious  Ss\ 

^^^.^^^ 

-^' 

-         ^ 

"^-Random  Ss 

^^  J  i 

/     1 

""^ 

^^,^^ 

' 

/      f 

^^"""^ 

/      / 

'       / 

^  Low  anxious  Ss 

/       F^ 

1       / 

1      / 

1      / 

4     / 

1               I 

1 

MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  257 

sponse  was  being  conditioned,  college  subjects  in  the  upper  50 
per  cent  of  the  distribution  of  MAS  scores  were  slightly  but  not 
significantly  superior  with  respect  to  conditionability.  As  Taylor 
(1956cz)  points  out,  however,  the  number  of  subjects  in  the  first 
experiment  was  unusually  small,  and  in  the  second  moderately 
anxious  subjects  were  included  in  both  the  high-  and  low-anxious 
groups  by  the  procedure  of  selection. 

Anxiety,  Chronic  or  Acute?  Concerning  the  general  concept  of 
anxiety  and  level  of  drive,  it  is  of  interest  to  note  that  two  views  of 
the  process  have  been  proposed  by  members  of  the  Iowa  group. 
Taylor,  in  her  original  article,  suggested  that  subjects  who  scored 
high  on  her  scale  might  be  considered  chronically  anxious.  If  so, 
they  would  tend  to  behave  as  though  they  had  a  relatively  high 
level  of  drive  even  in  nonstressful  situations.  Alternatively,  Rosen- 
baum  (1953),  and  Spence,  Farber,  and  Taylor  (1954)  have  se- 
riously entertained  the  possibility  that  persons  who  score  high  on 
the  MAS  are  individuals  who,  though  not  especially  anxious  when 
performing  simple,  familiar  tasks,  become  anxious  or  overreact 
emotionally  when  tested  in  unusual  or  threatening  situations.  On 
the  first  of  these  views,  high  anxiety  is  regarded  as  more  or  less 
chronically  present  in  certain  individuals;  on  the  second,  it  is  an 
acute  emotional  reaction  or  state  aroused  only  in  stressful  kinds  of 
situations. 

The  experimental  evidence  bearing  upon  these  two  views  of  the 
nature  of  anxiety  is  not  yet  sufficiently  extensive  to  permit  us  to 
choose  between  them,  though  the  weight  of  evidence  seems  to 
favor  the  acute  theory.  Rosenbaum,  for  example,  in  a  study  of 
stimulus  generalization  used  either  a  buzzer,  a  weak  shock,  or  a 
strong  shock  as  a  "punishing"  stimulus  for  slow  reactions.  On  the 
acute  hypothesis,  anxious  subjects  should  differ  from  nonanxious 
subjects  when  a  strong  shock  is  used  but  not  when  a  nonnoxious 
buzzer  is  used,  provided  the  situation  is,  in  other  respects,  devoid 
of  threat.  Rosenbaum  found,  in  accord  with  this  view,  that  the 
differences  between  high-  and  low-anxious  subjects  were  not  sig- 
nificant save  under  the  strong-shock  condition.  Apparently  the 
weak  shock  was  so  mild — it  was  described  to  the  subjects  as  a 
"slight"  skin  stimulation — that  it  was  no  more  stressful  than  the 
buzzer.  Further  support  for  the  acute  theory  comes  from  a  study 


258  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

of  eyelid  conditioning  by  Spence,  Farber,  and  Taylor  (1954).  Anx- 
ious subjects,  who  were  conditioned  by  these  investigators  under 
neutral  conditions,  showed  only  a  slight  (nonsignificant)  supe- 
riority in  response  frequency  when  compared  with  nonanxious 
subjects.  But  when  occasional  shocks  or  threats  of  shocks  were  in- 
troduced between  trials,  the  anxious  individuals  performed  at  a 
significantly  higher  level  than  those  with  low  MAS  scores.  Finally, 
the  experimental  findings  of  Bindra,  Paterson,  and  Strzelecki 
(1955)  may  also  be  interpreted  as  indirectly  supporting  the  acute 
hypothesis.  In  their  study,  involving  classical  salivary  conditioning, 
which  is  presumably  nonstressful,  the  performance  of  the  high- 
and  low-anxious  subjects  did  not  differ.  The  chronic  theory  would 
predict,  of  course,  that  even  in  a  nonemotional  situation  such  as 
this,  the  high-anxious  subjects  should,  because  of  their  higher 
level  of  drive,  perform  more  effectively,  unless  strong  competing 
(task-irrelevant)  responses  are  dominant. 

Studies  such  as  those  of  Wenar  (1954)  and  of  Spence  and 
Farber  (1953)  can  be  interpreted  as  supporting  either  the  acute 
or  the  chronic  view.  In  the  first  of  these  investigations,  which  was 
concerned  with  the  relation  of  anxiety  to  temporal  generalization, 
the  experimenter  measured  the  reaction  times  of  his  subjects  to 
a  buzzer,  a  weak  shock,  and  a  strong  shock.  He  failed  to  find, 
however,  any  increase  in  the  difference  between  the  mean  reaction 
times  of  anxious  and  nonanxious  subjects  as  a  function  of  the  in- 
tensity of  the  stimulus  to  which  they  were  reacting.  The  finding 
that  the  groups  differed  even  when  reacting  to  the  supposedly 
neutral  buzzer  fits  the  chronic  theory,  and  if  the  buzzer  and  the 
two  shocks  are  assumed  to  be  equally  stressful,  the  data  could  be 
made  to  conform  to  the  acute  theory.  The  findings  of  Spence  and 
Farber  (1953)  compare  with  those  of  Wenar  and  require  some- 
what similar  interpretations.  These  experimenters  did  not  find  the 
difference  between  the  conditioning  scores  of  anxious  and  non- 
anxious subjects  to  be  a  function  of  an  increase  in  the  intensity 
of  airpuff  used  as  the  unconditioned  stimulus.  Again,  one  might 
try  to  support  the  acute  theory  by  declaring  that  all  puffs  were 
equally  noxious,  though  this  seems  unlikely.  But  the  fact  that 
even  with  the  weakest  puff  the  high-anxious  subjects  conditioned 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  259 

more  readily  than  those  with  low  MAS  scores  is  coordinate  with 
the  chronic-anxiety  theory. 

Anxiety  and  Complex  Learning  Situations.  Nearly  all  of  the 
MAS  experiments  we  have  discussed  can  be  regarded  as  ones  in 
which  few  competitive  tendencies  to  make  task-irrelevant  re- 
sponses were  present.  In  the  eyelid-conditioning  situation  there  is 
doubtless  some  tendency  for  a  subject  to  inhibit  his  blinking  reac- 
tions to  the  CS,  and  some  writers  (Hilgard  and  Marquis,  1940) 
have  maintained  that  conditioned  responses  always  develop  in 
the  face  of  an  inhibitory  set.  Nevertheless,  through  the  use  of  ap- 
propriate instructions  and  by  having  the  subject  make  a  voluntary 
blink  to  a  ready  signal,  the  typical  tendency  to  hold  the  eye  open 
can  be  largely  eliminated.  When  this  has  been  done,  it  seems  rea- 
sonable to  regard  the  situation  as  one  in  which  the  indicator  re- 
sponse is  essentially  the  dominant  member  of  the  hierarchy.  In 
these  cases,  the  theoretical  expectation  is  that  high-anxious  sub- 
jects should  perform  better  than  low-anxious  subjects.  But  when 
the  task  is  such  as  to  permit  or  support  the  appearance  of  strong 
interfering  responses,  the  theory  becomes  more  complex  and  the 
predictions  change.  It  is  to  a  consideration  of  these  situations  and 
the  theory  appropriate  to  them  that  we  now  turn.  Our  treatment 
of  these  matters  rests  in  considerable  degree  upon  that  presented 
by  Spence  (1956)  in  his  Silliman  lectures. 

In  a  stimulus-response  theory  of  the  Hull-Spence  variety,  overt 
performance  on  any  task  is  a  consequence  of  complex  interactions 
and  competitions  among  task-relevant  (correct)  and  task-irrelevant 
(incorrect)  response  tendencies.  Other  factors  equal,  the  stronger 
the  drive,  the  stronger  all  excitatory  tendencies  become,  but  also, 
as  a  result  of  the  multiplicative  assumption,  the  greater  the  dispari- 
ties among  the  absolute  strengths  of  all  members  of  the  hierarchy. 
If  tendencies  dominant  under  low  drive  are  relevant  to  successful 
performance  of  the  assigned  task,  an  increase  in  drive  should  lead 
to  improved  performance.  But  when  the  dominant  tendencies  are 
those  regarded  as  incorrect  by  the  experimenter,  an  increase  in 
drive  will  lead  to  the  relative  strengthening  of  these  incorrect  tend- 
encies, and  performance  should  become  worse.  This  theory,  as  we 
have  seen,  enables  one  to  maintain  that  drive  always  functions  as 


260  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

an  energizer,  while  providing  an  adequate  explanation  for  the 
observation  that  high  drive,  on  occasion,  leads  to  poorer  rather 
than  to  better  overt  performance. 

In  the  earliest  experiments  designed  to  study  the  relation  of 
anxiety  level  to  performance  in  complex  situations,  both  verbal 
(serial  learning)  and  motor  tasks  (finger  maze)  were  used.  From 
analyses  of  these  tasks,  it  was  predicted  that  high-drive  (anxious) 
subjects  should  perform  more  poorly  than  low-drive  subjects.  This 
expectation  was  based  on  the  known  fact  that,  because  of  the 
serial  nature  of  these  tasks,  rather  strong  perseverative  and  antici- 
patory tendencies  are  often  present.  Such  tendencies — an  intrusion 
error  in  serial  verbal  learning  is  a  good  example — are,  by  definition, 
task-irrelevant,  and  their  presence  should  always  tend  to  degrade 
performance.  Furthermore,  the  disruptive  effect  of  these  conflicting 
tendencies  should  be  greater  for  the  high-drive  than  for  the  low- 
drive  subjects. 

Within  limits,  these  predictions  have  been  borne  out.  Thus, 
Taylor  and  Spence  (1952),  using  a  special  type  of  serial-verbal 
maze,  and  Farber  and  Spence  (1953)  with  a  finger  maze,  have 
found  that  low-drive  subjects  tend  to  be  the  better  performers.  In 
the  second  of  these  studies,  however,  it  was  noted  that  some  of  the 
choice  points  elicited  very  few  errors,  and  it  seems  reasonable, 
therefore,  to  regard  them  as  choices  where  the  correct  tendency 
was  dominant.  At  such  points  the  high-anxious  subjects  should  have 
performed  better  than  low-anxious  ones,  but  they  did  not.  Nega- 
tive results  have  also  been  reported  by  Hughes,  Sprague,  and  Ben- 
dig  (1954),  who  failed  to  obtain  significant  differences  between 
the  performance  levels  of  extreme  MAS  groups  who  were  tested 
with  several  serial-verbal  mazes. 

At  this  point  appears  the  perennial  problem  of  whether  the 
obtained  effects  of  anxiety  differences  could  be  due  in  part  to 
factors  other  than  differences  in  drive.  Obviously  they  could, 
and  those  who  have  worked  with  the  MAS  have  been  quite  aware 
that  individuals  lying  at  the  extremes  of  the  scale  may  differ  not 
only  with  respect  to  drive  intensity  but  also  with  respect  to  a 
variety  of  other  traits  or  characteristics.  One  of  the  several  pos- 
sibilities that  has  been  pointed  out  (Spence,  1956)  is  that  people 
who  score  at  the  high  end  of  the  MAS  may  be  those  who  would 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   HUMAN   PERFORMANCE  261 

also  rank  high  on  a  scale  of  "degree  of  susceptibility  to  distrac- 
tion." Should  this  be  the  case,  then  anxious  subjects  may  do  more 
poorly  on  serial  learning  tasks  because  they  are  paying  attention 
to  stimuli  that  are  irrelevant  to  successful  task  performance  and 
not  because  their  drive  level  is  high.  This  is  clearly  an  associative 
interpretation  of  performance  differences,  since  it  appeals  to  stable 
individual  differences  in  habits  of  "distractibility."  Child  and 
Waterhouse  (1953)  have  similarly  sought  to  explain  certain  in- 
stances of  so-called  motivated  behavior  by  reference  simply  to 
number  and  strength  of  task-interfering  tendencies. 

In  order  to  be  able  to  control  and  to  manipulate  the  relative 
associative  strengths  of  task-relevant  and  task-irrelevant  tendencies, 
Spence,  in  his  more  recent  studies  (1956),  has  turned  to  the  paired- 
associates  method  of  verbal  learning.  This  task  requires  the  subject 
to  form  associations  between  the  component  members  of  each  of 
several  pairs  of  words.  Upon  seeing  the  first  member  of  each  pair, 
the  subject  must  speak  the  second  word  (usually  within  about  two 
seconds)  before  it  is  presented.  On  successive  runs  through  the 
list  of  paired  words,  the  order  of  the  pairs  is  changed  to  minimize 
the  likelihood  that  associations  from  one  pair  to  another  will  be 
formed  within  the  list.  Of  special  importance  is  the  fact  that  rather 
wide  variations  in  the  strengths  of  the  correct  and  incorrect  tend- 
encies can  be  experimentally  produced.  For  instance,  the  strength 
of  the  association  between  the  stimulus  and  response  elements  of 
each  pair  can  be  increased  by  picking  out  response  words  having 
a  high  probability  of  being  given  as  associations  to  the  stimulus 
words.  Presumably,  the  stronger  the  tendency  for  the  stimulus 
item  to  call  out  its  particular  response  word  prior  to  training  in  the 
laboratory,  the  less  the  likelihood  that  incorrect  responses  will  be 
dominant.  Competitive  responses  can  also  be  minimized  by  mak- 
ing certain  that  the  stimulus  members  of  the  different  pairs  are 
neither  synonymous  nor  formally  similar. 

Spence  (1956)  has  performed  a  number  of  experiments  designed 
to  explore  the  consequences  of  varying  the  strength  of  competitive 
tendencies  in  a  paired-associates  task.  Figure  7:5  shows  the  results 
of  one  of  these  investigations  in  which  competition  between  pairs 
of  words  was  minimized  while  the  strength  of  the  tendency  for 
each  stimulus  word  to  elicit  its  paired  response  word  was  maxi- 


262 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


100 


90 


80 


70 


60 


■50 


40 


High  anxiety 
iV=20 

'  p ^  Low  anxiety 

/  JV=20 


6       7 

Trials 


10     11 


Fig.  7:5.  Performance  of  high-  and  low-anxious  subjects  on  a  verbal  learning 
task.  The  paired-associate  items  being  learned  were  selected  to  minimize  com- 
petition between  separate  pairs  of  words  and  to  maximize  the  tendency  for 
each  stimulus  word  to  elicit  its  paired  response  word.  {From  Spence,  J  956.) 

mized.  As  predicted  from  the  theory,  the  high-anxious  subjects 
learned  to  perform  this  task  significantly  better  than  did  low- 
anxious  subjects.  Presumably  this  is  because  the  lists  were  success- 
fully structured  to  minimize  the  appearance  of  incorrect  compet- 
ing reactions,  even  though  the  task,  taken  as  a  whole,  was  relatively 
complex. 

Several  additional  studies  have  been  reported  by  Spence,  in 
which  increases  in  the  strength  of  interfering  tendencies  were 
deliberately  produced  by  using  response  words  that  were  unlikely 
to  be  elicited  by  their  paired  stimulus  words  and  by  using  stimulus 
words  that  were  synonyms  for  one  another.  With  this  type  of 
paired-associates  list,  the  low-anxious  subjects  tended  to  perform 
better  on  the  strong-interference  pairs  than  did  the  highly  anxious 
subjects.  In  this  respect  the  results  of  three  different  experiments 
were  consistent,  but  in  none  was  the  effect  statistically  significant. 

In  concluding  this  section,  we  find  it  interesting  to  note  that 
Castaneda,  McCandless,  and  Palermo  (1956)  have  developed  a 
modified  form  of  the  MAS  for  use  with  fourth-,  fifth-,  and  sixth- 
grade  children.  Moreover,  these  investigators  have  shown  that  the 
performance  of  anxious  children  on  difficult  tasks  is  significantly 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  263 

worse  than  that  of  nonanxious  children  (Palermo,  Castaneda,  and 
McCandless,  1956),  that  anxiety  level  is  negatively  correlated  with 
intelligence  test  scores,  at  least  for  girls  (McCandless  and  Cas- 
taneda, 1956),  and  that  when  task  difficulty  is  varied  there  is  a 
significant  interaction  between  anxiety  and  task  difficulty,  anxious 
subjects  doing  relatively  superior  work  on  easy  items  and  inferior 
work  on  difficult  ones  (Castaneda,  Palermo,  and  McCandless, 
1956).  Thus,  the  empirical  relationships  found  for  anxious  and 
nonanxious  adults  tend  to  be  confirmed  with  children. 


Summary 

The  present  chapter  deals  with  theoretical  and  experimental 
aspects  of  the  problem  of  how  motivational  variables  affect  the 
performance  of  human  subjects  in  a  variety  of  situations.  The  ef- 
fects on  performance  of  drive,  defined  in  terms  of  severity  of 
deprivation,  in  terms  of  exteroceptive  stimulation  and  verbal  in- 
structions, and  in  terms  of  responses  to  standardized  tests,  are 
considered  in  turn.  To  reduce  the  enormous  literature  in  this  area 
to  more  manageable  proportions,  experiments  dealing  with  the 
effects  of  motivational  variables  upon  perceptual  behavior  have 
been  treated  separately  in  the  following  chapter. 

Investigations  in  which  attempts  have  been  made  to  vary  hu- 
man motivation  by  manipulating  severity  of  food  deprivation  are 
relatively  scarce,  and  the  results  are  far  from  consistent.  Accord- 
ing to  generalized  drive  theory,  hunger  should  enhance  all  reactive 
tendencies,  thereby  leading  to  better  performance  when  correct 
habits  are  strongest  and  to  poorer  performance  when  incorrect 
tendencies  are  dominant.  Experiments  designed  to  evaluate  these 
expectations  have  seldom  been  conducted,  however,  and  most  in- 
vestigators have  proceeded  on  the  assumption  that  hunger  or  other 
needs  should  augment  only  those  responses  that  are  related  to  the 
need.  When  subjects  are  maintained  on  a  semistarvation  schedule 
for  prolonged  periods  it  is  found  that  much  of  their  waking  time  is 
indeed  devoted  to  thoughts  and  daydreams  about  food  and  eat- 
ing. But  efforts  to  obtain  more  objective  evidence  for  this  phe- 
nomenon through  the  administration  of  standardized  psychological 
tests  have  generally  been  unsuccessful.  Similarly,  attempts  to  show 


264  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

that  relatively  short  periods  of  complete  deprivation  will  enhance 
the  frequency  of  food-related  responses  to  TAT-like  pictures,  to 
word-completion  test  items,  and  to  free-association  stimulus  words 
have  failed  to  provide  consistent  or  conclusive  support  for  the 
hypotheses  under  investigation. 

The  administration  of  electric  shock  to  human  subjects  either 
before,  during,  or  after  the  elicitation  of  certain  responses  produces 
significant  effects,  which,  in  certain  instances,  are  like  those  to  be 
expected  of  motivational  variables.  Specifically,  reactions  that  are 
consistently  followed  by  shock  reduction  tend  to  be  learned,  and 
those  followed  by  shock  induction  tend  to  be  abandoned.  More- 
over, randomly  administered  shocks  sometimes  appear  to  produce 
an  enhanced  emotional  or  motivational  level  that  is  generally 
facilitative  of  performance.  Under  a  variety  of  conditions,  however, 
these  generalizations  do  not  hold.  Not  only  does  shock  tend  to 
elicit  responses  that  interfere  with  the  successful  performance  of 
some  tasks,  but  it  may  also  serve,  particularly  with  human  sub- 
jects, as  a  source  of  specific  knowledge  concerning  the  correctness 
or  incorrectness  of  various  responses.  Although  the  motivational 
consequences  of  other  strong  stimuli  have  not  been  extensively 
studied  with  human  subjects,  we  may  note  that  the  intense  noises 
associated  with  industrial  or  military  operations  do  not,  for  the 
most  part,  appear  to  function  as  motivational  variables. 

Attempts  to  manipulate  human  motivation  by  the  use  of  "ego- 
involving"  or  "success"  and  "failure"  instructions  have  produced 
diverse  results.  Where  these  instructions  are  relatively  nonspecific 
and  are  accompanied  by  improved  performance,  the  arousal  of  a 
general  drive  may  be  indicated.  In  other  instances,  however,  in- 
structions seem  to  function  associatively,  either  because  they  con- 
tain problem-solving  hints  or  because  they  have  a  capacity  to  evoke 
facilitating  habits  or  attitudes.  But  few  studies  of  this  type  have 
been  designed  so  that  a  choice  might  be  made  between  motiva- 
tional and  associative  interpretations. 

The  procedure  of  defining  degree  of  motivation  in  terms  of  re. 
sponses  to  standardized  tests  has  been  widely  used  with  human 
subjects,  although  the  method  has  been  criticized  on  the  ground 
that  it  is  not  truly  experimental  and  that  it  is  especially  likely  to 
involve  the  confounding  effects  of  other  variables.  Upon  careful 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  HUMAN  PERFORMANCE  265 

analysis,  however,  these  objections  appear  to  be  unsupportable.  In 
principle,  adequately  rigorous  operational  definitions  of  drive 
can  be  based  upon  either  manipulative  or  selective  methods. 

The  assumption  that  human  motive  strength  can  be  usefully 
defined  by  analyzing  the  content  of  subjects'  imaginative  stories 
underlies  the  extensive  work  of  McClelland  and  his  associates.  For 
the  members  of  this  group  all  motives  are  learned,  and  all  are 
affectively  toned  expectations  of  the  coming  of  pleasant  or  un- 
pleasant consequences.  As  determinants  of  behavior,  motives  ap- 
parently always  function  as  facilitators,  although  the  effect  is 
limited  to  responses  that  are  in  some  way  relevant  to  the  motive. 
Moreover,  the  mechanisms  involved  in  the  facilitative  action  of 
motives  are  simply  those  of  associative  learning  theory,  and  no 
explicit  appeal  is  made  to  a  concept  of  drive  or  motivation  as  such. 
The  theory  is  thus  seen  to  be  associative  rather  than  motivational, 
though  the  intricacies  of  the  associative  interactions  have  not  been 
presented  in  detail. 

Another  large  group  of  investigations,  in  which  drive  level  has 
been  defined  by  test-situation  behavior,  consists  of  the  work  of 
Taylor  and  Spence  and  their  collaborators.  These  investigators 
have  proceeded  on  the  assumption  that  subjects  with  different 
drive  strengths  can  be  selected  on  the  basis  of  their  responses  to 
a  scale  of  manifest  anxiety,  and  that  the  behavior  of  such  subjects 
in  diverse  test  situations  should  be  deducible  from  the  basic  rela- 
tions of  Hull's  multiplicative-drive  theory.  Although  failures  to 
confirm  these  expectations  have  been  noted,  the  theory  is  well 
supported  by  a  substantial  body  of  positive  experimental  findings. 
Generally  speaking,  both  adults  and  children  who  are  defined  as 
having  high  drive  perform  more  efficiently  than  do  low-drive 
subjects  on  tasks  involving  few  competing  responses.  But  where 
strong  interfering  tendencies  are  present  low-drive  subjects  tend 
to  be  superior,  precisely  as  predicted.  The  underlying  theory  may 
be  characterized  as  primarily  motivational,  since  appeal  is  made  to 
a  concept  of  nonspecific  drive,  but  associative  principles  also  play 
an  important  supplementary  role. 


CHAPTER 

iiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiy^ 


8 


Motivational  Variables 
and  Perception 

It  has  long  been  known  that  sensory  and  perceptual  experiences 
are  largely  determined  by  the  properties  of  the  stimulus  energies 
impinging  upon  sensory  receptors.  And  every  student  of  psy- 
chology has  some  acquaintance  with  the  specific  stimulus-response 
relations  or  psychophysical  laws  that  have  been  painstakingly  deter- 
mined by  psychologists  and  physiologists.  Less  firmly  established, 
however,  and  of  more  recent  vintage,  is  the  view  that  the  reactions 
of  subjects  in  perceptual  experiments  depend  not  only  upon  stim- 
ulus variables  but  also  upon  the  personality,  attitudes,  associative 
predispositions,  and  level  of  motivation  of  each  and  every  subject. 
In  this  chapter  our  attention  is  focused  upon  the  last  of  these  rela- 
tions, that  between  motivational  variables  and  behavior  in  situa- 
tions described  as  perceptual. 

The  Problem  of  Perception  in  the  Study  of  Behavior 

When  pressed  for  an  exact  account  of  the  nature  of  perception, 
psychologists  rather  generally  tend  to  favor  either  of  two  somewhat 

266 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  267 

disparate  views.  The  first  of  these  views  is  that  perception  can  be 
construed  most  adequately  as  the  private  experience  of  the  per- 
ceiver.  To  understand  what  perception  is  Hke,  it  is  only  necessary 
that  one  engage  in  perceiving  for  himself.  Perception,  according  to 
this  phenomenological  position,  thus  turns  out  to  be  whatever  the 
individual  perceiver  perceives  perception  to  be.  Those  who  favor 
this  interpretation  appear  to  be  enchanted  by  the  wonders  of  per- 
ception and  regard  the  solution  of  its  mysteries  as  the  key  to  the 
understanding  of  all  psychological  problems.  On  this  view,  all  the 
phenomena  of  learning,  motivation,  personality,  adjustment,  and 
social  behavior  can  be  reduced  to,  or  best  understood  as,  examples 
of  the  operation  of  perception. 

The  second,  less  sanguine  view  of  perception  begins  by  rejecting 
the  notion  that  perception  can  ever  make  scientific  sense  so  long 
as  its  essential  nature  lies  hidden  within  the  private  experiential 
world  of  the  perceiver.  Perceiving  in  someone  else  is  not  an  activity 
that  is  visible  to  the  naked  eye  of  the  scientist.  If  one  is  to  use  the 
word  "perceiving"  at  all,  therefore,  with  reference  to  organisms 
other  than  one's  self,  the  term  must  be  introduced  by  means  of  a 
formal  definition,  the  elements  of  which  are  ultimately  reducible 
to  directly  indicatable  things.  One  can  observe  the  behavior  but 
not  the  experiences  of  one's  subjects;  hence  any  assertion  about 
the  perceptions  of  these  subjects  must  be  based  ultimately  upon 
how  they  behave.  According  to  this  second  point  of  view,  percep- 
tion must  have  the  status  of  a  scientific  inference  or  construct,  and 
like  so  many  other  constructs  (e.g.,  motivation,  habit  strength,  and 
cognition),  perception  is  real  only  to  the  degree  that  its  presence 
as  a  component  of  our  explanatory  accounts  of  behavior  serves  to 
enrich  our  understanding  of  that  behavior.  Moreover,  if  percep- 
tion is  to  function  as  an  element  in  a  systematic  account  of  be- 
havior it  must  be  defined  independently  of  the  behavior  it  is  pre- 
sumed to  be  affecting,  and  it  must  have  behavior-determining 
properties,  or  relations  to  antecedents  and  other  constructs,  that 
are  different  from  those  ascribed  to  other  postulated  entities  or 
processes.  If  not,  then  perception,  which  is  inherently  no  less  ex- 
pendable than  any  other  scientific  term,  need  not  be  invoked  as  a 
component  of  any  behavior  system. 

Is  a  Concept  of  Perception  Ever  Needed?  Those  who  hold  to 


268  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

the  second  of  the  above  views  tend  also  toward  the  opinion  that 
many,  if  not  all,  of  the  investigations  commonly  described  as  per- 
ceptual can  be  carried  to  successful  completion  without  appealing 
to  a  concept  of  perception.  This  is  especially  true,  it  would  seem, 
of  studies  in  which  subjects  respond  immediately  and  overtly  to 
the  presentation  of  stimulus  objects  of  one  kind  or  another.  Sup- 
pose, for  instance,  that  subjects  are  asked  to  identify  simple  geo- 
metrical forms.  If  certain  responses  are  elicited  by  particular  forms 
in  a  regular  manner,  then  empirical  relations  can  be  established 
between  physically  definable  stimulus  objects,  on  the  one  hand, 
and  frequencies  and/or  kinds  of  responses,  on  the  other.  Subse- 
quently, almost  unlimited  experimentation  can  be  conducted  to 
determine  the  conditions  under  which  these  relations  do  or  do  not 
hold.  One  can  vary  the  size,  color,  shape,  intensity,  texture,  and 
distance  of  the  figures,  or  note  whether  the  responses  are  affected 
by  training,  by  the  use  of  inverting  lenses,  by  the  level  of  dark 
adaptation,  and  so  on.  The  goal  of  such  research  is  to  determine 
the  range  of  conditions  across  which  the  stimulus-response  func- 
tion remains  invariant;  or,  alternatively,  to  outline  the  boundary 
conditions  that  must  be  fulfilled  if  the  stimulus-response  law  is  to 
hold  true.  This  can  be  done  quite  successfully  without,  at  any 
time,  referring  to  or  invoking  a  concept  of  perception.  Innumer- 
able studies  could  be  cited  to  support  the  contention  that  a  con- 
struct of  perception  is  not  essential  either  to  the  formulation  of 
many  stimulus-response  laws  or  to  the  determination  of  the 
interactive  effects  upon  them  of  motivational,  associative,  and 
other  variables.  Moreover,  highly  detailed  and  satisfactory  physi- 
ological interpretations  of  the  manifold  organic  events  interven- 
ing between  stimulus  and  response  can  be  developed  without  in- 
cluding perception  as  a  link  in  the  explanatory  chain. 

The  preceding  arguments  suggest  that  the  concept  of  perception 
may  be  superfluous  in  many  situations,  but  the  possibility  remains 
that  the  concept  might  play  a  useful  explanatory  role  in  some 
situations.  One  such  situation  is  that  in  which  a  stimulus  is  pre- 
sented but  no  overt  response  appears  until  some  time  after  the 
stimulus  has  been  removed.  In  attempting  to  interpret  this  be- 
havior one  might  assume  that  during  the  initial  stimulus-exposure 
period,  a  covert  perceptual  response  or  process  was  aroused.  And 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  269 

this  internal,  perseverating  sequel  to  stimulation  might  then  be 
treated  as  the  immediately  effective  determinant  of  the  subse- 
quently evoked  overt  response.  This  view  has  the  virtue  of  permit- 
ting us  to  incorporate  into  an  objective  theory  of  behavior  any 
instance  in  which  a  subject  says  that  he  perceived  something  (in 
the  past)  even  though  at  the  time  the  stimulus  was  presented 
he  made  no  overt  reaction  whatever. 

Defining  Perception.  If  perception  is  to  serve  as  a  conceptual 
bridge  in  such  delayed-response  experiments  and  in  others,  it  must 
be  operationally  defined,  the  definition  being  structured  so  as  to 
contain  no  reference  to  the  particular  behavior  that  is  alleged  to 
be  determined  by  perception.  In  defining  intervening  variables 
such  as  drive,  one  can  formulate  acceptably  independent  defini- 
tions in  several  ways,  and  the  same  variety  of  definition  is  ap- 
parently acceptable  for  the  concept  of  perception.  To  take  a 
single  example,  a  subject  might  be  defined  as  "perceiving"  in  one 
situation  on  the  basis  of  his  behavior  under  other  conditions.  To 
make  this  clear,  let  us  suppose  that  we  have  determined  for  a  given 
subject  an  empirical  relation  between  the  verbal  response  "triangle" 
and  a  physical  stimulus  having  a  triangular  form.  If  this  subject 
is  now  presented  with  a  triangle,  but  for  one  reason  or  another 
makes  no  overt  verbal  response,  we  can  still  assert  that  he  perceived 
the  triangle,  by  definition.  These  relations  are  shown  in  schematic 
form  in  Fig.  8:1.  The  St Rr  linkage  at  the  top  of  this  dia- 
gram is  the  empirical  law  relating  the  triangular  stimulus  {St)  to 
the  overt  verbal  response  (Rf)  •  This  law  is  then  used  as  the  basis  for 
the  assertion  that  a  covert  perceptual  response  (rp)  is  evoked  in  the 
stimulus-presentation  situation  where  no  overt  reaction  occurs.  If, 
as  is  shown  in  the  bottom  line  of  the  diagram,  the  verbal  response 
is  evoked  subsequently  when  the  subject  is  instructed  to  recall, 
even  though  St  is  not  present,  then  this  response  may  be  attributed 
to  the  perceptual  reaction.  The  occurrence  of  Rf  is  in  no  way  es- 
sential to  the  structure  of  the  definition  of  Tp,  however,  and  it  can 
be  asserted,  therefore,  that  the  subject  has  perceived,  irrespective 
of  whether  Rf,  some  other  response,  or  even  no  response  at  all  is 
elicited  during  the  recall  phase.  Thus  this  definition  of  tp  is  seen 
to  be,  as  it  must  be,  entirely  independent  of  whatever  behavior  one 
might  choose  to  attribute  to  Tp. 


270  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Empirical  law Sj, j >~Ry 


Definitional  chain 


I 

t 
Stimulus  present,       Sj. ►-  rp 

no  overt  response 


Recall  situation- 
overt  response,  Tp >-R^ 

stimulus  absent 

Fig.  8:1.  This  diagram  summarizes  the  several  steps  and  relations  that  would 
be  involved  in  one  kind  of  definition  of  perception.  First  of  all,  an  empirical 
law  relating  the  presentation  of  the  triangle  (St)  to  the  occurrence  of  an 
overt,  identifying  verbal  response  {Rv)  must  have  been  firmly  established.  This 
law  then  provides  the  grounds  for  the  statement  that  the  perceptual  response 
(rp)  has  been  evoked,  by  definition,  when  the  triangle  is  presented  but  the 
overt  response  is  absent.  Finally,  it  may  prove  useful  to  invoke  Vp  in  interpret- 
ing instances  in  which  Rv  appears  in  the  absence  of  the  triangle. 

Inasmuch  as  perception  can  be  defined  in  a  variety  of  different 
ways,  the  results  obtained  with  one  definition  may  differ  sub- 
stantially from  those  obtained  with  another.  For  instance,  if  a 
child  is  presented  with  a  number  of  circles  and  is  told  to  draw 
what  he  sees,  he  may  draw  a  number  of  ovals.  If  these  responses 
are  then  used  to  define  the  child's  perceptions,  it  is  necessary  to 
conclude  that  circles  are  perceived  as  ovals.  And  this  conclusion 
must  stand  until  some  other  definition  of  the  child's  ability  to 
perceive  can  be  formulated,  which  can  be  shown  to  have  more 
scientific  utility  and  significance  than  the  first.  For  example,  if  the 
child  shows  under  other  conditions  that  he  is  capable  of  sorting 
circles  into  one  pile  and  ovals  into  another,  we  may  find  it  profita- 
ble to  redefine  his  perceptions  accordingly.  By  one  of  these 
criteria  the  subject  perceives  circles  as  ovals,  but  by  the  other  he 
does  not.  When  two  definitions  of  perception  fail  to  coincide  in 
this  manner,  however,  neither  is  "right"  and  the  other  "wrong." 
A  correctly  formulated  definition  is  "wrong"  only  in  the  sense  that 
in  the  interpretation  of  a  broad  range  of  behavior  it  may  be  less 
useful  than  some  other  definition.  The  well-known  psychophysical 
methods,  with  their  emphasis  on  the  precise  control  and  measure- 
ment of  stimuli,  on  repeated  observations,  and  on  the  use  of 
statistically  grounded  inferences,  provide  us  with  our  most  trust- 
worthy methods  of  deciding  what  is  perceived  and  when. 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  271 

Motivational  Variables  and  Perception.  Any  experiment  in 
which  subjects  are  asked  to  identify,  detect,  or  compare  physically 
present  stimuli  would  qualify,  according  to  many  writers,  as  being 
concerned  in  some  way  with  perception.  Inasmuch  as  the  subjects 
in  such  experiments  are  responding  overtly,  it  seems  reasonable  to 
expect  that  the  introduction  of  motivational  variables  might  pro- 
duce changes  in  the  frequency,  latency,  and/or  correctness  of  the 
subjects'  responses.  The  responses  involved  are  the  customary  ones 
of  labeling,  naming,  and  discriminating,  by  saying  "same,"  "dif- 
ferent," "larger  than,"  and  the  like.  Consequently,  if  one  chooses  y 
to  define  perception  in  terms  of  these  responses,  one  must  conclude 
that  perception  has  been  modified  by  a  motivational  variable  when- 
ever that  variable  is  accompanied  by  changes  in  such  responses. 

Although  experiments  such  as  the  above  are  often  labeled  "per- 
ceptual," they  possess  no  unique  attributes  or  characteristics  by 
means  of  which  they  can  be  unambiguously  distinguished  from 
the  so-called  "discrimination"  or  "choice"  experiments.  Moreover, 
if  perception  is  regarded  as  a  covert  response  or  process  (e.g.,  r^  in 
Fig.  8:1)  intervening  between  the  external  stimulus  (S)  and  an 
overt  response   (R),  and  if  a  motivational  variable  is  operating 

throughout  the  entire  S R  sequence,  then  any  effect  of  that 

variable  upon  R  may  be  attributable  either  to  a  change  in  the  rela- 
tion of  S  to  Tp,  or  to  a  modification  of  the  relation  of  rp  to  R. 
Apparently,  most  studies  of  the  effects  of  motivation  on  percep- 
tion have  been  designed  so  that  the  motivational  variable  is  present 
both  while  the  stimuli  are  being  presented  and  while  the  response 
is  being  evoked.  None  of  these  studies  can  be  said,  therefore,  to 
have  answered  the  question  of  whether  perception,  as  well  as  overt  ^ 
behavior,  can  be  modified  by  motivation. 

In  principle,  however,  an  experiment  designed  to  provide  this 
information  appears  to  be  feasible.  For  example,  one  might  present 
identical,  impoverished  stimuli  to  two  groups  of  subjects,  one 
operating  under  high  drive,  the  other  under  low.  Overt  responses 
would  be  prevented  by  instructions  during  this  initial  stimulus- 
presentation  phase.  Then  at  a  later  time  the  drive  level  of  both 
groups  would  be  equated,  and  they  would  be  given  some  kind  of 
recall  or  recognition  test.  If  drive  affects  perception,  the  perform- 
ance of  the  two  groups  should  differ  during  the  second  test  phase. 


272  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

and  such  performance  differences  could  not  be  ascribed  to  the 
effects  of  drive  upon  the  relation  of  r^  to  R.  Effects  of  this  latter 
variety  could  be  detected,  however,  by  equating  drive  during  the 
stimulus-exposure  phase  and  varying  it  during  recall. 

From  these  considerations  the  conclusion  is  reached  that 
irrespective  of  how  the  motivation-perception  problem  is  formu- 
lated, perception  cannot  be  said  to  have  been  affected  by  motiva- 
tion unless  behavior  is  affected.  To  study  the  role  of  motivational 
variables  in  perception  is  to  study  the  changes  wrought  by  these 
variables  in  the  frequencies  or  kinds  of  responses  exhibited  by  sub- 
jects in  so-called  perceptual  experiments.  Whether  these  changes 
in  response  are  to  be  ascribed  to  modified  perceptions  or  to  changes 
in  response  systems  other  than  perception  hinges  on  the  design 
and  interpretation  of  one's  experiments. 

Multiplicative-drive  Theory  and  Perceptual  Behavior.  Hull,  in 
theorizing  about  behavior  in  classical  and  instrumental  condition- 
ing situations,  did  not  include  the  construct  of  perception  in  his 
group  of  intervening  variables.  But  the  responses  evoked  in  per- 
ceptual experiments  are  clearly  items  of  behavior,  and  it  is  ap- 
propriate, therefore,  to  inquire  as  to  how  such  responses  might  be 
affected  by  changes  in  Hull's  drive  (D). 
^  ^  Let  us  consider,  by  way  of  example,  a  psychophysical  (percep- 

tual) experiment  in  which  a  subject's  absolute  threshold  for  visual 
stimuli  is  determined  by  the  method  of  constant  stimuli.  With 
this  method,  a  number  of  discrete  stimuli,  whose  intensities  range 
above  and  below  threshold,  are  presented  singly  to  a  subject. 
Usually  he  is  instructed  to  say  "yes"  if  he  sees  the  stimulus  and 
"no"  if  he  does  not.  The  experimenter  tabulates  the  frequencies 
of  "yes"  and  "no"  responses  corresponding  to  each  of  the  stimuli 
and  after  converting  these  frequencies  into  percentages  plots  them 
against  the  stimulus  values  to  obtain  the  usual  psychophysical 
function.  The  solid-line  curve  of  Fig.  8:2  is  a  fictitious  example  of 
such  a  function.  As  this  curve  shows,  the  hypothetical  subjects 
seldom  perceive  (say  "yes"  to)  the  faintest  stimulus  and  almost 
always  say  "yes"  when  the  brightest  stimulus  is  presented.  By  con- 
vention, the  absolute  threshold  is  defined  as  the  value  of  stimulus 
intensity  that  elicits  "yes"  responses  50  per  cent  of  the  time.  In 
this  graph,  the  threshold  lies  at  stimulus  4  since  the  solid  curve 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   PERCEPTION 


273 


100 


75  - 


- 

Motivating--. 

instructions  ^^^ 

/ 

/      / 
/         / 
/        / 

'C         Usual 
^instructions 



A  A 
/A 

/              Lncw 



y 

1 

ttireshold 
ginal  threshold 

1             1             1 

50 


<!-  25 


12  3  4  5  6  7 

Stimulus  intensity 

Fig.  8:2.  The  solid-line  curve  is  a  fictitious  example  of  the  kind  of  psycho- 
physical function  commonly  obtained  when  the  method  of  constant  stimuli 
is  used  to  determine  an  absolute  threshold.  The  dashed-line  curve,  with  its 
corresponding  threshold,  is  the  predicted  outcome  of  the  assumption  that  in- 
structions alleged  to  be  motivating  actually  serve  to  affect  the  associative 
strengths  of  the  "yes"  response  to  all  stimulus  intensities  while  leaving  dri\e 
level  unaltered. 


intersects  the  horizontal  50  per  cent  response  hne  directly  above 
4.  Responses  of  saying  "no"  are  not  plotted  in  the  figure,  but  these 
would  decrease  from  a  maximum  at  the  left  to  a  minimum  at  the 
right  and  would  form  a  mirror  image  of  the  "yes"-response  curve. 
To  apply  Hull's  multiplicative-drive  theory  to  observations  such 
as  these  we  must  first  obtain  some  estimate  of  the  relative  habit 
strengths  of  the  responses  being  recorded.  On  the  simplifying  as- 
sumption that  drive  does  not  vary  with  stimulus  intensity,  it 
follows  that  the  habit  strength  of  the  "yes"  response  must  var}' 
directly  with  the  frequency  with  which  that  response  appears.  The 
habit  strength  to  say  "yes"  must  be  greatest,  therefore,  for  stimulus 
7  and  weakest  for  stimulus  1.  This  fundamental  assumption  of  a 
direct  relation  between  empirical  response  percentages  and  habit 
strength  is  indicated  by  the  "habit-strength"  legend  on  the  right- 
hand  ordinate.  It  is  not  necessary,  for  purposes  of  this  analysis, 
to  specify  the  mechanisms  by  which  these  habits  have  been  devel- 
oped. It  must  be  presumed,  however,  that  these  associative  tend- 
encies have  been  acquired  prior  to  the  experiment  and  are  trans- 


274  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

ferred  to  specific  laboratory  stimuli  by  means  of  verbal  instructions 
to  the  subjects. 

Having  made  this  assumption,  we  next  turn  to  the  question  of 

how  this  psychophysical  function  would  be  affected  by  the  ma- 

.nipulation  of  a  motivational  variable.  Within  the  theory  two 

/  distinct  answers  can  be  given,  depending  on  whether  the  variable 

\    leads  primarily  to  a  change  in  habit  strength  or  to  a  change  in 

^  drive.  In  this  discussion  we  shall  not  consider  instances  in  which 

motivational  variables  might  affect  both  associative  strength  and 

drive. 

To  illustrate  the  first  of  these  possibilities,  suppose  an  attempt 
is  made  to  raise  drive  level  by  telling  subjects  to  "try  hard"  and 
to  "pay  very  close  attentio^n"  to  the  stimuli  and  to  the  assigned 
task.  Instead  of  affecting  drive,  such  instructions  may  function 
simply  to  elicit  specific  receptor-adjustive  acts  (cf.  Spence,  l9S\a; 
Wycoff,  1952)  such  as  blinking  less  often,  moving  the  head  less, 
and  fixating  the  center  of  the  exposure  field  more  consistently. 
Or  they  may  evoke  tendencies  to  repress  thoughts  of  impending 
social  activities,  classroom  examinations,  and  so  forth.  If  such 
responses  are  elicited  by  the  alleged  motivating  instructions,  the 
subjects  should  indeed  show  improved  performance  in  detecting 
faint  stimuli.  In  this  instance  better  performance  would  be  indi- 
cated by  an  increase  in  the  frequency  of /"yes"  responses  and  a 
corresponding  decrease  in  "no"  reactions. (And  since,^by  assump- 
_tion,  response  frequency  reflects  habit  strength,  it  must  be  con- 
cluded that  the  instruction-induced  adjustive  acts  have  led  to  an 
effective  increase  in  the  habit  strength  of  the  -l^yes"  response  for 
all  stimuli  save  those  of  maximum  initial  strength  ./The  observable 
result  of  such  an  over-all  increase  in  habit  strength  would  be  a 
leftward  shift  of  the  psychophysical  function  and  a  corresponding 
drop  in  the  threshold.  This  is  shown  in  Fig.  8:2  by  means  of  the 
dashed-line  curve. 

Several  studies  designed  to  test  these  expectations  have  been 
conducted  in  the  psychological  laboratories  of  the  State  University 
of  Iowa.  The  results  of  two  of  these  are  shown  in  Fig.  8:3.  The 
data  plotted  in  the  upper  panel  were  obtained  by  Bechtoldt  and 
McDonough  (1958)  in  a  situation  in  which  the  subjects  were 
asked  to  report  whether  a  faint  gray  spot  could  be  seen  when 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  275 


100 


75 


50 


25 


Motivated  group 

iV=15 


Relaxed  group 

N  =  13 


-10 


8-6-4-2         0         2         4         6         8 
Exposure  duration  in  ms.  above  and  below  threshold 


10 


lUU 

^-0- ■" 

75 

" 

(/> 

Motivated  attitude  - 

\      '             / 

U1 

X^             / 

c 

'              / 

o 

Q. 

/                        .^ 

10 

/    ^^ 

w  50 

- 

tt) 
>> 

/^                                            1 

4) 

/  , 

A^ 

/  / 

^^Relaxed  attitude 

25 

- 

JV=20 

y 

tf 

_y^ 

n 

1 

1        1        1        1 

-10     -8-6-4-2         0  2         4         6         8 

Exposure  duration  in  ms.  above  and  below  threshold 


10 


Fig.  8:3.  The  data  plotted  in  the  upper  panel  were  obtained  by  Bechtoldt  and 
McDonough  (1958)  and  those  in  the  lower  panel  by  Ludvigson  (1958).  In 
both  instances,  attempts  to  increase  the  subjects'  level  of  motivation  by  verbal 
instructions  shifted  the  psychophysical  functions  toward  the  left  and  lowered 
the  absolute  thresholds.  These  empirical  curves  may  be  compared  with  the 
theoretically  predicted  results  shown  in  Fig.  8:2. 


276  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

presented  at  very  brief  exposures  in  a  tachistoscope.  The  right- 
hand  curve  was  obtained  from  subjects  who  were  told  to  relax 
and  take  it  easy,  and  the  left-hand  curve  from  subjects  who  were 
told  to  do  their  very  best.  Comparable  results  from  an  investiga- 
tion by  Ludvigson  (1958)  are  shown  in  the  lower  panel.  In  his 
experiment  a  single  group  of  subjects  performed  a  tachistoscopic 
identification  task  under  instructions  designed  to  be  motivating 
at  one  time  and  nonmotivating  at  another.  The  results  of  both 
of  these  studies  are  consistent  with  the  hypothesis  that  "pay-atten- 
tion" instructions  can  alter  behavior  in  a  perceptual  experiment  by 
affecting  associative  tendencies.  When  instructions  produce  these 
effects  they  should  not,  in  all  strictness,  be  described  as  "motivat- 
ing," and  interpretations  of  their  influence  on  behavior  should  be 
carefully  identified  as  associative,  since  they  contain  no  reference 
to  a  motivational  concept.  Incidentally,  there  is  little  reason  to 
suppose  that  instructions  to  try  harder  will  always  lead  to  better 
performance.  Such  instructions  might  actually  arouse  interfering 
tendencies  and  thereby  produce  a  decrease  in  efficiency. 

The  second  answer  to  the  question  of  how  an  alleged  motiva- 
tional variable  might  affect  behavior  in  a  psychophysical  experi- 
ment involves  the  assumption  that  the  variable  produces  a  change 
in  drive  strength  alone.  Referring  to  the  hypothetical  data  plotted 
as  the  solid  line  in  Fig.  8:4,  it  is  apparent  that  the  empirical 
frequencies  of  "yes"  and  of  "no"  responses  are  exactly  equal  for 
the  threshold  stimulus,  and  that  therefore  the  associative  strengths 
must  also  be  equal  at  that  point.  Under  these  conditions  an  in- 
crease in  drive  should  not  produce  any  change  in  the  relative  fre- 
^  quencies  of  the  "yes"  and  "no"  responses,  since  the  corresponding 
excitatory  potentials  will  remain  equal.  Consequently,  the  threshold 
in  a  psychophysical  experiment  of  this  kind  should  not  be  affected 
if  the  motivational  variable  leads  only  to  a  change  in  drive. 

When  the  "yes"  and  "no"  habit  strengths  are  not  equal,  how- 
ever, an  increase  in  drive,  on  the  multiplicative  assumption,  will 
magnify  the  absolute  difference  between  the  two  excitatory  tend- 
encies and  thereby  increase  the  frequency  with  which  the  domi- 
nant reaction  is  evoked.  This  condition  of  habit-strength  inequality 
is  met  for  all  stimuli  save  4.  At  stimuli  5,  6,  and  7  the  "yes- 
response"  habit  is  stronger  than  the  "no-response"  habit,  and  an 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   PERCEPTION 


277 


100 


Jfi  75 


50  - 


Q-  25 


:3J^ 

- 

High  drive ---:v/     X 

/  / 
// 
1/ 

Low  drives 

/  /    ' 
//      1 

^     /  f 
X/   / 

//           1 

^^                1      /Threshold 

1             2 

3            4             5 
Stimulus  intensity 

6 

7 

Fig.  8:4.  If  a  motivational  variable  leads  solely  to  an  increase  in  drive,  with- 
out affecting  associative  strengths,  then  the  accompanying  theoretical  analysis 
suggests  that  the  psychophysical  function  relating  percentage  of  "yes"  re- 
sponses to  stimulus  intensity  should  become  steeper.  This  is  indicated  here  by 
the  dashed-line  curve.  The  absolute  threshold,  however,  should  not  be  affected 
by  changes  in  drive  alone. 


increase  in  drive  should  enhance  the  frequency  of  "yes"  responses 
at  those  points.  By  the  same  reasoning,  intensified  drive  should 
reduce  the  frequency  of  "yes"  responses  to  stimuli  1,  2,  and  3, 
since  the  dominant  tendency  at  these  points  is  to  say  "no."  These 
predicted  effects,  which  are  shown  in  Fig.  8:4  by  means  of  the 
dashed  line  curve  labeled  "high  drive,"  should  be  negligible,  of 
course,  at  stimuli  1  and  7  because  of  "floor"  and  "ceiling"  effects, 
respectively.  On  the  multiplicative-drive  theory  then,  intensified 
drive  should  increase  the  steepness  of  the  slope  of  the  psychophys- 
ical function  throughout  the  middle  portions  of  the  stimulus  range, 
but  the  absolute  threshold,  if  defined  in  the  conventional  manner, 
should  not  change.  Since  an  increase  in  slope  means  a  decrease  in 
res,ponse  variability,  this  indicates,  in  one  sense,  an  increase  in  "per- 
ceptual sensitivity."  This  prediction  may  be  less  intuitively  reason- 
able than  our  first,  and  the  writer  knows  of  no  experimental  data 
that  clearly  support  it,  but  it  does  fit  with  the  commonly  held  view 
that  lackadaisical  (unmotivated?)  subjects  yield  flatter  psycho- 
physical functions  than  those  who  attend  strictly  to  business. 
Under  the  conditions  specified  in  the  foregoing  example,  an 


1^ 


278  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

increase  in  drive  per  se  should  not  reduce  the  absolute  threshold. 
But  in  the  typical  experiment  on  motivation  and  perception,  the 
threshold  is  not  defined  as  the  point  where  the  stimulus  is  per- 
ceived 50  per  cent  of  the  time,  but  as  the  point  at  which  it  is 
perceived  two  or  three  times  correctly  in  succession.  This  is  equiva- 
lent to  defining  the  threshold  as  lying  somewhere  above  the  50 
per  cent  level,  e.g.,  at  75  per  cent.  Referring  to  Fig.  8:4,  we  can  see 
that  the  intersection  of  the  high-drive  curve  with  the  horizontal 
line  at  the  75  per  cent  level  falls  to  the  left  of  the  intersection  of 
the  low-drive  curve  with  the  same  line.  If  the  threshold  were  thus 
defined  as  lying  above  50  per  cent,  then  increased  drive  should 
lead  to  a  lower  threshold. 

The  foregoing  interpretations  have  dealt  only  with  the  effects 
of  motivational  variables  upon  absolute  thresholds,  but  similar 
principles  can  be  applied  to  experiments  in  which  the  method  of 
constant  stimuli  is  used  to  determine  difference  limens.  In  such 
experiments,  each  of  several  comparison  stimuli  is  repeatedly  paired 
with  a  standard,  the  subject  being  asked  to  judge  whether  the 
comparison  stimuli  are  "greater"  or  "less"  than  the  standard  with 
respect  to  some  property  such  as  loudness,  length,  brightness,  or 
weight.  The  introduction  of  a  motivational  variable  into  an  experi- 
ment of  this  kind  ^ould  be  expected  to  produce  an  over-all  dis- 
_placement  of  the  psychophysical  function,  provided  the  variable 
leads  to  a  general  change  in  the  strength  of  the  associative  tendency 
to  say  "larger  than"  (or  "smaller  than").  The  practical  outcome 
of  such  a  displacement  would  be  a  shift  in  the  point  of  subjective 
equality  and  the  appearance  of  a  constant  error.  (In  a  subsequent 
section  of  this  chapter  it  is  noted  that  the  "value"  of  a  stimulus 
object  might  affect  a  psychophysical  function  in  this  manner.)  The 
slope  of  the  function  should  not  be  altered,  however,  by  habit- 
strength  modifications  alone,  save  in  the  unlikely  event  that  asso- 
ciative tendencies  corresponding  to  stimuli  that  are  greater  and 
less  than  the  standard  are  affected  in  opposite  directions. 

If  the  motivational  variable  enhances  drive,  leaving  associative 

jp -- strengths  unchanged,  then  an  increase  in  slope  is  the  only  pre- 

^^^^^^^^      dieted  outcome.  Initially,  associative  tendencies  to  say  "greater 

than"  should  be  stronger  than  tendencies  to  say  "less  than"  for 

stimuli  greater  than  the  standard,  and  the  reverse  should  be  true 


^ 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   PERCEPTION  279 

for  stimuli  less  than  the  standard.  An  increase  in  driye.  should 
function,  therefore,  on  the  multiphcative  assumption,  to  increase 
the  excitatory  potentials  of  correct  responses  relative  to  incorrect 
ones,  thereby  reducing  the  size  of  the  difference  limens  and  im- 
proving accuracy  of  discrimination.  Conversely,  decreased  drive 
should  result  in  less  accurate  discriminations.  However,  the  point  , 
of  subjective  equality,  where  "greater  than"  and  "less  than"  re-  v, 
spouses  are  equally  frequent  and  their  associative  strengths  are 
presumably  equal,  should  not  be  affected  by  modifications  in  drive 
strength. 

Tlie  results  of  several  studies  conducted  at  the  State  Universit} 
of  Iowa  are  consistent  in  showing  that  the  psychophysical  function 
tends  to  become  steeper  under  high  drive  when  the  method  of 
constant  stimuH  is  used  to  determine  difference  limens.  The  data 
from  two  of  these  experiments,  by  Clark  (1958)  and  by  Tandler 
(1958),  are  shown  in  Fig.  8:5.  The  same  task,  that  of  judging 
whether  each  of  a  number  of  comparison  circles  was  larger  or 
smaller  than  a  standard,  was  used  in  both  studies.  And  in  both 
experiments  drive  level  was  supposedly  lowered  by  pretending  that 
the  subjects'  responses  were  not  being  recorded  on  certain  trials 
and  that  these  trials  served  only  as  rest-period  activity.  It  is  clear 
from  these  experiments  that  under  the  alleged  high-drive  condition 
the  frequency  of  larger-than  responses  for  stimuli  larger  than  the 
standard  was  increased  and  the  frequency  of  larger-than  responses 
for  stimuli  smaller  than  the  standard  was  diminished.  However, 
the  issue  of  whether  the  observed  effects  are  due  to  changes  in 
drive  per  se  or  to  modified  habit  strengths  is  not  settled  by  these 
results. 

Throughout  the  foregoing  theoretical  development,  it  was  as- 
sumed that  the  stimuli  were  relatively  simple  events  such  as  faint 
lights  or  tones.  In  most  experiments  relating  perception  to  motiva- 
tion, however,  words,  nonsense  syllables,  or  complex  forms  are 
used  instead  of  lights  or  tones,  and  the  subjects  are  required  to 
name  or  identify  the  stimuli.  When  such  stimuli  are  presented 
clearly  and  for  relatively  long  periods  of  time,  the  correct  responses, 
with  rare  exceptions,  are  evoked  100  per  cent  of  the  time.  Hence 
if  one  is  to  study  the  effects  of  motivational  or  other  variables  on 
perception,  the  stimuli  must  be  presented  unclearly  or  in  some 


280 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


-5    - 


-3-2-1        0        1        2        3 
Difference  between  variable  and 
standard  stimulus,  mm 


100 

- 

Normal  drive 

^•f 

75 

/ 

50 

1 

Jl 

iV=32 

yy 

25 

Reduced         /  / 
drive  ^     /  / 

J  / 

J  / 

^^  / 

--r^^ 

U 

1     1     1     1     1 

1         1         1 

B.  F.  Tandler 

-5-4-3-2-1        0        1        2        3       4        5 

Difference  between  variable  and 

standard  stimulus,  mm 

Fig.  8:5.  This  figure  presents  the  results  of  two  independent  but  identical  ex- 
periments (Clark,  1958;  Tandler,  1958)  on  the  role  of  motivation  in  visual 
judgments  of  area.  The  method  of  constant  stimuli  was  employed  to 
determine  difference  limens,  some  observations  being  made  under  "normal" 
conditions  and  others  (reduced  drive)  when  the  subjects  were  led  to  believe 
that  their  responses  were  not  being  recorded. 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  281 

impoverished  form  so  that  identification  is  not  always  perfect. 
Impoverishment  can  be  effected  by  blurring  the  outlines  of  visual 
forms,  by  shortening  exposure  times,  by  reducing  stimulus  in- 
tensity, or  by  various  combinations  of  these  methods. 

To  extend  the  multiplicative-drive  theory  to  responses  elicited 
by  such  impoverished  stimuli,  it  is  necessary  first  to  consider  the 
effect  of  impoverishment  upon  the  habit  strength  of  the  identifying 
response.  One  possible  assumption  is  that  impoverishment  pro- 
duces no  change  other  than  a  decline  in  habit  strength.  If  so,  then 
increased  drive  should  magnify  the  values  of  the  excitatory  poten- 
tials for  all  impoverished  forms  of  the  stimulus,  and  performance 
in  identifying  the  stimulus  should  improve.  Moreover,  this  con- 
clusion should  hold  for  any  stimulus  to  which  a  naming  response 
has  been  strongly  associated,  irrespective  of  whether  the  stimulus 
is  or  is  not  related  to  the  drive-producing  conditions. 

Alternatively,  impoverishment  might  lead  not  only  to  a  decline 
in  the  strength  of  the  habit  for  the  correct  response,  but  also  to  a 
rise  in  the  strength  of  other  competitive  habits.  For  instance,  if 
the  printed  word  house  were  made  fainter  and  fainter,  the  middle 
letter  might  disappear  sooner  than  the  rest.  Hence,  for  the  im- 
poverished stimulus,  the  strength  of  the  habit  to  say  "hose"  might 
become  stronger  than  that  to  say  "house."  Should  impoverish- 
ment have  this  effect,  accuracy  of  identification  should  decline 
under  high  drive,  since  the  associative  tendencies  to  utter  the 
wrong  words  would  be  stronger  than  those  to  speak  the  correct 
words.  The  effect  of  drive  upon  the  absolute  threshold  for  simple 
physical  stimuli  (see  Fig.  8:4)  may  also  be  regarded  as  an  instance 
of  habit-strength  reversal  of  this  kind,  the  habit  strength  for  a 
response  of  "no"  being  presumed  to  exceed  the  "yes"  response 
habit  for  all  subthreshold  stimulus  values. 

These  expectations  from  the  multiplicative-drive  theory  may  or 
may  not  prove  accurate  when  subjected  to  experimental  test.  For 
our  present  purposes,  however,  this  is  of  minor  importance.  Of 
more  significance  is  the  fact  that  these  limited  predictions  illustrate 
the  application  of  a  motivational  theory  to  behavior  which,  if  one 
chooses,  may  be  described  as  "perceptual."  While  these  guesses 
have  been  made  without  reference  to  a  concept  of  perception,  it  is 
entirely  possible  that  performance  in  psychophysical  tasks  will 
ultimately  demand  such  reference. 


282  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Facilitative  effects  of  motivational  variables  upon  identifying  re- 
sponses to  impoverished  stimuli  can  be  interpreted  associatively  as 
well  as  motivationally  (cf.  Brown,  1953d).  Through  past  learning, 
need-related  responses  are  more  likely  than  others  to  have  become 
associated  with  stimulus  aggregates  composed  of  both  internal  and 
external  cues.  When  the  strong  supportive  function  of  unambigu- 
ous external  stimuli  is  weakened  through  impoverishment,  the 
relative  importance  of  internal  cues  will  be  enhanced,  and  if  the 
motivational  variable  alters  these  internal  stimuli,  selective  facili- 
tative effects  may  be  observed.  In  ever)'  instance,  therefore,  where 
motivational  variables  appear  to  have  modified  the  responses  that 
define  perception,  it  is  imperative  to  inquire  whether  the  effect 
was  indeed  motivational  or  whether  it  could  have  been  due  to 
existing  differences  among,  or  changes  in,  the  relative  strengths  of 
associative  tendencies. 

Primary  Sources  of  Drive  and  Perception 

The  studies  evaluated  in  this  section  are  necessarily  limited  to 
those  involving  hunger  and  thirst  as  primary  sources  of  drive  for 
the  reason  that  almost  no  other  primary  sources  of  motivation 
have  been  manipulated  in  studies  of  perception.  Electric  shock, 
which  also  seems  to  qualify  as  a  primary  source  of  drive,  has  often 
been  used  in  perceptual  experiments  but  in  a  manner  that  makes 
the  treatment  of  such  studies  more  appropriate  to  a  later  section 
on  perception  and  secondary  sources  of  motivation.  Specifically, 
electric  shocks  have  nearly  always  been  paired  with  visual  stimuli 
during  preperception  phases  of  experiments,  and  have  usually  not 
been  administered  while  perceptual  proficiency  is  being  measured. 

The  Effects  of  Deprivation  upon  Perceptual  Responses.  An  ex- 
periment by  McClelland  and  Atkinson  (1948)  provides  us  with 
an  example  of  investigations  of  the  effects  of  food  deprivation 
upon  behavior  in  a  perceptual  situation.  In  this  study  sub- 
jects who  had  gone  without  eating  for  periods  of  from  1  to  2, 
4  to  5,  and  16  to  18  hours  were  asked  to  report  what  they  saw  at 
various  times  on  a  dimly  illuminated  screen.  On  most  occasions 
no  pictures  of  any  kind  were  projected  on  the  screen,  but  the 
subjects  were  made  to  believe  that  extremely  faint  pictures  were 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   PERCEPTION  283 

indeed  being  shown.  This  behef  was  strengthened  by  the  initial 
showing  of  a  recognizable  object  and  by  occasional  hints  from  the 
experimenter  as  to  the  nature  of  the  "objects"  being  shown.  Under 
these  conditions,  subjects  who  had  been  without  food  for  16  to  18 
hours  gave  significantly  more  food-related  responses  than  did  those 
with  1  to  2  hours  of  deprivation,  the  number  of  responses  made  by 
the  4  to  5-hour  group  falling  in  between.  The  results  were  not 
entirely  consistent,  however,  since  in  some  cases,  in  answer  to 
questions  posed  by  the  experimenter,  increasingly  hungry  subjects 
gave  more  frequent  responses  related  to  instrumental  acts  of  secur- 
ing food,  but  did  not  give  more  frequent  responses  dealing  with 
food  items  as  such.  Moreover,  as  the  experimenter's  hints  contained 
increasingly  direct  references  to  food,  the  number  of  food  responses 
increased,  but  not  differentially  as  a  function  of  hunger.  And  when 
vaguely  defined  blots  were  projected  on  the  screen  instead  of 
blank  slides,  the  frequency  of  food-related  responses  diminished. 

According  to  some  critics,  the  McClelland-Atkinson  investiga- 
tion is  not  "perceptual,"  since  when  blank  slides  were  projected  on 
the  screen  there  was  "nothing  there"  save  a  dim  "blob"  of  light 
for  the  subjects  to  perceive.  Nevertheless,  the  subjects  were  told 
that  very  faint  pictures  would  be  projected  and  that  guesses  might 
often  have  to  be  made  as  to  the  nature  of  the  pictures.  Under 
these  conditions  the  subjects  did  report  seeing  things,  and,  with 
the  exceptions  noted  above,  the  more  severe  their  hunger  the 
more  numerous  their  food-related  responses.  Thus  an  empirical 
relationship  was  obtained  between  a  motivational  variable  and  re- 
sponses by  which  perception  could  be  defined.  The  question  of 
whether  it  would  be  scientifically  useful  to  define  perception  in 
terms  of  responses  occurring  in  the  absence  of  structured  external 
stimuli  can  be  answered  only  by  a  careful  evaluation  of  the  relative 
merits  of  this  and  of  alternative  definitions. 

Lazarus,  Yousem,  and  Arenberg  (1953)  have  reported  that  the 
recognition  of  tachistoscopically  presented  pictures  of  food  objects 
improves  with  hunger.  This  conclusion  was  based  on  data  obtained 
from  four  groups  of  subjects  whose  tachistoscopic  recognition 
thresholds  for  both  food  and  nonfood  objects  were  tested  under 
0  to  1,  2,  3  to  4,  and  5  to  6  hours  of  food  deprivation,  respectively. 
The  trend  of  the  data  for  the  first  three  groups  was  clearly  in  a 


284  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

direction  to  support  the  authors'  conclusions,  but  a  dechne  in 
performance  was  observed  in  the  case  of  the  hungriest  group. 
Because  of  this  reversal,  conclusions  from  this  study  as  to  the 
sensitizing  effect  of  hunger  on  perception  must  be  limited  to  short 
periods  of  deprivation.  Nevertheless,  the  tendency  for  recognition 
accuracy  to  improve  with  mild  degrees  of  hunger  was  observed 
in  two  independently  conducted  experiments,  and  somewhat  sim- 
ilar findings  have  been  reported  by  Levine,  Chein,  and  Murphy 
(1942).  According  to  Lazarus  et  al.  the  drop  in  perceptual  effi- 
ciency at  the  longer  deprivation  intervals  may  be  a  consequence 
of  a  conditioned  hunger  cycle,  a  possibility  previously  suggested 
by  Sanford  (1937). 

That  the  facilitative  effect  of  hunger  on  perception  is  relatively 
ephemeral  is  suggested  by  the  results  of  a  further  study  by  Lazarus 
et  al.  This  investigation  was  identical  with  the  first,  save  that  fewer 
subjects  were  run  in  each  group  and  all  observers  were  required, 
after  each  stimulus  presentation,  to  select  a  response  from  a  list 
containing  the  names  of  the  10  pictures  plus  six  additional  items. 
When  freedom  of  choice  was  restricted  in  this  way,  recognition 
of  food  objects  became  increasingly  worse,  though  not  significantly 
so,  as  the  period  of  deprivation  was  lengthened.  No  evidence  was 
found  in  either  study  to  indicate  that  hungry  subjects  make  more 
food-related,  prerecognition  responses  or  give  more  food  associa- 
tions to  the  stimulus  words  of  a  free-association  test  than  non- 
hungry  subjects.  Thus  the  findings  of  these  several  studies,  though 
suggestive  of  a  relation  between  hunger  and  tachistoscopic  recog- 
nition thresholds,  are  not,  because  of  reversals  of  direction  and 
interexperiment  inconsistencies,  entirely  convincing. 

Two  additional  experiments,  by  Wispe  and  Drambarean  and 
by  Taylor  have  yielded  contradictory  results.  Wispe  and  Dramba- 
rean (1953)  asked  subjects  who  had  been  without  food  and  water 
for  0,  10,  and  24  hours  to  identify  tachistoscopically  presented 
words.  Both  common  and  uncommon  words,  some  related  and 
some  unrelated  to  food  and  water  deprivation,  were  used.  Analyses 
of  recognition  thresholds  revealed  that  degree  of  "commonness" 
was  the  most  important  factor  determining  word  recognition. 
Among  both  the  common  and  uncommon  words,  however,  signifi- 
cant interactions  were  obtained  between  severity  of  deprivation 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  285 

and  need  relatedness  of  the  stimulus  words.  That  is,  recognition 
times  for  neutral  words  were  unaffected  by  deprivation,  whereas 
times  for  need-related  words  dropped  markedly  from  the  0-hour 
to  the  10-hour  condition,  thereafter  remaining  at  about  the  same 
level  for  the  24-hour  group.  The  authors  conclude  from  these  data 
that  need-related  words  are  recognized  more  easily  as  deprivation 
increases.  Although  the  subjects'  previous  experience  with  words 
would  account  for  their  ability  to  recognize  common  words  more, 
readily  than  uncommon  ones,  the  apparently  positive  effects  of 
deprivation  could  scarcely  be  ascribed  to  the  factor  of  familiarity 
since  the  differently  deprived  groups  were  presented  with  the  same 
words. 

Taylor  (1956b),  however,  in  an  experiment  similar  to  that  of 
Wispe  and  Drambarean  failed  to  confirm  their  findings.  In  her 
study  the  subjects'  set  to  expect  the  presentation  of  food  words 
was  manipulated  in  addition  to  their  degree  of  physiological  need. 
In  two  replications  of  the  experiment,  with  different  orders  of 
stimulus  presentation,  Taylor  observed  that  the  recognition  thresh- 
olds of  deprived  subjects  for  need-related  words  did  not  differ 
significantly  from  those  of  satiated  subjects.  Subjects  who  had  been 
set  to  expect  need-related  words,  however,  did  have  lower  thresholds 
than  control  subjects. 

A  series  of  experiments  by  Gilchrist  and  Nesberg  (1952)  pro- 
vides some  final  examples  of  studies  relating  need  to  perception. 
These  investigators  attempted  to  avoid  certain  of  the  methodolog- 
ical deficiencies  of  previous  experiments  by  studying  the  short-term 
perceptual  recall  of  both  need-related  and  neutral  objects.  Specif- 
ically, their  subjects  were  shown  colored  slides  of  food  objects  (or 
neutral  objects),  the  intensity  of  the  projector  lamp  being  set  at 
a  standard  level.  Subsequent  to  the  projection  of  each  slide,  the 
lamp  voltage  was  either  raised  or  lowered  and  subjects  were  asked 
to  readjust  the  voltage  until  the  projected  image  looked  the  same 
as  when  first  presented.  A  stable  result  from  an  integrated  series 
of  four  experiments  was  that  all  subjects  tended  to  make  positive 
time  errors.  That  is,  they  tended  to  make  the  projected  image 
brighter  than  the  standard  level.  The  positive  time  errors  for 
satiated  subjects  remained  constant,  whereas  those  for  deprived 
subjects  increased  progressively  with  hours  of  food  deprivation  up 


286 


THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 


to  a  limit  of  20  hours.  In  effect,  therefore,  performance  became 
progressively  worse  as  a  function  of  increasing  hunger.  In  one 
experiment  involving  pictures  of  fluids,  increasingly  severe  thirst 
(for  subjects  who  were  also  hungry)  was  accompanied  by  higher 
and  higher  voltage  settings,  whereas  for  satiated  subjects  no  such 
progressive  increase  in  positive  time  error  appeared.  Figure  8:6 
shows  the  lamp-voltage  settings  made  by  thirsty  and  satiated  sub- 
jects as  a  function  of  time  since  the  start  of  the  experiment. 

Of  special  interest  here  is  the  dashed-line  portion  of  the  curve 
for  the  thirsty  subjects.  As  the  label  indicates,  the  final  point  on 
the  curve  was  obtained  after  the  thirsty  subjects  had  been  per- 
mitted to  drink  as  much  ice  water,  orange  juice,  and/or  milk  as 
they  wished.  This  strikingly  precipitous  drop  was  highly  significant 
and  was  replicated  in  two  further  experiments.  In  these,  Gilchrist 
and  Nesberg  showed  that  the  increasingly  positive  time  error 
associated  with  increased  need  was  not  due  merely  to  the  visually 
patterned  nature  of  the  food  pictures  but  was  dependent  specifically 
on  their  need-related  characteristics.  From  these  studies  the  authors 
concluded  that  as  need  increased,  positive  time  errors  in  the 
illuminance  matches  of  objects  relevant  to  that  need  tended  to 
increase. 

Since  Gilchrist  and  Nesberg  offer  no  theoretical  interpretations 
of  their  rather  dramatic  findings,  it  is  of  interest  to  see  whether 


0  2  4  6 

Hours  from  start  of  experiment 


Fig.  8:6.  Average  lamp- 
voltage  settings  made  by 
thirsty  and  satiated  sub- 
jects in  adjusting  the 
brightness  of  a  projected 
image  of  thirst-related  ob- 
jects to  subjective  equality 
with  a  previously  seen 
image.  True  physical 
equality  would  have  been 
obtained  if  the  voltages 
had  been  set  at  80.  The 
drop  at  the  right-hand  side 
for  the  thirsty  group 
coincided  with  their  hav- 
ing drunk  fluids  ad  libi- 
tum. (From  Gilchrist  and 
Nesberg,  J 952.) 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   PERCEPTION  287 

the  type  of  explanation  proposed  earlier  in  this  chapter  can  be 
expanded  to  encompass  their  results.  We  note  first  of  all  that 
even  satiated  subjects  consistently  made  positive  constant  errors  in 
their  illuminance  matches.  This  means  that  if  two  equally  bright 
stimulus  objects  are  presented,  one  after  the  other,  the  second  is 
judged  dimmer  than  the  first.  Or  it  means  that  if  a  subject  is 
allowed  to  adjust  the  brightness  of  a  second  object  to  subjective 
equahty  with  a  first,  he  tends  to  set  the  second  brightness  level 
higher  than  that  of  the  first.  Thus  a  positive  time  error  implies 
that  the  tendency  to  make  adjustive  response  settings  above  the 
"true"  value  is  stronger  than  the  tendency  to  make  adjustive  reac- 
tions below  the  "true"  value.  Hence  the  two  corresponding  habit 
strengths  must  be  unequal.  But,  as  we  have  repeatedly  noted, 
when  habit  strengths  are  unequal,  increasing  drive  produces  an 
increasing  disparity  between  the  corresponding  excitatory  tenden- 
cies and  thereby  an  increase  in  the  predominance  of  one  overt 
response  over  another.  Thus  the  finding  that  positive  errors  increase 
in  magnitude  with  hunger  but  not  under  satiation  follows  as  a 
logical  consequence  of  the  multiplicative-drive  hypothesis.  On  this 
view,  drive  variations  should  have  no  effect  when  constant  errors 
are  absent.  This  theory  does  not,  of  course,  encompass  the  data  at 
the  0-hour  point  in  Fig.  8:6.  However,  the  surprisingly  low  voltage 
settings  made  at  that  point  by  the  subjects  who  were  later  to 
become  thirsty  may  well  have  been  due  to  sampling  fluctuations. 
At  the  start  of  the  experiment  both  groups  were  equal  with  respect 
to  level  of  deprivation,  and  hence  their  lamp-voltage  settings 
should  have  been  approximately  identical. 

This  interpretation,  though  applicable  to  the  difference  between 
deprived  and  satiated  subjects,  must  be  modified  to  fit  the  data 
obtained  by  Gilchrist  and  Nesberg  when  the  illuminance  levels 
of  need-related  and  non-need-related  pictures  were  matched  by 
the  same  subjects.  These  findings,  shown  in  Fig.  8:7,  would  prob- 
ably call  for  the  introduction  of  an  incentive  motivation  factor. 
Thus,  as  deprivation  becomes  more  severe,  the  need-related  items 
may  elicit  anticipatory  responses  of  enhanced  vigor,  and  greater 
and  greater  increments  might  be  added  to  drive.  This  should  lead, 
as  indicated  above,  to  an  increase  in  the  relative  strength  of  the 
dominant  response  and  hence  to  progressively  larger  constant 


288 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

85 


Hours  from  start  of  experiment 


Fig.  8:7.  Additional  data  from  the  Gilchrist-Nesberg  (1952)  experiment.  In 
this  phase  a  single  group  of  subjects  was  tested  with  both  need-related  and 
non-need-related  stimulus  objects.  Quite  clearly,  the  magnitude  of  the  positive 
error  increases  for  need-related  items  but  not  for  neutral  items  as  a  function  of 
hours  of  water  (and  food)  deprivation.  The  effect  seems  to  disappear  im- 
mediately, however,  when  the  subjects  are  permitted  to  drink. 


errors.  By  contrast,  non-need-related  items  should  not  produce 
incentive-generated  motivational  increments.  At  this  point,  how- 
ever, the  theory  seems  to  fall  short;  for  although  increasing  thirst 
should  have  progressively  magnified  the  constant  errors  even  for 
non-need-related  items,  it  did  not  do  so  (see  Fig.  8:7,  lower  curve) . 
Nevertheless,  the  terminal  drop  of  the  curve  for  non-need-related 
pictures,  like  that  for  need-related  stimuli,  is  consistent  with 
theoretical  expectations. 

We  conclude  this  section  with  the  following  summarizing  com- 
ments. Research  purporting  to  have  shown  a  relationship  between 
intensity  of  physiological  need  and  responses  in  perceptual  situa- 
tions has  yielded  suggestive  and  stimulating,  though  controversial 
and  inconsistent,  results.  In  some  instances,  deprivation  seems  to 
facilitate  the  identification  of  need-related  pictures  or  words  pre- 
sented at  near-threshold  levels.  Rather  often,  however,  inconsistent 
or  negative  results  have  followed  from  the  use  of  similar  methods. 
Indeed,  in  experiments  such  as  those  of  Gilchrist  and  Nesberg, 
increased  deprivation  has  been  shown  to  lead  to  poorer  rather  than 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   PERCEPTION  289 

better  "perceptual"  performance.  All  in  all,  therefore,  experi- 
mental findings  in  this  area,  as  well  as  theories  as  to  their  nature 
and  relationships  to  other  varieties  of  motivated  behavior,  must 
be  viewed  with  reservations. 


Secondary  Sources  of  Drive  and  Perception 

Up  to  this  point,  we  have  dealt  only  with  experiments  in  which 
deprivation  has  served  as  the  principal  motivational  variable,  and 
in  which  motivational  properties  of  the  to-be-perceived  stimuli, 
if  any,  have  tended  to  play  a  secondary  role.  By  far  the  largest 
group  of  experiments,  however,  consists  of  those  in  which  the 
stimuli  serve  both  as  to-be-perceived  cues  and  as  the  principal  de- 
terminants of  level  of  motivation.  In  nearly  all  of  these  cases  the 
presumed  capacity  of  the  cues  to  function  as  motivational  variables 
can  reasonably  be  attributed  to  processes  of  learning.  Such  studies 
can  legitimately  be  treated,  therefore,  as  instances  of  the  influence 
of  secondary  or  learned  sources  of  drive  on  perceptual  behavior. 

Motivation  and  Judgments  of  Magnitude.  Most  investigators 
whose  studies  fall  in  this  category  have  been  concerned  with  the 
problem  of  whether  visual  estimates  of  size  are  significantly  affected 
by  the  value  of  the  objects  being  judged.  Usually,  the  stimulus 
objects  have  been  coins,  subjects  being  asked  to  equate  coin  size 
to  that  of  a  neutral  disk,  whose  diameter  can  be  varied.  Unfor- 
tunately, many  of  the  early  experiments  were  characterized  by 
methodological,  experimental,  and  statistical  inelegancies,  and 
little  confidence  can  be  placed  in  the  results.  For  example,  in 
some  studies  an  illuminated  patch  of  light  served  as  the  variable 
stimulus,  the  diameter  of  which  was  adjusted  by  the  subject  to 
equal  that  of  a  relatively  dark  coin  seen  against  a  light  background. 
This  deviation  from  conventional  psychophysical  practice  was 
sometimes  further  magnified  by  permitting  subjects  to  hold  the 
coins  in  their  hands,  tactual  cues  thereby  being  added  to  one  stimu- 
lus complex  but  not  to  the  other.  Moreover,  adequate  controls 
were  seldom  included  for  the  effects  of  the  inscriptions  on  the 
coins  or  for  differences  among  them  in  color,  thickness,  and  weight. 
In  spite  of  these  defects,  or  perhaps  because  of  them,  the  results 
of  early  studies  (e.g.,  Bruner  and  Goodman,  1947)  were  so  strik- 


290  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

ing  that,  if  they  did  nothing  else,  they  aroused  widespread  interest 
and  stimulated  others  to  perform  parallel  experiments.  In  subse- 
quent investigations  the  introduction  of  methodological  refine- 
ments has,  in  some  instances,  reduced  or  obliterated  the  supposed 
enhancing  effect  of  value  on  size.  But  positive  results  have  also 
been  obtained  under  more  carefully  controlled  conditions  and  the 
phenomenon  may  well  be  genuine. 

Although  the  majority  of  experiments  have  been  directed  toward 
determining  the  effects  of  value  on  estimates  of  size,  it  has  also 
been  reported  that  judgments  of  weight,  numerosity,  and  bright- 
ness are  altered  by  so-called  motivational  factors.  The  motiva- 
tional state  is  most  commonly  assumed  to  be  aroused  by  the 
specific  stimuli  being  judged,  though  it  has  sometimes  been  varied 
by  the  selection  of  subjects  whose  socioeconomic  needs  are  pre- 
sumed to  differ. 

Value  as  a  Source  of  Drive.  One  of  the  major  conceptual  prob- 
lems attending  studies  of  the  perception  of  valued  objects  is  that 
of  specifying  the  mechanism  by  which  variations  in  value  might 
produce  changes  in  drive.  Inquiries  as  to  the  nature  of  value  raise 
many  complex  questions  that  have  intrigued  and  baffled  economists 
and  philosophers  for  generations.  For  the  student  of  behavior, 
however,  it  seems  apparent  that  value  cannot  meaningfully  be 
treated  as  a  property  of  physical  objects  as  such,  and  that  the  most 
useful  definition  would  be  structured  in  terms  of  an  object's  power 
to  elicit  preferential  approach  and  seizing  responses  from  organ- 
isms. This  would  imply,  incidentally,  that  value  is  always  relative. 
A  lump  of  sugar  has  more  positive  value  to  a  rat  than  a  block  of 
wood  if  and  only  if  the  rat  approaches  and  seizes  the  sugar  instead 
of  the  wood.  A  50-cent  coin  is  more  valuable  than  a  dime  only 
to  the  degree  that  individuals  prefer  the  former  to  the  latter. 
If  the  individuals  are  infants  rather  than  adults,  or  if  they  have 
not  been  raised  in  our  culture,  or  if  the  test  is  conducted  during 
a  period  of  severe  inflation,  neither  coin  may  have  more  value 
than  the  other,  and  neither  coin  may  have  more  value  than  a 
blank  disk  of  paper  or  metal.  To  say,  then,  that  a  coin  or  any 
other  object  has  value  is  to  assert  that  it  elicits  responses  of  certain 
kinds,  at  certain  times,  and  from  certain  individuals,  and  in  addi- 
tion, that  these  responses  are  different  from  those  elicited  by  other 


C 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   PERCEPTION  291 

coins  or  other  objects.  A  physical  object  is  valuable  only  to  the 
extent  that  organisms  approach  and  choose  it  in  preference  to 
other  objects. 

Defining  value  in  terms  of  behavior  helps  to  clarify  the  problem 
of  how  a  valuable  stimulus  object  might  produce  an  increase  in 
drive.  The  behavior  of  approaching  and  seizing  objects  such  as 
coins,  jewelry,  new  cars,  and  the  like,  which  is  characteristic  of 
adults  in  our  culture,  is  evidently  learned  as  a  consequence  of  the 
rewards  provided  by  society.  When  a  subject  in  an  experiment 
on  judgment  of  size  is  presented  with  both  a  coin  and  a  neutral 
disk,  the  coin  must,  if  it  is  to  be  defined  as  having  positive  value, 
elicit  stronger  tendencies  of  approaching  and  choosing  than  does 
the  neutral  disk.  And  since  the  coin  has  become  a  positive  goal 
object,  the  sight  of  it  may  well  elicit  learned  tendencies  to  make 
anticipatory  goal  reactions  (rgS),  which  in  turn  may  contribute 
increments  to  the  subject's  general  level  of  drive  (D).  When  the 
problem  is  structured  in  this  manner,  value  becomes  covariant 
with  strength  of  incentive  motivation,  a  topic  discussed  in  detail 
in  Chapter  5. 

In  brief,  when  the  value  of  a  stimulus  object  is  manipulated, 
simultaneous  (and  correlated)  changes  are  presumed  to  be  induced 
in  the  strengths  of  learned  tendencies  to  approach  and  possess 
the  object.  And  in  so  far  as  anticipatory  goal  reactions  occur, 
their  vigor,  and  hence  the  drive  increments  they  provide,  should 
also  increase  with  the  value  of  the  goal  object. 

A  parallel  interpretation  can  be  made  of  studies  in  which 
motivational  or  affective  levels  have  been  manipulated  by  the 
selection  of  groups  alleged  to  differ  in  personality  or  in  social 
position.  Thus,  if  judgments  of  coin  size  are  made  by  poor  and 
rich  children,  it  might  be  argued  that  the  groups  differ  with  respect 
to  the  strengths  of  their  habits  to  seek  and  secure  coins,  and  per- 
haps also,  therefore,  in  the  intensities  of  their  anticipatory  [drive- 
contributing)  responses.  However,  variations  in  drive  strength  alone 
should  not  affect  judgments  of  coin  size  if  the  associative  tendency 
to  say  "larger  than"  is  equal  in  strength  to  the  tendency  to  say 
"smaller  than"  when  a  coin  is  compared  to  a  neutral  disk  of 
identical  size.  Presumably,  therefore,  differences  in  the  strengths 
of  linguistic  habits  must  be  invoked  as  an  adjunct  to  the  preceding 


f 


292  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

interpretation.  This  matter  will  be  treated  in  more  detail  after  the 
consideration  of  additional  illustrative  investigations. 

Experimental  Studies  of  the  Judged  Size  of  Coins.  If  the  value 
of  an  object  determines  its  apparent  size  to  any  degree,  the  effect 
must  be  revealed  through  changes  in  the  nature  of  subjects'  re- 
jponses  concerning  the  size  of  that  object.  Phrased  in  this  way, 
the  problem  seems  relatively  straightforward,  but  the  design  of  an 
experiment  adequate  to  provide  unequivocal  results  is  far  from 
simple.  It  would  not  do,  for  example,  to  present  a  coin  to  a  subject 
and  ask  him  simply  to  estimate  its  size  in  inches  or  millimeters. 
Even  if  the  mean  of  his  judgments  differed  significantly  from  true 
physical  size,  one  would  have  no  way  of  knowing  whether  the 
discrepancy  was  due  to  value,  to  the  presence  of  a  picture  on  the 
coin,  to  the  subject's  lack  of  practice  in  making  such  estimates,  or 
to  any  of  a  number  of  other  factors.  In  principle,  there  is  only 
one  way  in  which  the  effects  of  value  on  judged  size  can  be 
unambiguously  assessed:  judgments  must  be  made  of  the  relative 
size  of  a  valued  object  when  it  is  compared  with  less  valued 
objects  having  essentially  identical  physical  properties.  By  this 
criterion,  an  ideal  experiment  on  size  as  a  function  of  monetary 
value,  would  be  one  in  which  subjects  are  required  to  say  whether 
genuine  coins  (or  bills)  looked  larger  or  smaller  than  counterfeit 
moneys.  Were  an  experiment  done  in  this  way,  all  sources  of 
variability  save  value  would  be  properly  controlled.  Conclusions 
based  on  the  use  of  control  objects  whose  physical  properties  or 
backgrounds  deviate  substantially  from  those  of  the  valued  objects 
cannot  be  regarded  as  definitive.  Moreover,  for  complete  confirma- 
tion of  the  value-size  hypothesis,  increases  in  value  would  have  to 
be  accompanied  by  progressively  greater  distortions  of  apparent 
size,  at  least  over  a  certain  range  of  sizes.  The  greater  an  object's 
value,  the  greater  should  be  the  distortion  of  its  apparent  size  when 
compared  with  suitable  control  objects.  Unfortunately,  nearly  all 
existing  studies  have  failed,  in  one  respect  or  another,  to  meet 
these  ideal  conditions,  and  we  must  content  ourselves  with  sug- 
gestive rather  than  conclusive  findings. 

Confining  our  attention  for  the  moment  to  studies  of  common 
coins,  we  find  scant  evidence  that  when  they  are  physically  present 
their  size  is  enhanced.  In  their  initial  investigation  Bruner  and 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION 


293 


Goodman  (1947)  reported  astonishingly  large  overestimations  of 
coin  sizes  when  compared  with  judgments  of  cardboard  disks.  But 
findings  of  subsequent  studies  in  which  the  controlling  base  line 
has  been  more  appropriately  provided  by  metal  disks  have,  in  the 
main,  been  negative. 

Carter  and  Schooler  (1949),  seeking  to  check  the  Bruner-Good- 
man  results,  asked  children  to  adjust  the  size  of  a  circular  patch 
of  light  to  correspond  to  the  sizes  of  various  coins,  metal  disks, 
and  cardboard  disks.  Their  results,  for  coins  and  aluminum  disks 
only,  are  presented  in  Fig.  8:8.  The  cardboard-disk  data  have  been 
omitted  on  the  ground  that  cardboard  disks  are  less  suitable  as 
control  objects  than  aluminum  disks.  As  these  curves  reveal,  the 
sizes  of  the  penny,  dime,  and  nickel  were  all  underestimated, 
though  not  significantly,  both  with  reference  to  true  size  and  to 
aluminum  disks.  Both  the  25-  and  50-cent  pieces  were  overesti- 
mated, the  latter  significantly  so.  Subsequently,  Bruner  and  Ro- 
drigues  (1953)  also  found  the  penny  and  nickel  to  be  judged 
smaller  than  worthless  metal  counterparts,  only  the  quarter  being 
estimated  as  larger  (nonsignificantly)  than  its  corresponding  metal 
disk.  Both  coins  and  metal  disks,  however,  were  judged  as  larger 


Monetary  value 


15 


3  10- 


E 
2    5 


5-5 


^-10 


10^    1^  5(^ 


25^ 


50^ 


18  20  22  24  26 

Diameter,  mm 


28         30 


Fig.  8:8.  Experimental  data  indicating  that  small  coins  tend  to  be  judged 
smaller  and  large  coins  larger  than  aluminum  disks  equal  in  size  to  the  various 
coins.  These  results  were  derived  from  tests  in  which  physically  present  coins 
and  disks  were  matched  to  a  circular  patch  of  light,  whose  diameter  could  be 
controlled  by  the  subjects.  {Adapted  from  Carter  and  Schooler,  J 949.) 


294  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

than  paper  disks.  The  rather  commonly  held  view  that  coins, 
when  physically  present,  tend  to  be  judged  larger  than  metal  disks 
of  comparable  size  is  thus  apparently  supported  by  the  data  for 
only  one  coin  (50-cent  piece)  from  a  single  experiment  (Carter- 
Schooler).  And  even  this  effect  may  be  due  less  to  value  per  se 
than  to  other  factors  such  as  the  design  on  the  coin. 

Whether  available  data  support  the  notion  that  degree  of  over- 
estimation  of  size  increases  with  value  is  also  questionable.  In  the 
Carter-Schooler  study,  the  effect  was  indeed  greater  for  the  more 
valuable  of  the  two  coins  that  were  overestimated.  But  in  the 
Bruner-Rodriguez  study,  since  only  the  quarter  was  overestimated 
( the  50-cent  piece  was  not  used )  relative  degree  of  overestimation 
cannot  be  determined.  These  latter  authors,  finding  little  evidence 
for  absolute  overestimation,  suggest  that  when  the  members  of  a 
stimulus  series  are  valuable,  the  differential  enhancement  between 
the  terminal  members  of  that  series  will  be  greater  than  between 
corresponding  members  of  a  neutral  series.  But  their  data,  cited  to 
support  this  contention,  do  not  show  differential  enhancement, 
if  this  is  taken  literally  to  mean  that  all  coins  are  enhanced  in 
some  degree,  higher  valued  ones  being  enhanced  more.  Rather, 
their  findings,  like  those  of  Carter  and  Schooler,  are  that  negative 
^-^  I  enhancement  (underestimation)  occurs  for  small  coins  and  posi- 
tive enhancement  for  larger  ones.  To  explain  this  by  the  value 
hypothesis  one  would  have  to  contend  that  coins  of  little  value 
have  even  less  value  than  metal  disks;  but  such  a  twist  would  im- 
pose a  severe  strain  on  the  value  hypothesis.  Apparently,  therefore, 
it  is  necessary  to  conclude  that  when  judgments  are  made  of  the 
size  of  physically  present  coins,  under  controlled  conditions,  their 
value  is  an  as-yet-unproved  determinant  of  their  apparent  size. 

Before  leaving  this  problem  of  judged  size  of  coins,  we  should 
note  that  the  socioeconomic  status  of  the  subject,  his  age,  and 
other  factors  may  influence  his  estimates.  Children  described  as 
"poor"  by  Bruner  and  Goodman  overestimated  physically  present 
coins  more  than  did  "rich"  children.  But  Carter  and  Schooler, 
who  used  larger  groups,  obtained  no  significant  differences  between 
the  judgments  of  rich  and  of  poor  children  under  coins-present 
conditions.  To  confound  the  issue  further,  Rosenthal  (1951)  re- 
ports the  size  estimations  of  rich  ten-year-olds  to  be  greater  than 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION 


295 


those  of  poor  subjects  for  every  coin,  but  the  reverse  to  hold  for 
six-year-olds.  In  many  studies,  judgments  have  also  been  made  of 
the  remembered  sizes  of  coins  by  both  rich  and  poor  subjects. 
These  memory  judgments  have  not  been  treated  here  since  they 
fall  outside  the  conventionally  defined  area  of  perception,  but  it 
appears  likely  that  value  has  a  more  marked  effect  upon  judgments 
of  remembered  size  than  upon  the  apparent  size  of  physically 
present  objects  (e.g..  Carter  and  Schooler,  1949). 

Other  Studies  of  Apparent  Magnitude  and  Value.  We  turn  now 
to  other  studies,  in  which,  for  the  most  part,  coins  were  not  used 
as  stimulus  objects  or  in  which  unusual  techniques  were  adopted. 
In  this  latter  respect  the  investigation  of  Ashley,  Harper,  and 
Runyon  (1951)  is  of  special  interest.  Seeking  to  control  attitudes 
towards  money,  these  investigators  told  hypnotized  subjects  to 
forget  their  previous  life  histories.  On  some  occasions  the  subjects 
were  told  they  really  had  lived  very  poverty-stricken  lives,  and  at 
other  times  that  they  had  been  reared  in  extremely  well-to-do 
homes.  All  subjects  were  also  tested  in  the  normal  waking  state. 
When  the  "poor"  state  was  induced,  subjects  tended  slightly  to 
overestimate  the  sizes  of  all  coins,  relative  to  true  size,  and  when 
the  subjects  were  "rich,"  they  tended  to  underestimate  all  sizes. 

The  results  of  this  experiment,  for  responses  made  with  coins 
present,  are  shown  in  Fig.  8:9.  The  differences  between  the  sub- 
jects' responses  when  "poor"  and  when  "rich"  were  statistically 
significant,  but  the  differences  between   "poor"  and  "normal," 


Fig.  8:9.  Judgments  of  the 
size  of  physically  present 
coins  made  by  subjects  un- 
der normal  conditions  and 
under  hypnotically  in- 
duced "rich"  and  "poor" 
attitudes.  {Adapted  from 
Ashley,  Harper,  and  Run- 
yon, 1951.) 


i.l 
1.0 

Poor^y/^^ 

Normal^/     / 

0.9 

A                      /\X    > 

/^\                /       /      / 

/      \             /      /      / 

0.8 

~  y  /K  \     /    /  ^ 

'  /  \  \  /    /    / 

/-^V^x/^ 

0.7 

\      / 

V 

0.6 

A  =  True  size 

n1 

r  ,     , 

5         10 

Value  of  coin,  cents 


25 


296  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

"poor"  and  "true"  size,  "rich"  and  "normal,"  and  "rich"  and 
"true"  size  were  not  evaluated  by  Ashley  et  al.  and  were  pre- 
sumably not  significant.  Indeed,  for  three  of  the  coins,  the  subjects, 
when  "poor,"  came  closer  to  the  true  sizes  than  when  "normal," 
and  the  size  exaggerations  produced  by  the  "poor"  instructions, 
though  they  occurred  for  every  coin,  were  of  doubtful  significance. 
Moreover,  the  tendency  of  the  subjects  (adults)  when  in  the 
"rich"  state  to  underestimate  all  sizes  is  consistent  with  neither 
Rosenthal's  data  from  ten-year-old  subjects  nor  with  the  results 
provided  by  Bruner  and  Goodman's  rich  subjects.  Very  possibly, 
as  Ashley  et  al.  have  noted,  their  findings  may  be  due  in  part  to 
the  fact  that  their  subjects  when  "poor"  were  very  attentive  and 
hence  more  accurate,  whereas  the  same  subjects  when  in  the 
"rich"  state  were  relatively  careless,  responded  quickly,  and  only 
"condescendingly  cooperated." 

A  final  phase  of  the  Ashley,  Harper,  and  Runyon  study  marks 
the  use  of  a  new  and  ingenious  procedure.  In  this  phase  the 
hypnotized  subjects,  under  both  "rich"  and  "poor"  instructions, 
were  required  to  match  the  diameters  of  a  variable  circle  of  light 
and  a  metal  slug.  At  diverse  times  the  slug  was  described  to  the 
subjects  as  either  lead,  silver,  white  gold,  or  platinum.  The  results 
of  this  test,  reproduced  in  Fig.  8:10,  show  that  estimated  size 
tended  to  increase  with  the  declared  value  of  the  metal  and  that 
"poor"  judgments  inclined  more  toward  overestimation  than  "rich" 
ones.  Because  the  same  slug  was  used  under  all  conditions,  one 
cannot  appeal  to  uncontrolled  external  stimulus  factors  to  explain 
the  results.  Unfortunately,  since  we  have  so  little  knowledge  of 
what  takes  place  during  hypnosis,  these  findings  cannot  readily 
be  generalized  to  "normal"  subjects.  Nevertheless,  tests  conducted 
under  hypnosis  may  reveal  the  operation  of  processes  whose  effects 
in  waking  subjects  are  usually  obscured  by  sets,  attitudes,  and  the 
like. 

Experimental  results  entirely  negative  with  respect  to  the  size- 
value  hypothesis  have  been  reported  by  Lysak  and  Gilchrist  ( 1955 ) . 
Using  paper  currency  rather  than  coins,  they  required  adult  subjects 
to  match  the  bills  against  control  rectangles  bearing  designs  of 
varying  complexity.  Estimates  of  size  were  found  to  be  unaffected 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION 


297 


Lead 


Silver  White  gold 

Alleged  metal  of  slug 


Platinum 


Fig.  8:10.  Subjects  under  hypnotically  induced  "rich"  and  "poor"  attitudinal 
states  made  judgments  of  the  size  of  a  gray  iron  slug.  The  effects  upon  their 
judgments  of  being  told  that  the  slug  was  made  of  lead,  silver,  white  gold,  or 
platinum  are  shown  in  the  figure.  {Adapted  from  Ashley,  Harper,  and  Runyon, 
1951.) 


by  the  monetary  value  of  the  bills,  though  apparent  size  increased 
with  increasing  complexity  of  patterns  on  the  control  rectangles. 

In  some  experiments  essentially  valueless  objects  have  been 
artificially  endowed  with  symbolic  "value"  by  inscribing  them  with 
marks  such  as  the  dollar  sign.  This  procedure  was  followed  by 
Solley  and  Lee  (1955).  In  their  study  white  cardboard  disks  bear- 
ing the  dollar  sign  were  found  to  be  significantly  overestimated 
even  though  the  nonmonetary  symbols  used  on  control  disks  had 
been  judged  to  have  the  same  degree  of  "perceptual  closure"  as 
the  dollar  sign.  These  data  were  interpreted  to  mean  that  symbolic 
value  affects  perceived  size,  but  the  brevity  of  the  original  report, 
which  describes  only  one  other  symbol  (swastika),  makes  critical 
appraisal  difficult.  The  disks  were  equated  for  degree  of  closure, 
but  this  may  not  have  eliminated  the  kinds  of  stimulus  variables 
which,  in  perceptual  illusions,  lead  to  nonveridical  report. 

The  hypothesis  that  symbolic  value  affects  apparent  size  is 
supported  to  some  degree,  however,  by  a  study  of  Dukes  and 
^van  (1952).  Their  subjects  participated  in  a  "gambling"  game 


298  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

involving  cards  of  identical  size  but  of  different  symbolic  value, 
as  indicated  by  printed  numbers  ranging  from  —  300  through  0  to 
+  300.  These  cards  were  randomly  chosen,  and  the  subject  won 
or  lost  amounts  determined  by  the  printed  numbers.  After  each 
such  trial,  the  subjects  selected,  from  a  graduated  series  of  blank 
control  cards,  one  which  they  judged  equal  in  size  to  the  value  card. 
As  the  monetary  value  printed  on  the  test  card  increased  from  0 
to  +  300  the  subjects  tended  to  select  larger  reference  cards.  That 
is,  the  estimates  of  size  were  smallest  for  test  cards  of  0  (printed) 
value  and  increased  in  a  negatively  accelerated  manner  as  symbolic 
value  was  heightened.  However,  the  subjects  also  tended  to  select 
larger  and  larger  blank  reference  cards  as  the  value  of  the  printed 
cards  changed  from  0  to  —  300.  If  one  regards  this  as  decreasing 
positive  value,  as  seems  reasonable,  then  the  results  for  the  negative 
cards  fail  to  conform  to  the  value-size  hypothesis.  These  results 
might  be  due  in  part  to  the  fact  that  the  physical  length  of  the 
numbers  stamped  on  the  cards  increased  with  both  positive  and 
negative  value.  Consequently,  the  tendency  to  overestimate  the 
size  of  the  cards  at  the  extremes  of  the  scale,  whether  positive  or 
negative,  may  have  been  dependent  on  the  size  of  the  printed 
numbers  rather  than  on  "subjective  value."  No  nonvalued  control 
cards  were  used  to  evaluate  the  significance  of  this  factor. 

Additional  positive  results  have  been  reported  by  Beams  (1954), 
who  observed  that  children  with  strong  food  preferences  tended 
to  make  significantly  more  frequent  larger-than  judgments  of  their 
favored  foods.  Mausner  and  Siegel  (1950),  however,  using  stamps 
of  similar  size  and  shape,  but  of  alleged  values  ranging  from  5 
cents  to  $12,  found  no  evidence  for  the  alteration  of  recognition 
thresholds  by  value. 

Similar  studies,  in  which  factors  other  than  value  have  been 
manipulated,  have  produced  both  positive  and  negative  results. 
Thus  Bruner  and  Postman's  (1948)  subjects  judged  tokens  in- 
scribed with  positive  symbols  as  larger  than  tokens  bearing  negative 
or  unpleasant  inscriptions.  Klein,  Schlesinger,  and  Meister  (1951), 
however,  in  a  comparable  study  were  unable  to  demonstrate  that 
the  apparent  size  of  neutral  objects  was  changed  by  affective 
symbols.  Young  children  may  be  more  susceptible  to  these  effects, 
since  Lambert,  Solomon,  and  Watson   (1949)   report  enhanced 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   PERCEPTION  299 

estimates  of  the  size  of  neutral  disks  that  have  been  associated 
with  rewards,  and  diminutions  of  size  when  rewards  are  with- 
drawn. 

Though  lack  of  space  does  not  permit  a  full  report  of  other 
studies  relevant  to  the  problem  of  size  as  a  function  of  value,  it 
seems  fair  to  conclude  that,  at  best,  the  effect  is  relatively  slight 
especially  when  the  valued  objects  are  physically  present.  Value 
seems  to  exert  its  greatest  effects  upon  the  judgments  of  children 
and  hypnotized  adults,  and  individual  differences  in  the  need  for 
money  influence  judged  size,  provided  that  estimates  are  made 
from  memory. 

An  Interpretation  of  Size-Value  Relations.  The  data  we  have 
reviewed  on  the  size-value  hypothesis,  though  leaving  many  ques- 
tions unanswered,  are  sufficiently  suggestive  to  warrant  further 
research  as  well  as  the  development  of  theories  as  to  how  value 
might  affect  apparent  size.  In  this  latter  area  little  has  been  done, 
and  Jenkin  (1957),  in  his  comprehensive  review,  lists  only  two 
such  attempts.  One  of  these  is  a  single  sentence  by  Bruner  and 
Rodrigues  suggesting  that  the  effect  may  be  due  somehow  to  the 
frequent  pairing  in  the  environment  of  size  and  value.  The  other, 
a  proposal  of  Dukes  and  Bevan,  is  that  value,  like  certain  param- 
eters of  electronic  circuits,  functions  to  "tune"  the  organism  to 
respond  selectively  and  with  "amplification"  to  valued  objects.  In 
an  earlier  section  of  this  chapter  it  was  suggested  that  valued 
objects  might  function  after  the  manner  of  incentives  to  arouse 
anticipatory  drive-producing  reactions.  However,  the  details  of 
the  process  through  which  value  might  affect  size-estimating  be- 
havior were  not  presented,  and  it  is  to  this  task  that  we  now  turn. 

In  a  psychophysical  study  employing  the  method  of  constant 
stimuli,  accentuated  size  would  be  revealed  as  a  displacement  of 
the  function  toward  the  region  of  the  stimulus  dimension  com- 
posed of  large  comparison  objects.  Such  a  shift  has  been  dia- 
gramed in  Fig.  8:11,  the  assumption  being  that  the  solid-line  curve 
was  obtained  when  a  metal  disk  the  size  of  a  50-cent  piece  was 
compared,  as  the  standard  stimulus,  with  other  metal  disks.  The 
dashed-line  curve  is  assumed  to  have  resulted  from  the  use  of  a 
real  half  dollar  as  the  standard  stimulus.  In  this  imaginary  experi- 
ment, the  point  of  subjective  equality  (PSE)  falls  at  stimulus  4 


300 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


(O  T3 
(O    (D 


4= 


uu 

Neutral  disk  as— -.^^     y/^       y^ 

standard  stimulus  ^^^V*^         ^ 

75 

•            / 

/          ^ 

/          jt--      *^°'"  ^^ 

/         /'^—-standard 

50 

/          /             stimulus 

/  \       /^ 

/          /        1 

/          1  /          1 

X          ^           ' 

25 

/         ./jPSEforl 
/           X        1    disk    |-«—PSE  for  coin 

^^^             ^ 

^^^             ^                        1                 1 

n 

— ^T               — <?•                   1                     1                     1                     1                     1 

1  2  3  4  5  6  7 

Diameter  of  variable  stimulus  disks 

Fig.  8:11.  Fictitious  data  to  illustrate  the  kind  of  displacement  of  a  psycho- 
physical function  that  should  be  obtained  with  the  method  of  constant 
stimuli  if  a  coin  tends  to  be  judged  larger  than  a  neutral  disk  of  equal  diameter. 
It  is  assumed  here  that  the  point  of  subjective  equality  {PSE)  shifts  from 
variable  stimulus  4  to  stimulus  5  when  the  coin  is  used  as  the  standard 
stimulus. 


with  a  metal-disk  standard  stimulus  and  at  stimulus  5  with  the 
coin  as  a  standard.  For  simplicity,  no  change  in  slope  is  assumed 
to  have  accompanied  the  rightward  displacement  of  the  curve.  In 
interpreting  the  dashed-line  curve  we  must  remember  that  the 
decreased  percentages  of  "larger  than"  judgments  for  all  the 
comparison  metal-disk  stimuli  mean  a  general  increase  in  the 
tendency  to  judge  the  valued  coin  as  "larger." 

As  a  result  of  our  previous  analyses  the  conclusion  was  reached 

that  an  increase  in  drive  alone  should  increase  the  steepness  of  a 

psychophysical  function,  but  should  not  displace  the  entire  func- 

rtion  in  the  manner  shown  in  Fig.  8:11.  Altered  habit  strengths, 

V  however,  could  have  this  effect.  The  necessary  steps  in  developing 

y  this  argument  are  as  follows: 

First,  we  reiterate  the  view  that  an  object  such  as  a  coin  has 
positive  value  only  because  individuals  approach  and  select  it  in 
preference  to  other  objects.  Consequently,  objects  can  only  be 
rank-ordered  with  respect  to  value  when  we  know  the  rank  orders 
of  their  capacities  to  elicit  choosing  and  seizing  responses.  Sec- 
ondly, in  a  great  many  instances,  objective  size  tends  to  vary  direct- 


■  Pt 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  301 

ly  with  value,  especially  when  similar  types  of  objects  are  grouped 
together.  Houses,  cars,  diamonds,  ranches,  TV  sets,  candy  bars, 
and  bundles  of  money  are,  for  the  most  part,  more  valuable  when 
large  than  when  small.  Consequently,  it  seems  reasonable  to  expect 
that  tendencies  to  make  verbal  responses  such  as  "large,"  "impres- 
sive," "bigger,"  "heavier,"  "broader,"  and  "higher,"  should  become 
strongly  associated  through  learning  with  those  objects  toward 
which  strong  habits  of  approach  are  being  established.  Hence  it 
follows  that  any  object  of  demonstrable  value  must  be  one  tending 
strongly  to  evoke  instrumental  choice  reactions  and,  in  addition, 
verbal  responses  of  the  general  class  "large."  Finally,  a  shift  of  the 
point  of  subjective  equality  must  occur  if  a  valued  object  elicits 
more  "larger-than"  responses  than  a  neutral  object  of  equal  size. 
To  find  such  a  shift  is  to  obtain  empirical  evidence  that  "value  l^-J^H"^ 
leads  to  a  perceptual  accentuation  of  size." 

It  will  be  seen  that  this  interpretation  of  the  effects  of  value 
upon  judgments  of  size  is  purely  associative,  since  it  contains  no 
reference  to  a  specific  motivational  entity.  Moreover,  this  view  is 
similar  in  some  respects  to  the  Bruner-Rodrigues  conception,  men- 
tioned earlier,  and  to  suggestions  presented  by  Lambert,  Solomon, 
and  Watson  (1949).  Our  interpretation  is  also  consistent  with 
the  findings  of  experiments  such  as  that  of  Proshansky  and  Murphy 
(1942),  in  which  perceptual  judgments  were  altered  by  rewards 
and  punishments. 

The  Perception  of  Stimuli  Associated  -with  Noxious  Events.  As 
we  have  seen,  it  may  be  possible,  by  manipulating  the  value  of 
a  stimulus  object,  to  vary  habit  strengths  and/or  incentive  motiva- 
tion and  hence  to  change  the  nature  of  the  responses  defining 
perceived  magnitude.  If  a  subject  is  repeatedly  punished  rather 
than  rewarded  for  responding  to  certain  stimuli,  one  would  expect 
that  avoidance  behavior  and  emotionality  would  become  strongly 
associated  with  such  stimuli  and  that  changes  in  drive  and  habits 
resulting  from  such  learning  might  also  affect  perceptual  behavior. 

Existing  experiments  in  which  anxiety-arousing  stimuli  have  been 
used  as  the  to-be-perceived  cues  may  be  divided  into  two  broad 
classes.  In  one  the  perceptual  identification  of  initially  neutral 
cues  is  tested  following  a  training  period  in  which  noxious  stimuli 
— usually  electric  shocks — have  been  paired  with  the  neutral  cues 


302  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

— usually  words.  Studies  constituting  the  second  group  are  distin- 
guished by  the  use  of  stimuli  such  as  vulgar  words,  which,  as  a 
consequence  of  socialization  training,  have  supposedly  acquired 
tendencies  to  evoke  emotional  reactions  of  disgust,  apprehension, 
or  anxiety.  (The  present  section  deals  with  only  the  first  group, 
the  second  being  covered  subsequently.)  Though  superficially  dif- 
ferent, both  groups  of  experiments  pose  the  question  of  whether  a 
conditioned  stimulus  for  an  emotional  response  can  be  more  {or 
less)  readily  identified  than  an  equally  familiar  neutral  stimulus. 
Or,  when  account  is  also  taken  of  typical  experimental  procedures, 
the  question  becomes  that  of  whether  responses  of  identifying  and 
naming  impoverished  forms  of  a  given  stimulus  will  be  altered 
when  that  stimulus  also  elicits  an  emotional  response. 

Conceptualizing  the  problem  in  this  manner  permits  us  to  relate 
this  kind  of  perceptual  research  to  other  traditionally  nonpercep- 
tual  problems.  For  one  thing,  it  becomes  clear  that  in  this  area 
the  student  of  perception  and  the  student  of  conditioned  fear  or 
anxiety  are  dealing  with  much  the  same  phenomena,  though  the 
former  individual  is  less  interested  in  the  strength  of  the  emotional 
response  than  in  its  effects  on  identifying  reactions.  The  student 
of  perception  asks  whether  a  learned  emotional  tendency  functions 
as  a  motivational  variable  in  modifying  the  effective  strength  of  a 
nonemotional  associative  tendency  (the  identifying  response)  when 
both  tendencies  are  attached  to  the  same  stimulus.  But  this,  as 
has  been  noted  in  Chapter  5,  is  very  similar  to  the  acquired-drive 
problem.  It  is  this  relation  that  has  led  us  to  treat  these  perceptual 
tasks  as  activities  involving  secondary  sources  of  drive. 

Studies  of  the  perception  of  threatening  stimulus  objects  are 
also  similar  to  experiments  on  stimulus  generalization,  save  that 
in  the  former  studies  the  stimulus  in  its  clearly  identifiable  form 
elicits  both  a  learned  identifying  response  and  an  emotional  reac- 
tion that  may  function  motivationally.  In  presenting  generalized 
(impoverished)  versions  of  that  stimulus,  therefore,  one  seeks  to 
determine  whether  the  generalized  identifying  response  will  be 
modified  in  motivational  ways  by  the  simultaneously  elicited  gen- 
eralized emotional  response.  A  so-called  neutral  control  stimulus  is 
presumably  one  whose  impoverished  versions  elicit  a  generalized 
identifying  response  but  little  or  no  emotion. 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  303 

The  problems  that  arise  in  studying  the  identification  of  inimical 
cues  are  also  related  to  those  that  attend  research  on  stimulus 
distinctiveness.  The  central  problem  in  the  latter  investigations  is 
whether  the  identifiability  of  a  stimulus,  as  estimated  from  the 
ease  with  which  new  responses  can  be  attached  to  it,  can  be 
enhanced  by  associating  other  distinctive  (often  nonverbal)  re- 
sponses with  that  cue.  Here,  however,  in  contrast  to  the  so-called 
perceptual  experiments,  the  added  associative  connections  are 
typically  neutral  emotionally. 

In  the  light  of  the  preceding  analysis,  and  assuming  that  emo- 
tional arousal  often  has  motivational-variable-like  effects,  we  must 
go  on  to  specify  the  mechanism  or  mechanisms  underlying  emo- 
tionally altered  perceptions. 

Mechanisms  of  Emotionally  Modified  Perceptual  Behavior.  It  is 
an  unfortunate  fact  that  in  the  studies  under  consideration  one 
finds  few  specific  statements  or  hypotheses  as  to  how  emotionality 
may  affect  perception.  Although  it  is  usually  assumed  that  emo- 
tionality is  motivating,  almost  nothing  is  said  about  either  the 
nature  of  motivation  or  its  relation  to  perception.  In  general  terms, 
motivation  is  alleged  to  function  either  to  prevent  the  individual 
from  seeing  the  stimulus  clearly — this  is  termed  perceptual  defense 
— or  to  help  him  to  see  the  stimulus  more  clearly — this  is  percep- 
tual vigilance  or  sensitization.  As  numerous  writers  have  noted, 
however,  specific  hypotheses  as  to  which  of  the  two  effects  will 
occur  under  a  given  set  of  conditions  are  singularly  rare. 

On  the  assumption  that  a  perceptual  situation  involves  the 
sequence  of  the  stimulus  (S),  a  covert  perceptual  response  (fp), 
and  an  overt  (usually  verbal)  identifying  response  (Ry),  there 
appear  to  be  two  possible  ways  in  which  Rr  can  be  affected  by 
stimulus-evoked  emotionality.  First,  if  the  emotional  response  (re) 
occurs  either  before,  or  concomitantly  with,  r^,  then  the  develop- 
ment of  Tp,  and  ultimately  of  Ry,  could  either  be  hindered  or 
facilitated  by  r^,  depending  upon  the  properties  assigned  to  fg. 
Second,  if  Tg  has  a  longer  latency  than  rp,  as  would  certainly  be 
the  case  if  the  occurrence  of  re  were  contingent  upon  rp,  then  any 
effects  of  re  upon  overt  behavior  would  have  to  be  due  to  modifica- 
tions of  the  functional  linkage  between  rp  and  Rv  or  to  direct 
effects  upon  Ry.  According  to  some  authors,  it  is   only  when 


304  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

behavior  is  affected  in  the  first  of  these  ways  that  one  can  properly 
speak  of  "pure"  perceptual  defense  or  vigilance.  For  such  writers 
alterations  in  behavior  attributable  to  the  second  of  the  above 
mechanisms  should  be  regarded  as  instances  of  response  suppres- 
sion or  augmentation,  since  the  alleged  perceptual  response  (r^)  is 
not  directly  affected  by  rg. 

To  clarify  the  implications  of  this  interpretation,  let  us  suppose 
that  a  single  taboo  word  is  presented  just  once  at  near  threshold 
level  to  each  of  a  group  of  subjects.  If  this  word  is  identified  less 
often  than  an  equally  familiar  neutral  word  (presented  in  the 
same  way  to  other  subjects),  either  the  hypothesis  of  "pure"  per- 
ceptual defense  or  the  hypothesis  of  response  suppression  could 
account  for  the  results.  But  if  each  subject  is  presented  with  only 
one  word  on  a  single  occasion,  the  emotionality  produced  by  that 
word  can  only  affect  r^,  and  thereby  produce  "pure"  perceptual 
defense  or  vigilance,  if  Tg  occurs  as  soon  as  or  before  r^.  Unfor- 
tunately, little  can  be  said  about  the  relative  latencies  of  emotional 
and  perceptual  responses.  But  from  what  is  known  concerning 
the  latencies  of  peripheral  autonomic  reactions  (cf.  Solomon  and 
Wynne,  1954)  it  would  appear  that  emotional  responses  may 
develop  too  slowly  to  affect  perception  itself  in  a  single-trial  situa- 
tion such  as  this. 

Stimulus-  induced  emotionality  may  not,  therefore,  affect  percep- 
tion in  this  kind  of  single-trial  experiment,  but  the  procedures 
followed  in  actual  experiments  are  such  that  even  if  Vg  does  have 
a  long  latency,  it  nevertheless  can  affect  perception.  Thus  it  is 
customary  in  studies  of  perceptual  defense  to  present  each  word 
a  number  of  times,  exposure  durations  being  increased  progres- 
sively, as  in  the  ascending  order  of  the  method  of  limits,  until 
recognition  occurs.  Obviously  even  a  long-latency  Ve,  provided  it 
persists  for  several  seconds,  can,  under  these  conditions,  antedate 
and  thereby  modify  perceptual  responses  elicited  by  subsequent 
presentations  of  the  same  or  different  words.  Moreover,  the  emo- 
tionality generated  by  additional  taboo  words  in  a  list  could  serve 
either  to  heighten  the  average  emotional  level  or  to  prevent  its 
decline.  Conventional  experimental  procedures,  therefore,  insure 
that  Tp  can  be  affected  by  emotionality,  though  they  do  not  insure 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  305 

that  the  influence  of  fg  will  be  confined  to  Vp  alone,  since  a  persist- 
ing Te  could  also  affect  the  relation  of  tp  to  Ry. 

Evidence  to  support  this  hypothesis  of  persisting  emotionality 
is  provided  by  the  McGinnies  and  Sherman  (1952)  study,  in  which 
recognition  thresholds  for  neutral  words  were  found  to  be  elevated 
by  the  prior  presentation  of  taboo  words.  They  used  the  term 
"generalization"  for  this  effect,  but  it  seems  more  appropriate  to 
describe  it  as  persisting  or  residual  emotionality.  Incidentally,  the 
hypothesis  of  persisting  emotionality  leads  to  the  methodological 
recommendation  that  neutral  words  should  not  be  interspersed 
among  nonneutral  words  in  the  same  list  if  one  wishes  to  maximize 
differences  in  the  thresholds  for  the  two  kinds  of  words. 

Turning  now  to  the  specific  roles  that  might  be  played  by  Te, 
it  is  clear  that  both  its  possible  contribution  to  general  drive  and 
its  associative  effects  merit  consideration.  On  the  assumption  that 
drive  varies  directly  with  the  strength  of  rg,  the  problem  is  reduced 
to  the  more  general  one  that  we  have  already  discussed  of  word- 
identification  thresholds  as  a  function  of  drive  intensity.  Thus  if 
the  associative  strengths  of  the  neutral  and  taboo  words  in  a  single 
list  are  simply  weakened  by  impoverishment  rather  than  sup- 
planted by  other  (incorrect)  associative  tendencies,  then  all  thresh- 
olds should  be  lowered  by  heightened  drive.  Or  if  taboo  words 
alone  are  presented  to  one  group  of  subjects  and  neutral  words 
to  another  group  (familiarity  equated)  then  only  the  taboo-word 
thresholds  should  be  lowered,  provided  additional  qualifying  as- 
sumptions such  as  the  above  are  also  met. 

Any  associative  interpretations  that  one  might  formulate  of  the 
effects  of  Te  upon  word-identification  thresholds  would  probably 
follow  the  general  lines  of  reasoning  presented  in  Chapter  4  and 
in  earlier  portions  of  this  chapter.  For  example,  it  might  be  postu- 
lated that  Te  leads  to,  or  produces,  distinctive  internal  stimuli  (Se) 
and  that  either  facilitative  or  competitive  reaction  tendencies  have 
been,  or  can  become,  attached  to  Sg  through  learning.  From  these 
assumptions,  defenselike  or  vigilancelike  effects,  that  are  either 
selective  or  nonselective  with  respect  to  taboo  and  neutral  words, 
could  be  satisfactorily  explained.  It  should  be  noted,  however, 
that  the  concept  of  emotionality  is  not  crucial  to  associative  inter- 
pretations such  as  these,  and  in  a  later  section  of  this  chapter  it 


306  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

will  be  shown  that  some  of  the  findings  of  perceptual  experiments 
can  be  deduced  from  nonemotional  assumptions  resembling  those 
of  modern  conflict  theory. 

The  Perception  of  Stimuli  That  Have  Been  Paired  with  Shock. 
We  turn  now  to  specific  laboratory  studies  in  which  recognition 
thresholds  have  been  determined  for  stimuli  with  which  electric 
shocks  have  been  associated.  Investigations  of  the  recall  of  shocked 
words  or  syllables  are  omitted  on  the  ground  that  they  are  related 
only  indirectly  to  perceptual  behavior. 

In  an  experiment  whose  major  purpose  was  not  the  investigation 
of  perceptual  accuracy  as  a  function  of  conditioned  emotionality, 
Lazarus  and  McCleary  (1951)  nevertheless  obtained  some  relevant 
evidence.  In  the  standardization  phase  of  their  experiment,  10  five- 
letter  nonsense  syllables  were  presented  tachistoscopically  at  near 
threshold  levels.  On  the  basis  of  the  subjects'  responses,  two  groups 
of  five  syllables  each  were  equated  with  respect  to  the  number 
of  times  they  were  correctly  recognized  and  also  with  respect  to 
the  frequency  of  their  use  by  the  subjects.  Thus  possible  differences 
in  familiarity  between  the  two  sets  of  syllables  were  minimized. 
Then,  with  the  syllables  clearly  exposed  for  one-second  periods, 
galvanic  skin  responses  (GSRs)  were  conditioned  to  five  of  the 
syllables  by  the  use  of  electric  shock.  Finally,  all  syllables  were 
again  presented  in  a  tachistoscope  at  short  exposure  times,  GSRs 
were  recorded,  and  five  seconds  after  each  exposure  the  subjects 
made  verbal  reports  of  what  they  had  seen. 

The  results  obtained  from  tabulations  of  verbal  reports  are  of 
immediate  relevance  here.  These  data,  when  corrected  for  response 
preference,  failed  to  indicate  significant  differences  in  the  recog- 
nition of  shock  and  nonshock  syllables.  However,  when  no  correc- 
tion for  response  frequency  was  made,  seven  of  nine  subjects  iden- 
tified the  shock  syllables  more  accurately  than  the  nonshock 
syllables,  though  again  the  differences  were  not  significant.  These 
data  are  consistent  with  the  view  that  success  in  perceptual  iden- 
tification depends,  in  part,  upon  response  frequency,  but  they 
yield  no  support  for  the  supposition  that  the  addition  of  an  emo- 
tional tendency  to  a  stimulus  (by  conditioning)  modifies  the 
accuracy  of  identifying  responses. 

From  analyses  of  their  GSR  data,  Lazarus  and  McCleary  con- 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  307 

eluded  further  that  even  when  subjects  are  unable  to  make  correct 
verbal  identifying  responses,  autonomic  discrimination  may  be 
possible.  This  judgment  was  based  on  the  fact  that  all  nine  of 
their  subjects  gave  larger  GSRs  to  shock  than  to  nonshock  syllables 
even  when  the  syllables  were  incorrectly  reported  verbally.  This 
effect  was  termed  subception  to  indicate  that  "perceptual"  dis^ 
crimination,  defined  by  autonomic  activity,  apparently  takes  placp, 
even  when  "perceptual"  discrimination,  defined  by  verbal  report, 
does  not. 

The  subception  effect  and  comparable  effects  reported  by  Mc- 
Ginnies  (1949)  and  others  have  generated  considerable  argument 
and  counterargument.  The  findings  place  some  theorists  in  the 
difficult  position  of  having  to  hold  that  a  shock  syllable  is  in  a 
sense  "perceived"  as  a  shock  syllable  (and  hence  the  subject  reacts 
to  it  emotionally),  and  yet  that  it  is  not  "perceived"  since  the 
subject  cannot  identify  it  correctly.  Thus  subjects  are  both  discrim- 
inating and  not  discriminating. 

This  seeming  paradox  disappears  if  we  reject  the  notion  that  all 
behavior,  including  autonomic  activity,  is  a  reflection  of  perception 
and  that  the  "real"  nature  of  perception  can  be  appraised  only 
through  phenomenological  statements  concerning  conscious  aware- 
ness. In  perception,  as  in  all  other  subject-matter  areas  of  psychol- 
ogy, there  is  no  one  "true"  measure,  and  inferences  based  on  any 
particular  measure  need  not,  and  often  do  not,  correlate  perfectly 
with  inferences  grounded  in  a  second  measure.  A  subject  in  a 
verbal  learning  experiment,  for  example,  may  appear  to  have 
learned  nothing  if  we  estimate  his  learning  by  means  of  the  method 
of  recall.  But  with  the  savings  method,  we  may  be  able  to  show 
quite  clearly  that  practice  has  led  to  considerable  learning.  Simi- 
larly, a  rat  in  a  T  maze  may  choose  one  side  as  often  as  the  other, 
and  from  this  we  would  conclude  that  no  differential  response 
tendency  has  been  established.  Measurements  of  running  time, 
however,  may  indicate  significantly  longer  times  on  one  side  than 
on  the  other,  and  quite  different  conclusions  may  be  indicated. 
By  analogy,  the  subjects  of  the  Lazarus-McCleary  experiment  were 
not  "discriminating"  when  verbal  reports  were  taken  as  the  criteria 
of  differential  response,  but  when  reference  was  made  to  the 
average  amplitudes  of  their  autonomic  reactions,  they  were  "dis- 


308  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

criminating."  The  fact  that  the  two  measures  yield  different  results 
should  cause  little  surprise  in  the  light  of  our  experience  in  other 
research  areas.  Bewilderment  ensues  only  when  we  speak  in  non- 
operational  terms  of  "awareness."  Unless  we  are  to  abandon  the 
principle  of  scientific  determinism  we  must  maintain,  as  Bricker 
and  Chapanis  (1953)  have  insisted,  that  when  responses  to  shock 
syllables  are  genuinely  greater  than  those  to  nonshock  syllables, 
and  if  other  factors  are  equal,  then  the  stimuli  provided  by  the 
two  kinds  of  syllables  must  be  unequal.  The  fact  that  verbal-identi- 
fying responses  to  shock  and  nonshock  syllables  do  not  differ  is 
indeed  interesting,  but  it  is  paradoxical  only  when  we  champion 
the  view  that  such  responses  constitute  the  only  "true"  mirror  of 
perception  as  it  "really"  is. 

Returning  now  to  additional  experiments  involving  electric 
shock,  we  find  several  of  interest.  Murphy  (1953),  for  example, 
obtained  evidence  that  shock  may  facilitate  the  perceptual  iden- 
tification of  nonsense  syllables.  However,  the  tachistoscopic  thresh- 
olds for  shock  syllables  were  not  significantly  lower  than  those 
for  nonshock  syllables,  save  when  a  normal  scale-value  trans- 
formation was  made  of  the  original  data.  Thus  the  degree  of 
generality  of  his  results  may  be  somewhat  limited.  Lysak  (1954) 
has  also  reported  that  previously  shocked  nonsense  syllables  are 
more  readily  seen  than  neutral  syllables  if  punishment  is  not  ad- 
ministered in  the  recognition  situation.  When  shocks  are  given 
both  during  training  and  recognition  phases,  however,  significantly 
higher  thresholds  are  obtained  for  shock  syllables  than  for  non- 
shock  syllables. 

Recce  (1954)  has  described  an  investigation  purporting  to 
demonstrate  a  relation  between  the  reinforcement  occasioned  by 
shock  reduction  following  the  pronunciation  of  a  nonsense  syllable 
and  the  visual  recognition  threshold  for  that  syllable.  He  used  a 
paired-associates  verbal  learning  task  in  which  electric  shocks  were 
administered  on  half  of  the  pairs  of  syllables.  For  one  group  of 
subjects  shock  was  terminated  (shock-escape  condition)  as  soon 
as  the  response  syllable  was  pronounced.  But  for  a  second  group 
the  shock  was  kept  on  (nonescape  condition)  for  the  entire  dura- 
tion of  syllable  presentation.  On  the  tachistoscopic  tests  the 
shock-escape  group  exhibited  generally  lower  thresholds  than  the 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  309 

group  for  whom  shock  escape  was  not  possible.  The  thresholds  for 
the  shock-escape  group,  however,  did  not  differ  from  those  of  a 
nonshocked  control  group.  Apparently  the  thresholds  of  the  shock- 
escape  group  were  not  lowered  by  reinforcement,  but  rather  the 
thresholds  of  the  nonescapable-shock  group  were  raised.  During  the 
course  of  the  paired-associates  learning  task,  shock  escape  produced 
significantly  better  learning  than  did  the  inescapable  shock  con- 
dition, but  not  better  than  the  nonshock  condition.  Thus  the 
obtained  differences  in  thresholds  appeared  to  be  due,  not  to 
improvement  resulting  from  shock  escape,  but  to  interference 
generated  by  inescapable  shock.  Poorer  performance  during  learn- 
ing would  indicate  weaker  associative  strengths,  and  hence  the 
recognition  scores  for  the  nonescapable-shock  group  should  be 
lower.  (This  would  qualify,  evidently,  as  an  associative,  not  a 
motivational,  interpretation.)  Finally,  Recce  found  no  significant 
differences  between  the  recognition  thresholds  for  shocked  and 
neutral  syllables  within  each  group,  regardless  of  whether  the 
syllables  were  the  "stimulus"  or  the  "response"  members  of  the 
pair.  This  is  consistent  with  the  negative  findings  of  the  Lazarus-\ 
McCleary  study  described  above,  and  with  the  theoretical  analysis'! 
in  the  preceding  section. 

In  a  more  recent  study  of  shock  and  perception,  Pustell  (1957) 
employed  geometrical  figures  (diamond,  circle,  square,  triangle) 
rather  than  taboo  words  or  nonsense  syllables.  In  a  pretest  phase, 
a  tachistoscope  was  used  to  present  cards,  on  each  of  which  were 
mounted  three  grey  forms  and  one  black  form.  The  subjects'  task 
was  to  identify  the  spatial  position  of  the  darker  figure  on  each 
card.  Then  in  a  training  phase  various  subgroups  of  subjects  were 
shocked  while  looking  at  each  of  the  different  black  figures. 
Tests  for  the  effects  of  shock  were  conducted  by  presenting  cards 
on  which  all  four  figures  were  black,  the  requirement  now  being 
to  point  out  the  section  of  the  card  "which  stood  out"  most. 
Because  of  the  brief  stimulus  exposures,  the  subjects  never  realized 
that  the  all-black  sets  of  forms  were  different  from  the  original 
training  sets  having  only  one  black  figure.  Significant  changes  in 
perceptual  thresholds  were  obtained  with  male  but  not  female 
subjects.  As  the  result  of  shock,  the  males  became  more  "vigilant," 
the  particular  form  previously  associated  with  shock  being  more 


310  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

often  denoted  as  "standing  out"  than  nonshock  forms.  Women, 
however,  were  affected  in  the  opposite  direction,  tending  to  become 
"defensive."  For  them  the  shock  figures  were  less  hkely  (not  sig- 
nificantly) to  be  seen  as  "outstanding."  Pustell,  in  attempting  to 
account  for  these  findings,  has  postulated  that  perhaps  anxiety 
provides  a  facilitative  cue  for  men  which  helps  them  to  identify 
the  shock  figure,  whereas  anxiety  (in  a  way  that  is  not  explained) 
provides  drive  for  women  and  thus  leads  them  to  be  defensive. 

The  Perception  of  Socially  Taboo  Stimuli.  Current  interest  in 
the  problem  of  the  perception  of  socially  taboo  words  stems  largely 
from  an  investigation  by  Bruner  and  Postman  (1947),  in  which 
elevated  thresholds  for  taboo  as  compared  with  neutral  words  were 
ascribed  to  perceptual  defense.  Although  the  literature  on  percep- 
tual defense  is  very  extensive,  explicit  definitions  of  the  term  are 
rare,  a  fact  which  may  account,  in  part,  for  the  frequent  debates 
the  field  has  witnessed  in  recent  years.  From  implicit  statements, 
however,  it  is  evident,  as  we  have  already  indicated,  that  perceptual 
defense  means  quite  different  things  to  different  writers.  For  some 
the  term  is  appropriate  only  to  those  incidents  in  which  the  pre- 
perception  is  both  unconscious  and  specific  to  the  preperceived 
stimulus,  and  in  which  the  defensive  reaction  affects  perception 
itself.  For  other  workers  perceptual  defense  seems  to  denote  sim- 
ply the  empirical  finding  of  higher  recognition  thresholds  for 
inimical  than  for  neutral  stimuli.  And  in  other  instances  the  term 
is  used  to  refer  to  a  more  or  less  conscious  avoidance,  of  the  sort 
made  by  individuals  when  they  catch  a  fleeting  glimpse  of  a  grue- 
some or  revolting  scene.  Closing  the  eyes,  looking  askance,  or 
thinking  of  other  things  are,  in  this  special  sense,  instances  of 
perceptual  defense.  The  term  perceptual  vigilance  has  also  been 
variously  and  vaguely  used,  though  it  has  received  less  attention 
than  the  concept  of  defense,  perhaps  because  vigilance  is  less 
dramatically  related  to  psychoanalytic  theory. 

During  the  years  since  defense  and  vigilance  first  came  into  psy- 
chological prominence,  two  major  trends  have  developed  in  re- 
search and  interpretation.  The  first  is  characterized  by  investiga- 
tions and  explanations  designed  to  prove  that  the  phenomena  of 
both  defense  and  vigilance  can  be  adequately  explained  by  appeal 
to  conventional  principles  of  associative  learning.  The  aim  of  these 


'       MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   PERCEPTION  311 

studies  has  been  to  show  that  differences  in  the  learning  history  of 
subjects  prior  to  their  entering  the  laboratory  can  account  for 
what  may  appear  to  be  laboratory-induced  changes  in  perceptual 
processes.  In  essence,  this  is  simply  an  associative  view  of  the  mech- 
anisms mediating  either  raised  or  lowered  identification  thresholds. 

The  second  stream  of  research  arises  from  the  premise  that 
defensiveness  and  vigilance  are  not  adjustive  reactions  of  the  popu- 
lation at  large  but  attributes  of  individual  personalities.  On  this 
view  some  subjects  will  be  defensive,  some  vigilant,  and  others 
may  be  both,  depending  on  the  nature  of  the  stimulus  material 
and  the  circumstances  under  which  it  is  presented.  Our  treatment 
of  research  in  this  area  will  involve  the  consideration  of  these  two 
major  trends. 

Perception  of  Taboo  Materials  as  an  Associative  Phenomenon. 
The  first  and  most  devastating  blows  against  the  view  that  defense 
is  an  unconscious,  motivationally  determined  effect  on  perception 
per  se  were  struck  by  Howes  and  Solomon  (1950)  and  by  Solomon 
and  Howes  (1951).  These  authors  approached  the  problem  from 
a  strictly  operational  point  of  view,  much  as  we  have  approached 
it  in  earlier  sections  of  this  chapter.  This  led  them  to  the  conclu- 
sion that  perception  is  not  studied  directly,  but  is  inferred  from, 
or  defined  by,  characteristics  of  the  subject's  responses  and  of  the 
stimuli  presented  to  him.  In  the  majority  of  experiments  on  human 
perception,  moreover,  the  subject's  responses  are  verbal  or  lin- 
guistic, and  hence  it  is  only  when  linguistic  responses  change 
that  one  can  properly  speak  of  changes  in  perception.  Thus,  to 
study  perception  in  these  situations  is  to  investigate  the  manifold 
variables  of  which  linguistic  behavior  is  a  function.  As  Solomon 
and  Howes  (1951)  have  phrased  it,  ".  .  .  any  variable  that  is  a 
general  property  of  linguistic  responses  must  also  be  a  property  of 
any  perceptual  concept  that  is  based  upon  those  responses"  (p. 
257). 

The  principal  conception  to  which  this  line  of  attack  leads  is 
that  the  perception  of  printed  words  must  depend,  in  considerable 
degree,  upon  the  frequency  with  which  the  individual  has  seen, 
pronounced,  and  used  those  words  in  the  past.  That  is,  the 
stronger  the  learned  associative  tendency  to  give  a  linguistic  re- 
sponse to  a  certain  cue,  the  more  readily  will  impoverished  forms 


312  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

of  that  cue  elicit  the  correct  response,  provided  impoverishment 
does  not  itself  alter  relative  associative  strengths.  In  the  typical 
perceptual  experiment,  this  means  that  recognition  thresholds 
should  decrease  as  familiarity  increases.  In  the  terminology  of  this 
book,  Howes  and  Solomon  were  simply  asserting  that  the  thresh- 
olds for  linguistic  identifying  responses  are  inversely  related  to  the 
habit  strengths  of  those  responses. 

In  criticizing  previous  studies  in  which  perceptual  defense  was 
alleged  to  have  been  operating,  Solomon  and  Howes  noted  that 
the  taboo  words  might  have  been  in  many  cases  less  familiar  to 
college  subjects  than  were  the  neutral  control  words.  Where  this 
was  true,  higher  thresholds  for  taboo  words  could  easily  be  ex- 
plained without  invoking  the  notion  of  defense.  And  by  a  similar 
line  of  reasoning  one  could  also  account  for  instances  of  perceptual 
vigilance,  provided  only  that  cogent  evidence  for  the  greater 
familiarity  of  the  stimuli  could  be  adduced. 

This  criticism  of  the  concept  of  perceptual  defense  has  un- 
doubtedly had  a  widespread  salutary  effect  upon  research  in  this 
area.  Almost  without  exception,  some  attempt  is  made  in  current 
investigations  of  the  phenomenon  to  equate  taboo  and  neutral 
words  for  familiarity  and/or  frequency  of  usage  prior  to  determin- 
ing their  relative  recognition  thresholds.  Familiarity  values  are 
most  commonly  allotted  to  stimulus  words  on  the  basis  of  their 
frequency  of  occurrence  in  written  English,  as  determined  by 
Thorndike  and  Lorge  (1944).  However,  there  is  some  question 
whether  the  Thorndike-Lorge  counts  are  representative  of  word 
frequencies  in  today's  written  English.  The  word  "Kotex,"  for 
example,  which  is  sometimes  used  as  a  taboo  word,  does  not  ap- 
pear in  these  counts.  Moreover,  it  is  doubtful  whether  any  index 
of  frequency  based  on  written  English  is  entirely  adequate  as  an 
estimate  of  word  familiarity  in  the  population  at  large  and  espe- 
cially among  college  students.  As  a  consequence,  those  who  defend 
the  concept  of  perceptual  defense  (e.g.,  McGinnies,  1950)  can 
assert  with  some  confidence  that  the  words  whore,  bitch,  and  belly 
are  far  more  familiar,  at  least  in  spoken  English,  than  the  words 
beatific,  elegies,  and  vignettes,  even  though  the  Thorndike-Lorge 
semantic  counts  show  them  all  to  be  equally  frequent.  If  the 
thresholds  for  taboo  words  such  as  these  are  elevated,  the  cham- 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  313 

pion  of  defense  may  declare  that  this  is  in  spite  of  their  relatively 
high  familiarity  as  estimated,  perhaps,  from  frequency  of  usage  in 
bull  sessions  and  bars.  And  the  opponent  of  defense,  relying  upon 
a  different  criterion  of  familiarity,  may  reason  that  the  elevated 
thresholds  are  due  simply  to  weaker  associative  strengths.  Opin- 
ions differ,  therefore,  with  respect  to  the  appropriateness  of  various 
methods  of  defining  familiarity.  But  it  is  generally  conceded  that 
any  alleged  instance  of  perceptual  defense  is  suspect  in  the  absence 
of  evidence  that  the  associative  strengths  of  critical  and  neutral 
words  have  been  equated. 

Perhaps  the  best  control  of  the  frequency  variable  has  been 
achieved  in  studies  where  the  same  words  have  been  used  under 
conditions  designed  to  make  them  either  threatening  or  neutral. 
McGinnies  and  Sherman  (1952),  as  we  have  pointed  out,  found 
that  neutral  words,  when  preceded  by  taboo  words,  exhibitedr 
higher  thresholds  than  when  the  neutral  words  were  preceded  by! 
other  neutral  words.  An  interpretation  in  terms  of  differential! 
familiarity  cannot  reasonably  be  applied  to  this  experiment  though  { 
residual  emotionality  might  account  for  the  findings.  Wienar 
(1955)  endowed  words  with  either  threatening  or  nonthreatening 
characteristics  by  imbedding  them  in  different  contexts  for  differ- 
ent groups.  His  subjects  exhibited  sensitization,  however,  rather 
than  defense,  a  threat  group  requiring  fewer  recognition  trials 
than  a  nonthreat  group.  This  finding  is  consistent  with  the  sup- 
position that  threat  leads  to  an  increment  in  drive,  which  in  turn 
magnifies  tendencies  to  make  appropriate  linguistic  responses  in 
the  recognition  situation. 

A  survey  of  experiments  in  which  adequate  controls  for  familiar- 
ity were  lacking  indicates  that,  with  unselected  populations,  both 
higher  and  lower  thresholds  are  reported  for  taboo  words,  the  first 
result  being  more  frequent  than  the  second.  The  preponderance 
of  defensive  indications  is  not  great,  however,  and  even  if  the 
familiarity  variable  were  not  involved  in  important  degree,  proc- 
esses other  than  defense  may  have  been  operating.  One  plausible 
explanation,  also  proposed  by  Howes  and  Solomon,  is  that  subjects 
may  resist  saying  a  taboo  word  in  the  presence  of  an  experimenter 
even  for  several  trials  after  the  word  has  been  covertly  identified. 
Thus,  for  example,  a  subject  might  well  hesitate  to  say  the  word 


314  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

penis  aloud  even  though  reasonably  certain  that  this  specific  word 
had  been  presented.  Since  the  tendency  to  inhibit  the  overt  enun- 
ciation of  taboo  words  in  certain  kinds  of  social  situations  is  un- 
questionably learned,  it  is  not  unreasonable  to  regard  this  "defen- 
sive mechanism"  as  fundamentally  associative. 

That  response  suppression  of  this  kind  may  often  function  to 
produce  "apparent  perceptual  defense"  is  indicated  by  a  variety 
of  studies.  Chief  among  these  is  the  investigation  of  Whittaker, 
Gilchrist,  and  Fischer  (1952),  in  which  it  was  found  that  Negro 
subjects  deliberately  refrained  from  making  verbal  identifications  of 
words  derogatory  to  their  race  until  the  stimuli  became  unam- 
biguously clear.  This  conclusion  was  based  on  verbal  statements 
of  the  subjects  and  on  the  fact  that  the  effect  was  observed  when 
the  experimenter  was  white  but  not  when  he  was  a  Negro.  Evi- 
dence for  comparable  effects  comes  from  other  studies  in  which 
subjects  have  reported  withholding  responses  or  where  significant 
subject-experimenter  interactions  have  been  observed.  The  act  of 
refraining  from  overt  enunciation  because  of  felt  or  imagined  so- 
cial threats  is  itself  quite  obviously  a  kind  of  defense  against 
anticipated  embarrassment.  It  does  not  qualify  as  perceptual  de- 
fense, however,  if  by  this  term  one  means  the  selective  filtering 
of  incoming  inimical  stimulus  patterns. 

In  trying  to  keep  subjects  from  withholding  overt  verbal  re- 
sponses, experimenters  have  devised  a  number  of  different  proce- 
dures. For  example,  subjects  may  be  instructed  to  respond  in 
writing  rather  than  orally;  they  may  be  told  ahead  of  time  that 
vulgar  words  are  to  be  presented  and  that  they  should  not  be  con- 
cerned over  speaking  them;  or  they  may  be  given  facilitative  sets 
through  instructions  which  allege  that  hesitation  in  uttering  the 
critical  words  is  a  sign  of  maladjustment  and  neuroticism.  The 
results  obtained  with  procedures  such  as  these  favor  the  conclu- 
sion that  as  the  tendency  to  withhold  overt  responses  diminishes, 
differences  between  recognition  thresholds  for  taboo  and  neutral 
words  tend  to  disappear.  Postman,  Bronson,  and  Gropper  (1953), 
for  example,  whose  subjects  responded  in  writing,  actually  found 
taboo  words  to  have  lower  thresholds  than  neutral  words,  a  differ- 
ence which  they  attributed  to  an  initial  underestimation  of  the  rel- 
ative familiarity  of  the  inimical  words.  Moreover,  Freeman  (1954) 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  315 

reported  that  when  subjects  were  set  to  look  for  taboo  words, 
recognition  thresholds  were  no  different  than  for  neutral  words. 
It  also  seems  likely  that  taboo-word  thresholds  tend  to  be  higher 
than  neutral-word  thresholds  at  the  start  of  an  experimental  ses- 
sion, the  difference  disappearing  progressively  as  the  subjects  come 
to  expect  and  get  set  to  report  the  taboo  items  (Bitterman  and 
Kniffen,  1953;  Lacy,  Lewinger,  and  Adamson,  1953). 

The  fact  that  subjects  who  are  told  to  expect  socially  unaccept- 
able words  tend  not  to  exhibit  perceptual  defense  does  not,  how- 
ever, constitute  a  crucial  argument  against  perceptual  defense. 
When  subjects  are  so  instructed,  they  are  thereby  predisposed  to- 
ward the  making  of  one  or  more  of  a  relatively  limited  number  of 
responses.  This  set  to  respond,  which  seems  to  qualify  as  an  asso- 
ciative process,  might  facilitate  the  identification  of  critical  words. 
But  if  the  taboo  and  neutral  thresholds  do  not  differ  significantly 
under  conditions  such  as  these,  the  advocate  for  defense  could 
certainly  argue  that  if  the  "bad"  words  had  not  been  selectively 
favored  their  thresholds  might  well  have  been  higher. 

In  summary,  it  can  be  stated  with  reasonable  confidence  that  in 
many  instances  where  an  unconscious  mechanism  of  perceptual 
defense  is  alleged  to  have  been  involved,  the  results  can  be  ex- 
plained more  simply  and  more  parsimoniously  by  appeal  to  well- 
known  principles  of  associative  learning.  Among  these  principles 
are  those  of  frequency  of  exposure  to  a  stimulus,  frequency  of 
previous  elicitation  of  the  response,  learned  tendencies  to  with- 
hold socially  inappropriate  responses,  and  selective  sets  which 
predispose  subjects  either  to  look  for  or  not  to  look  for  taboo 
words.  There  are  few  experiments,  indeed,  in  which  none  of  these 
associative  interpretations  has  proved  reasonable  and  in  which 
perceptual  defense  stands  out  as  the  most  acceptable  hypothesis. 

Competing  Response  Theory  of  Perceptual  Defense.  We  shall 
conclude  this  chapter  shortly  with  a  brief  look  at  studies  purport- 
ing to  show  that  perceptual  defense  and/or  vigilance  are  charac- 
teristic modes  of  adjustment  of  individual  personalities.  First,  how- 
ever, let  us  see  whether  some  of  the  findings  of  the  experiments 
we  have  just  considered  can  be  interpreted  in  somewhat  different 
associative  terms  than  those  proposed  by  Solomon  and  Howes. 

Initially,  let  us  assume  that  printed  vulgar  words  arouse  tend- 


316 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


encies  both  to  speak  and  not  to  speak.  Vulgar  words  (or  shocked 
words)  are  thus  the  counterparts  of  ambivalent  stimuli  in  a  con- 
flict situation  (cf.,  e.g.,  Miller,  1944;  Brown,  1957).  They  tend,  as 
a  result  of  socially  administered  reinforcements  and  punishments, 
to  elicit  incompatible  positive  and  negative  responses.  Moreover, 
since  severity  of  punishment  for  saying  a  vulgar  word  probably 
varies  directly  with  its  degree  of  vulgarity,  it  is  further  hypothesized 
that  the  tendency  for  such  words  to  elicit  avoidance  or  nonspeak- 
ing  responses  also  varies  directly  with  vulgarity. 

These  postulated  relationships  are  shown  graphically  in  Fig. 
8:12.  Here  the  base  line  denotes  degree  of  vulgarity,  and  the 
ordinate  shows  the  strength  of  the  positive  and  negative  tend- 
encies corresponding  to  each  word.  To  simplify  matters,  all  words 
are  regarded  as  being  equally  familiar  and  hence  as  possessing  iden- 
tical, strong,  positive  tendencies.  The  inhibitory  tendency  is  in- 
dicated as  weaker  than  the  positive  for  each  word,  whether  vulgar 
or  not,  since  in  actual  experiments  nearly  all  subjects  do  speak  such 
words  when  they  are  clearly  presented.  These  assumptions  permit 
one  to  deduce,  among  other  things,  that  overt  responses  to  "dirty" 
words  should  have  a  longer  latency  than  responses  to  neutral  words, 
even  when  all  are  presented  clearly.  To  deduce  the  phenomenon 


>^ 

o 

c 

0) 

•                                  .0                                  • 

Positive  tendency/ 

■o 

c 

a> 

x> 

-«' 

c 

^ 

o 

^ 

^ 

■•6 

jy 

(0 

^ 

a> 

^^ 

^^ 

•s 

^^ 

^'^^ ^^"~- Negative  tendency 

a> 

^^ 

x* 

w 

1 

1                  1                  1                  1 

Low 


Moderate 
Degree  of  vulgarity  of  stimulus  words 


High 


Fig.  8:12.  Relative  strengths  (assumed)  of  positive  tendencies  to  speak  and 
negative  tendencies  not  to  speak  when  stimulus  words  of  varying  degrees  of 
vulgarity  are  clearly  presented  (i.e.,  long  exposure  times  are  used).  The 
curves  are  constructed  on  the  premise  that  all  of  the  words  are  equally  familiar 
(flat  positive-tendency  curve),  but  differ  in  the  degree  to  which  they  elicit 
tendencies  to  inhibit  overt  expression. 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION 


317 


of  higher  tachistoscopic  recognition  thresholds  for  taboo  words, 
however,  we  need  additional  concepts. 

One  principle  that  seems  to  hold  considerable  promise  here  is 
that  of  stimulus  generalization.  To  apply  this  principle,  let  us  sup- 
pose that  the  tendency  to  speak  a  written  word  is  maximal  when 
tachistoscopic  exposure  time  is  long,  but  that  as  the  stimulus  be- 
comes impoverished  with  reduced  exposures,  the  strength  of  the 
tendency  decreases.  In  short,  the  function  relating  exposure  time 
to  strength  of  reaction  tendency  is  assumed  to  be  similar  to  a 
gradient  of  stimulus  generalization.  This  supposition  is  portrayed 
graphically  in  Fig.  8:13,  where  the  upper  curve  is  the  strength  of 
the  tendency  to  speak  a  moderately  vulgar  word  for  each  of  a  num- 
ber of  different  exposure  times.  (The  highest  point  on  this  curve 
has  been  set  to  equal  the  height  of  the  horizontal  positive-tend- 
ency curve  in  Fig.  8:12.)  This  figure  illustrates  the  further  hy- 
pothesis that  the  tendency  not  to  speak  the  off-color  word  also 
generalizes  along  the  dimension  of  exposure  time.  (The  maximum 
strength  of  the  weak  negative  tendency  equals  that  for  a  mod- 
erately vulgar  word  in  Fig.  8:12.)  Were  we  to  combine  this  gen- 
eralization figure  with  the  previous  one,  these  gradients  would  ex- 
tend out  toward  the  viewer  at  a  right  angle  from  the  surface  of 


MODERATELY  VULGAR  WORD 


Positive  tendency. 


Short 


Moderate 
Stimulus  exposure  duration 


Long 


Fig.  8:13.  Hypothetical  generalized  tendencies  to  pronounce  and  to  refrain 
from  pronouncing  a  moderately  vulgar  word.  Both  tendencies  are  assumed  to 
become  weaker  as  the  stimulus  is  impoverished  by  reducing  exposure  dura- 
tion. The  distance  (A)  between  the  points  of  the  double-headed  arrow  denotes 
the  assumed  amount  by  which  the  positive  tendency  must  exceed  the  negative 
for  the  response  to  become  overt. 


318  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Fig.  8:12,  Similar  pairs  of  generalization  curves  could  obviously 
be  constructed  for  each  of  the  words  of  Fig.  8:12. 

Assume  now  that  the  positive  and  negative  tendencies  summate 
algebraically  and  that  the  positive  must  exceed  the  negative  by  a 
certain  fixed  amount  for  the  response  to  become  overt.  As  has  been 
noted,  in  determining  thresholds  with  a  tachistoscope,  a  word  is 
usually  presented  for  increasingly  long  exposures  until  the  subject 
correctly  identifies  the  word  on  two  or  three  occasions.  In  terms  of 
Fig.  8:13,  this  means  that  over  successive  trials  there  will  be  a 
progressive  increase  in  the  difference  between  the  positive  and 
negative  tendencies.  This  increase  is  clearly  consistent  with  the  fact 
that  correct  recognition  responses  become  more  probable  with  in- 
creased exposure  duration.  It  has  been  assumed  that  the  identify- 
ing response  will  not  be  elicited  until  the  positive  tendency  ex- 
ceeds the  negative  by  a  certain  definite  amount,  which  is  indicated 
in  Fig.  8:13  by  the  double-headed  arrow  identified  by  a  delta  (A). 
For  this  off-color  word,  therefore,  the  recognition  threshold  should 
lie  at  an  exposure  duration  just  slightly  greater  than  one  of  mod- 
erate length. 

Suppose,  however,  that  an  unusually  vulgar  word  is  substituted 
for  the  off-color  one.  For  such  a  very  vulgar  word,  assuming  equal 
familiarity,  we  should  expect  the  positive  tendency  to  be  the  same 
as  before  but  the  negative  tendency  to  be  greater  for  all  exposure 
times.  This  is  schematized  in  Fig.  8:14,  where  the  negative  tend- 
ency at  maximum  is  about  equal  to  that  for  the  most  vulgar  word 
in  Fig.  8:12.  Since  the  generalized  inhibitory  tendency  is  stronger, 
as  is  shown  here,  for  all  exposure  durations,  the  positive  and  nega- 
tive curves  lie  closer  together  throughout  the  range  of  the  ex- 
posure-duration dimension  than  was  the  case  for  the  off -color  word. 
With  the  very  dirty  word,  therefore,  relatively  long  exposure  dura- 
tions must  be  reached  before  the  difference  (A)  between  the 
positive  and  negative  tendencies  becomes  sufficient  to  permit  the 
verbal  (recognition)  response  to  occur.  As  this  diagram  shows, 
the  double-headed  arrow  lies  farther  to  the  right  than  it  did  in 
the  previous  figure,  and  since  this  corresponds  to  increased  ex- 
posure durations,  a  higher  threshold  for  a  very  dirty  than  for  an 
off-color  or  neutral  word  can  thus  be  deduced.  Of  especial  sig- 
nificance, here,  is  the  fact  that  neither  emotion,  nor  drive,  nor 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND   PERCEPTION 


319 


VERY  VULGAR  WORD 


Positive  tendency 


Short 


Moderate 
Stimulus  exposure  duration 


Fig.  8:14.  Hypothetical  gradients  in  the  strength  of  generalized  positive  and 
negative  linguistic  tendencies  for  a  very  vulgar  word.  Here  the  difference  be- 
tween positive  and  inhibitory  tendencies  (A)  that  is  arbitrarily  assumed  to  be 
required  for  the  evocation  of  an  overt  reaction  falls  at  a  longer  exposure  dura- 
tion than  in  the  case  of  a  less  vulgar  word  (cf.  Fig.  8:13).  A  higher  recogni- 
tion threshold  for  very  vulgar  than  for  equally  familiar  neutral  or  moderately 
vulgar  words  can  thus  be  deduced. 

perceptual  defense,  nor  differential  familiarity  has  been  invoked  as 
a  necessary  adjunct  to  the  deduction. 

Personality  Characteristics  and  the  Perception  of  Taboo  Mate- 
rials. Those  who  currently  favor  the  concept  of  perceptual  defense 
emphasize  the  notion  that  defense  is  an  individual  mode  of  ad- 
justment to  threat.  If  their  idea  is  tenable,  then  an  unselected 
population  of  subjects  would  not  be  expected  to  exhibit  perceptual 
defense.  Rather,  since  some  individuals  react  in  a  defensive  man- 
ner and  others  in  a  sensitized  manner,  randomly  chosen  subjects 
should  show  neither  defense  nor  vigilance,  their  distinct  modes  of 
reacting  being  concealed  by  the  process  of  averaging. 

This  view,  that  reactions  to  threatening  stimuli  differ  consider- 
ably from  individual  to  individual  and  from  situation  to  situation, 
leads  to  research  procedures  which  differ  from  those  we  have 
previously  discussed.  The  principal  change  is  that  subpopulations 
of  subjects  are  chosen  initially  from  larger  groups  by  means  of 
tests  purporting  to  reveal  characteristic  personality  differences. 
Perceptual  tests  are  then  carried  out  to  determine  whether  the 
personality  attributes  correlate  with  degree  of  defensiveness  or 
vigilance.  In  principle  this  method  is  like  that  used  in  studies  of 


ti 


(W 


320  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

need  achievement  and  of  manifest  anxiety.  It  is  a  procedure  di- 
rected toward  the  discover)^  of  R-R  relationships,  since  it  is  hoped 
that  responses  made  to  the  items  of  one  test  will  be  correlated  with 
responses  elicited  by  a  second  test. 

This  general  approach  appears  to  have  stemmed  from  studies 
such  as  that  of  Postman,  Bruner,  and  McGinnies  (1948),  in  which 
an  attempt  was  made  to  relate  perceptual  selectivity  to  a  factor 
described  as  "personal  values."  By  personal  values  these  authors 
apparently  mean  individual  differences  in  the  degree  to  which  one 
is  interested  in,  or  places  high  value  upon  certain  things  or  ideas. 
Thus  a  scientist  presumably  places  a  higher  value  upon  scientific 
principles,  relations,  and  attitudes,  than  on  comparable  aspects  of 
other  areas  such  as  religion,  economics,  or  politics.  Similarly,  the 
artist,  the  politician,  and  the  businessman  each  has  his  own  char- 
acteristic value  or  interest  patterns.  And  even  individuals  who  can- 
not be  identified  in  terms  of  professional  affiliation  presumably 
have  higher  values  for  some  areas  than  for  others,  and  these  high- 
and  low-value  areas  should  be  detectable  by  means  of  suitable 
tests. 

In  the  Postman,  Bruner,  and  McGinnies  experiment,  college 
subjects  were  tested  by  means  of  the  Allport- Vernon  Study  of 
Values,  a  test  designed  to  yield  value  ratings  in  areas  described  as 
economic,  theoretical,  religious,  social,  esthetic,  and  political.  Each 
subject  was  also  given  the  perceptual  task  of  identifying  words  in 
each  of  the  six  value  areas.  The  results  of  the  perceptual  test  in- 
dicated that  there  was  some  tendency  for  the  subjects  to  see  words 
in  their  own  high-value  categories  more  readily  than  those  in  their 
low-value  groups.  Thus  an  individual  with  a  high  religious-value 
score  was  described  as  having  been  sensitized  to  religious  words. 
Conversely,  for  such  a  person^  scientific  or  theoretical  words  might 
be  threatening,  and  if  so,  he  should  exhibit  perceptual  defense  for 
such  words. 

Although  some  of  the  statistical  and  graphic  procedures  of  this 
study  can  be  seriously  questioned,  similar  results  have  been  re- 
ported by  Haigh  and  Fiske  (1952),  Solomon  and  Howes  (1951), 
and  others.  It  is  of  interest,  therefore,  to  consider  some  of  the 
factors  that  might  produce  a  positive  correlation  between  test- 
defined  value  orientation  and  perceptual  identifying  responses. 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  321 

For  most  writers  "value  orientation"  refers  to  a  kind  of  inner 
personalistic  factor  capable  of  organizing  both  the  perceptions  and 
the  overt  actions  of  the  individual.  Thus,  for  example,  Brown  and 
Adams  (1954)  assert  that  a  value  area  is  a  "central,  cognitive,  affec- 
tive construct."  As  such,  it  is  given  the  properties  of  determining 
both  selective  responses  made  to  value-test  items  and  selective 
perceptions  of  value-related  stimulus  words.  Postman,  Bruner,  and 
McGinnies  say  little  concerning  the  nature  of  value  orientation  per 
se,  save  that  it  results  from  a  long  process  of  socialization  and 
functions  to  modify  perception  by  means  of  selective,  accentuative, 
and  fixative  mechanisms. 

The  results  of  studies  relating  perception  to  value  orientation 
can  probably  be  explained,  however,  without  appealing  to  value  as 
such.  Thus  it  might  be  supposed  that  a  high  aesthetic  (or  other) 
value  orientation,  as  defined  by  scores  on  the  Allport-Vernon  test, 
means  simply  that  one  is  interested  in,  and  devotes  considerable 
attention  to  aesthetic  matters.  But  a  strong  interest  in  aesthetic 
and  artistic  subjects  would  lead  one  to  read  articles  and  books  on 
such  topics  to  the  relative  exclusion  of  other  works.  Consequently 
the  person  with  a  high  aesthetic-value  score  should  become  more 
familiar  with  the  particular  words  used  in  writings  on  aesthetics 
than  with  words  in,  for  example,  the  areas  of  science  and  politics. 
If  he  had  such  familiarity,  then  he  would  more  readily  identify 
aesthetic  words  when  they  were  presented  tachistoscopically  than 
words  of  other  value  areas.  And  this  should  hold  true  even  though 
the  aesthetic  and  nonaesthetic  words  occurred  with  equal  fre- 
quency in  printed  English  and  hence  would  be  defined  as  "equally 
familiar"  in  terms  of  a  criterion  such  as  the  Thorndike-Lorge  word 
count. 

This  interpretation,  it  may  be  seen,  is  essentially  the  associative, 
nonmotivational  one  proposed  by  Solomon  and  Howes  (1951) 
and  reiterated  by  Postman  (1953ci),  and  by  Farber  (1955).  It  is 
the  view  that  recognition  thresholds  are  determined  by  familiarity, 
that  unequal  familiarity  with  words  of  different  value  groupings 
depends  upon  one's  interests  or  preferences,  and  that  interests  or 
preferences  might  be  detected  by  responses  to  the  items  of  the 
Allport-Vernon  scale. 
Whether  value  as  a  special-purpose  cognitive  construct  need 


322  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

be  evoked  in  connection  with  such  an  interpretation  remains  a 
matter  of  individual  preference.  One  could  argue,  in  the  interest 
of  parsimony,  that  the  concept  of  value  is  quite  superfluous  since 
its  alleged  functions  as  a  determinant  of  behavior  can  be  ex- 
plained by  assuming  that  individuals  have  learned  through  socially 
administered  rewards  and  punishments  to  be  interested  in  differ- 
ent kinds  of  things.  Or  it  might  be  argued  that  value  orientation  is 
somehow  an  antecedent  to,  and  a  determinant  of,  one's  differential 
interests,  and  that  these  in  turn  determine  familiarity  and  hence 
differential  recognition  thresholds. 

Eriksen  (1954)  has  been  an  active  exponent  of  the  view  that 
defense  and  vigilance  are  idiosyncratic  rather  than  universal  modes 
of  response  to  threat.  He  has  criticized  the  conventional  proce- 
dures in  which  "dirty"  words  are  presented  to  randomly  selected 
subjects  on  the  ground  that  such  words  are  probably  not  anxiety 
arousing  for  all  or  even  most  typical  college  subjects.  Moreover, 
he  maintains  that  an  adequate  test  of  the  perceptual  defense  hy- 
pothesis necessarily  demands  some  evaluation  of  the  ways  in 
which  individual  subjects  handle  or  react  to  anxiety.  On  this 
view  one  must  demonstrate  that  individuals  differ  in  degree  of 
defensiveness  to  anxiety-arousing  stimuli  presented  in  nonpercep- 
tual  situations.  Subjects  cannot  be  said  to  be  perceptual  defenders 
unless  some  independent  support  is  thus  provided  for  the  assump- 
tion that  they  are  generally  defensive. 

The  adoption  of  this  theoretical  position  generally  leads  to  dis- 
tinctive kinds  of  research.  For  example,  Lazarus,  Eriksen,  and 
Fonda  (1951)  used,  with  neurotic  subjects,  a  sentence-completion 
test  in  which  some  of  the  sentences  could  easily  be  filled  out  with 
sexual  or  aggressive  solutions.  Subjects  who,  on  the  basis  of  this 
test,  could  be  defined  as  "expressive"  with  respect  to  sex  were  able 
to  perceive  auditorily  presented  sexual  sentences  as  well  as  neutral 
sentences.  But  subjects  who  tended  to  block  or  give  distorted 
endings  to  the  sexual  sentences  could  not  hear  the  sexual  sentences 
as  well  as  they  could  hear  the  neutral  ones.  In  another  study, 
Eriksen  (1951)  has  reported  that  some  subjects  show  signs  of 
blocking  or  emotional  upset  to  TAT  pictures  which  usually  elicit 
aggressive  reactions,  whereas  other  subjects  express  aggression  quite 
freely  in  their  stories.  When  tested  on  a  perceptual  recognition 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  323 

test,  the  former  subjects  had  higher  thresholds  for  aggressive  than 
for  neutral  pictures,  whereas  the  latter  subjects  had  relatively  low 
thresholds  for  the  aggressive  scenes. 

Research  studies  designed  along  similar  lines  have  been  carried 
out  by  Stein  (1953),  Chodorkoff  (1956),  and  Neel  (1954),  all  of 
whom  have  found  defensiveness  or  vigilance,  as  revealed  by  per- 
ceptual thresholds,  to  be  correlated  with  the  results  of  other  tests 
purporting  to  identify  personality  characteristics  of  individual 
subjects. 

By  way  of  conclusion  it  may  be  noted  that  although  the  study  of 
perceptual  defense  and/or  vigilance  as  an  individual-difference 
phenomenon  seems  like  an  attempt  to  prove  the  reality  of  percep- 
tual defense  in  the  face  of  such  criticisms  as  those  of  Solomon  and 
Howes,  it  is  nevertheless  a  perfectly  acceptable  way  of  proceeding. 
The  fact  that  randomly  chosen  subjects  may  not  exhibit  defense, 
particularly  when  frequency  of  prior  experience  with  the  stimuli 
has  been  properly  controlled,  does  not  mean  that  some  individuals 
might  not  exhibit  the  effect.  Clearly,  one  can  define  defensiveness 
in  terms  of  responses  to  a  sentence-completion  test  or  to  a  test  of 
some  other  kind,  and  then  proceed  to  study  the  relation  of  de- 
fensiveness thus  defined  to  reactions  evoked  in  other  test  situations. 
The  individual-difference  method  does  not,  however,  preclude  the 
possibility  that  the  reactions  to  all  tests  are  due  to  differential 
experiences  with  the  materials  of  the  tests  rather  than  to  percep- 
tual defense.  When  individuals  who  are  "expressive"  with  respect 
to  sexual  matters  are  selected  out  of  a  group,  we  may  simply  be 
selecting  those  who,  in  addition  to  being  expressive,  or  perhaps 
because  of  their  expressiveness,  have  had  more  extensive  experience 
with  sexual  words,  symbols,  and  ideas.  On  the  other  hand,  the 
test-defined  "sexual  inhibitor"  might  well  have  had  fewer  exposures 
to,  and  experiences  with,  materials  of  a  sexual  nature.  If  such 
groups  differ  in  their  ability  to  identify  sexual  words,  it  might  be 
more  sensible  to  explain  these  results  by  referring  to  individual 
differences  in  associative  strengths  rather  than  to  traits  of  defensive- 
ness or  to  value  systems  with  vague  motivational  overtones. 


324  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Summary 

Of  central  importance  to  the  discussions  in  this  chapter  is  the 
general  problem  of  the  effects  of  motivational  variables  upon 
perception.  However,  the  perceptions  of  subjects  whose  behavior 
is  being  studied  by  the  psychologist  cannot  be  observed  directly 
by  him,  and  perception  must  therefore  enter  into  theories  of  be- 
havior in  the  role  of  a  scientific  construct.  Like  other  constructs, 
e.g.,  motivation  and  associative  strength,  perception  must  be  ex- 
plicitly defined  within  scientific  language,  and  it  must  prove  its 
significance  through  its  capacity  to  enhance  our  understanding  of 
behavior.  That  a  construct  of  perception  may  not  be  needed  in 
behavior  theory  is  suggested  by  the  fact  that  many  so-called  percep- 
tual experiments,  in  which  subjects  are  required  to  identify  or  com- 
pare physically  present  stimulus  objects,  can  be  successfully  con- 
ducted and  useful  stimulus-response  laws  determined  without  any 
reference  to  perception.  Nevertheless,  perception  may  serve  a  use- 
ful explanatory  purpose  in  some  situations,  especially  those  in 
which  overt  identifying  responses  do  not  occur  until  some  time 
after  a  stimulus  has  been  withdrawn.  Inasmuch  as  perception  is 
often  defined  in  terms  of  subjects'  linguistic  responses,  a  motiva- 
tional variable  may  be  said  to  have  affected  perception  when  its 
introduction  leads  to  changes  in  the  kinds  or  frequencies  of  lin- 
guistic responses  exhibited  by  subjects  in  so-called  perceptual  ex- 
periments. 

In  an  effort  to  relate  the  motivation-perception  problem  to 
material  contained  in  earlier  chapters,  an  attempt  is  made  to  apply 
the  multiplicative-drive  hypothesis  to  behavior  in  psychophysical 
test  situations.  From  the  assumption  that  empirically  determined 
response  frequencies  provide  evidence  of  relative  habit  strengths 
1/  the  conclusion  is  reached  that  absolute  thresholds  may  either  be 
elevated  or  depressed  if  a  motivational  variable  leads  solely  to  the 
arousal  of  competitive  or  facilitative  habits.  But  if  the  variable 
affects  drive  alone,  the  slope  of  the  psychophysical  function  should 
fcecome  steeper,  the  threshold,  as  conventionally  defined,  remain- 
ing unaffected.  Similar  lines  of  reasoning  are  applied  to  the  inter- 
pretation of  data  obtained  from  studies  of  differential  sensitivity 
and  of  recognition  thresholds  for  meaningful  stimuli. 


MOTIVATIONAL  VARIABLES  AND  PERCEPTION  325 

Studies  of  the  effects  of  primary  sources  of  drive  upon  behavior 
in  perceptual  situations  have  yielded  suggestive  but  inconsistent 
results.  Some  observations  suggest  that  food  and/or  water  depriva- 
tion enhances  the  frequency  with  which  need-related  words  are 
given  as  responses  to  unstructured  stimuli  and  to  near-threshold 
presentations  of  need-related  words  or  pictures.  Deprivation  op- 
erations have  also  produced  contradictory  results,  both  within  and 
between  experiments,  and  in  some  cases  deprivation  leads  to 
poorer  performance  even  with  need-related  stimulus  items. 

A  large  majority  of  studies  relating  motivational  variables  to 
perception  consist  of  those  in  which  the  to-be-perceived  stimuli 
themselves  are  thought  to  function  as  motivational  variables.  Thus 
words  that  have  been  associated  with  positive  rewards,  with  elec- 
tric shock  in  the  laboratory,  or  with  social  punishments  have  been 
used  as  to-be-identified  stimuli  on  the  assumption  that  the  percep- 
tion of  such  words  will  be  modified  by  their  acquired  motivational 
properties.  Analyzed  in  this  way,  the  problem  may  be  described  as 
that  of  the  influence  of  secondary  sources  of  drive  upon  perceptual 
behavior. 

A  review  of  representative  investigations  purporting  to  show 
that  the  judged  size  of  objects  is  affected  by  their  value  leads  to 
the  conclusion  that  the  effect  at  best  is  slight,  especially  when  the 
valued  objects  are  physically  present.  The  judgments  of  children 
and  of  hypnotized  adults  appear  to  be  most  readily  affected  by  the 
variable  of  object  value,  and  individual  differences  in  the  need  for 
money  affect  judgments  of  remembered  coin  size.  It  is  suggested, 
by  way  of  interpretation,  that  because  of  socialization  processes,-*^ 
objects  of  value  tend  to  evoke  both  stronger  instrumental  prefer- 
ence responses  and  more  frequent  verbal  responses  of  the  general 
class  "large"  than  do  comparable  nonvalued  objects.  The  elicitation 
of  more  frequent  "larger-than"  responses  by  valued  objects  in  a  psy- 
chophysical investigation  is  the  basic  datum  indicating  that  value 
leads  to  an  accentuation  of  judged  size. 

Interpretations  of  differences  in  the  recognition  thresholds  for 
emotion-arousing  and  for  neutral  words  have  commonly  involved 
appeal  to  mechanisms  of  perceptual  defense  or  perceptual  sensitiza- 
tion (vigilance).  Defense  is  usually  described  as  an  unconscious 
process  akin  to  repression  that  functions  to  protect  one  from 


326  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

perceiving  things  that  are  distasteful  or  anxiety-arousing.  Early 
studies  purporting  to  have  demonstrated  this  phenomenon  have 
been  criticized  for  failing  to  equate  the  familiarity  of  taboo  and 
neutral  stimuli.  Later  investigations,  in  which  different  criteria  of 
familiarity  have  been  employed,  have  yielded  inconsistent  results, 
defense  being  reported  in  some  cases  and  vigilance  in  others.  In 
most  instances  interpretive  mechanisms  other  than  defense  or 
vigilance,  such  as  response  suppression,  familiarity,  and  predispos- 
ing sets,  appear  to  provide  more  parsimonious  interpretations  of 
lowered  or  raised  recognition  thresholds.  Higher  recognition  thresh- 
olds for  taboo  words  might  also  be  explained  on  the  grounds  that 
tendencies  both  to  speak  and  not  to  speak  such  words  have  been 
established  through  learning  and  that  these  tendencies  generalize 
along  the  dimension  of  exposure  duration.  Assuming  that  an  iden- 
tifying response  will  not  become  overt  until  the  tendency  to  speak 
exceeds  the  tendency  not  to  speak  by  a  given  fixed  amount,  it  is 
concluded  that  recognition  thresholds  would  fall  at  longer  ex- 
posure durations  for  taboo  than  for  neutral  words. 

The  final  section  of  this  chapter  contains  a  brief  review  of  in- 
vestigations designed  to  show  that  perceptual  defense  and  vigi- 
lance are  idiosyncratic  phenomena.  Underlying  these  studies  is 
the  view  that  an  individual  is  defensive  only  with  respect  to  cer- 
tain kinds  of  taboo  items  and  that  perceptual  defense  cannot  be 
demonstrated,  therefore,  unless  the  subjects'  defensive  areas  have 
been  appropriately  identified.  Experimental  findings  have  sup- 
ported this  contention,  since  defensiveness  (or  vigilance),  as  de- 
fined by  selection  procedures  of  a  nonperceptual  nature,  has  been 
found  to  correlate  with  perceptual  thresholds.  Even  in  these  in- 
stances, however,  alternative  interpretations  couched  in  terms  of 
individual  differences  in  familiarity  with  certain  classes  of  stimuli 
merit  careful  appraisal. 


CHAPTER 


9 


Miscellaneous 
Motivational  Problems 

This  final  chapter  deals  with  a  variety  of  problems,  which, 
though  only  tenuously  related  to  one  another,  are  all  of  consider- 
able interest  to  the  student  of  motivation.  Each  of  these  topics 
might  have  been  woven  into  the  fabric  of  the  preceding  chapters, 
but  only,  it  was  felt,  with  some  loss  of  continuity  and  over-all 
unity.  As  we  shall  see,  the  bearing  of  the  questions  considered 
here  upon  previously  discussed  problems,  though  somewhat  tan- 
gential, is  nevertheless  significant. 

Approach-eliciting  Stimuli  as  Motivational  Variables 

At  several  places  in  the  foregoing  pages  (especially  in  Chapters 
3  and  7)  it  has  been  noted  that  motivational  properties  are  com- 
monly attributed  to  such  external  stimuli  as  intense  electric  shocks, 
bright  lights,  blasts  of  air,  loud  noises,  and  acrid  odors.  Presum- 
ably these  stimuli  are  regarded  as  motivators  because,  as  experi- 
mental variables,  they  satisfy  one  or  more  criteria  (cf.  Chapter  2) 
for  the  identification  of  motivational  variables.  In  addition,  these 

327 


328  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

stimuli  tend  to  evoke  responses  of  escape  or  withdrawal,  a  charac- 
teristic that  results  in  their  being  described  as  noxious  or  aversive. 

There  are  many  other  external  stimuli,  however,  that  tend  to 
evoke  approach  rather  than  escape  reactions.  These  "benign" 
stimuli  are  often  described  as  lures  or  incentives,  suggesting  that 
they,  like  their  more  intense  noxious  counterparts,  may  also  func- 
tion as  motivational  variables.  Since  we  have  not  yet  considered 
this  problem  in  detail,  we  turn  now  to  the  question  of  whether 
and  under  what  conditions  approach-eliciting  stimulus  objects  do 
indeed  serve  as  motivational  variables  in  addition  to  fulfilling  their 
obvious  role  as  behavior  directors. 

The  large  majority  of  instances  in  which  appeals  have  been 
made  to  the  drive-arousing  functions  of  approach-evoking  cues 
are  to  be  found  in  studies  of  so-called  exploratory,  manipulatory, 
and  curiosity  behavior.  Investigators  responsible  for  such  studies 
have  typically  postulated  the  existence  of  special-purpose  drives 
that  are  named  in  terms  of  the  observed  behavior.  Thus,  explora- 
tory, manipulatory,  and  curiosity  drives  have  been  proposed  as 
explanatory  concepts.  And  in  most  instances  the  impression  is 
conveyed  that  the  external,  mild,  stimulus  objects  "pull"  the 
organism  toward  them,  exemplifying  a  motivating  property  that  is 
"attractive"  rather  than  "repellent."  Though  the  theoretical  im- 
plications and  formal  details  of  this  view  have  not  been  as  care- 
fully elaborated  as  might  be  desired,  the  general  conception  has 
proved  appealing  to  those  who  insist  that  behavior  is  motivated  as 
much  by  "positive"  goals  as  it  is  by  internal  disquietudes. 

Existing  studies  in  which  concepts  of  exteroceptively  aroused 
drives  have  been  invoked  may  be  roughly  divided  into  two  groups. 
First,  there  are  those  in  which  the  behavior-directing  goal  object 
has,  in  the  past,  either  functioned  repeatedly  as  a  reward  or  has 
been  closely  associated  with  reward.  In  these  studies,  whatever 
drive-arousing  properties  the  lure  may  possess  are  typically  attrib- 
uted to  learning.  In  the  second  group  of  experiments,  the  remote 
stimulus  object  is  either  completely  or  relatively  novel  to  the 
subject;  in  fact,  its  capacity  to  arouse  drive  is  said  to  be  contin- 
gent upon  its  novelty.  When  such  an  object  is  first  seen  by  the 
organism,  a  drive  of  "curiosity"  or  "exploration"  is  allegedly 
aroused.  This  new  drive  is  said  to  impel  the  individual  to  move 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  329 

toward,  and  to  touch,  smell,  manipulate,  or  inspect  the  object. 
In  the  one  case,  therefore,  drive  increments  are  aroused  by  highly 
familiar  objects  that  have  often  served  as,  or  have  been  associated 
with,  empirically  reinforcing  conditions;  and  in  the  other,  en- 
tirely unfamiliar  sources  of  stimulation  generate  special-purpose 
drives  to  explore  and/or  to  manipulate.  We  consider  each  of  these 
possibilities  in  turn. 

Incentive-aroused  Drive.  The  general  idea  that  an  event  such  as 
the  sight  of  familiar  food  may  heighten  one's  motivational  level  is 
by  no  means  recent,  but  relatively  precise,  systematic  formula- 
tions of  this  idea  appear  to  have  been  first  presented  by  Spence 
(195Itz)  and  by  Hull  (1951).  As  we  have  already  observed  (e.g., 
in  Chapter  5),  these  theorists  contend  that  appetitive  responses 
composing  the  final  eonsummatory  chain  become  classically  con- 
ditioned to  the  stimuli  provided  by  food  and  its  environs.  Through 
stimulus  generalization,  primarily,  certain  fractional  components 
of  the  eonsummatory  response  sequence  will  be  elicited  even 
when  the  animal  is  yet  some  distance  from  the  goal.  These  reac- 
tions (rgs)  are  thought  to  produce  a  drive  increment  (K)  which 
combines  additively  with  D  and  which,  like  D,  multiplies  all  as- 
sociative tendencies.  The  anticipatory  goal  reaction  (r^)  is  also 
said  to  produce  characteristic  interoceptive  stimuli  (s^s)  to  which 
a  variety  of  responses  (either  learned  or  unlearned)  may  be  asso- 
ciated. The  expectation  of  food  is  thus  seen  as  a  learned  tendency 
to  make  anticipatory,  partial  responses  of  the  kind  involved  in 
eating.  These  responses  can  affect  other  behavior  either  motiva- 
tionally  or  associatively  or  in  both  ways. 

Inasmuch  as  we  have  already  remarked  upon  the  relation  of  the 
rg-Sg  mechanism  to  the  general  problem  of  acquired  sources  of 
drive  and  to  such  conceptions  as  McClelland's  affective  arousal, 
only  a  few  additional  comments  need  be  made  here.  First,  propo- 
nents of  the  view  that  motivation  stems  from  external  sources  as 
well  as  from  bodily  disequilibria  have  largely  ignored  the  possibility 
that  the  rg-Sg-^K  mechanism  might  fulfill  some  of  their  needs. 
Harlow  (1953),  for  example,  in  a  paper  that  heartily  endorses  the 
importance  of  external  cues  as  sources  of  drive  makes  no  reference 
to  this  mechanism.  This  omission  may  be  due  to  his  desire  to  stress 
the  instinctive  aspects  of  the  process  as  well  as  to  a  conviction  that 


330  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

the  so-called  secondary  sources  of  drive  are  of  little  theoretical 
significance.  Second,  an  important  implication  of  the  Tg-Sg  concep- 
tion is  that  it  provides  a  means  whereby  the  organism's  level  of 
motivation  can  be  enhanced  while  the  goal  is  being  approached, 
even  though  the  lure  itself  remains  hidden  until  the  final  moment 
of  goal  attainment.  One  who  holds  that  external  stimuli  are  drive 
arousing  only  while  they  are  actually  impinging  upon  the  subject's 
distance  receptors  could  scarcely  maintain  that  invisible  lures  are 
motivating.  Third,  since  K,  the  D-like  factor,  is  the  result  of  con- 
ditioning, its  magnitude  can  be  relatively  independent  of  the  in- 
tensity of  the  conditioned  stimulus.  The  motivational  increment  is 
triggered,  as  it  were,  by  external  stimuli,  but  its  magnitude  is 
primarily  a  function  of  the  intensity  of  the  learned  internal  reac- 
tions (rgs)  rather  than  of  the  intensity  of  the  external  stimulus.  To 
the  extent  that  this  may  be  true,  these  instances  of  externally 
aroused  drive  reduce  in  the  final  analysis  to  internal  disquietudes 
that  may  be  similar  to  those  attending  hunger,  thirst,  and  emo- 
tionality. 

Novel  Stimuli  as  Sources  of  Drive.  The  view  that  unfamiliar 
stimulus  objects  are  approached,  explored,  and  manipulated  rests 
upon  a  variety  of  well-authenticated  observations.  Specifically,  it 
has  been  noted  that  rats  and  a  number  of  other  organisms,  includ- 
ing man,  will  move  toward  some,  though  by  no  means  all,  strange 
or  novel  objects.  Upon  arrival  the  organism  may  touch,  push,  pull, 
sniff  at,  manipulate,  mouth,  bite,  or  lick  the  previously  remote 
object.  Thus,  exploratory,  manipulatory,  and  curiosity  behavior 
consists  of  two  phases:  an  initial  phase  of  orienting  toward  and 
approaching  a  given  region  or  object,  and  a  secondary  phase  com- 
posed of  a  variety  of  nonlocomotor  reactions  that  appear  after  the 
novel  object  has  been  reached.  The  reaction  patterns  of  the  sec- 
ond phase  are  typically  described  as  "manipulatory,"  especially 
when  exhibited  by  monkeys  or  men  who  are  capable  of  com- 
plicated manual  acts.  To  the  degree  that  exploration-eliciting  ob- 
jects are  indeed  novel,  interpretations  based  on  learned,  object- 
specific,  anticipatory  responses  (e.g.,  rgS)  are  patently  inappro- 
priate. In  fact,  as  familiarity  with  the  novel  object  increases, 
exploration  declines.  Recourse  is  sometimes  had,  therefore,  to 
the  special-purpose  concepts  of  curiosity  or  exploratory  drives. 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  331 

Experimental  Studies  of  Exploratory  and  Manipulatory  Be- 
havior. The  rather  extensive  Hterature  descriptive  of  experiments 
on  exploration  and  manipulation  has  been  summarized  by  Glanzer 
(1958),  Butler  (1958),  Berlyne  (1958),  and  Dember  and  Fowler 
(1958).  Further  detailed  review  of  these  studies  cannot  be  under- 
taken here,  but  a  knowledge  of  some  of  their  principal  findings  is 
essential  to  a  further  discussion  of  theoretical  issues. 

Perhaps  the  most  general  statement  one  can  make  about  these 
experiments  is  that  in  a  wide  variety  of  situations  animals  often 
behave  so  as  to  reduce  contacts  with  familiar  stimuli  or  locales  and 
to  increase  contacts  with  novel  objects  or  regions.  As  an  example, 
when  rats  are  permitted  to  run  freely  through  a  simple  T  or  Y 
maze,  they  tend,  on  any  given  trial,  to  enter  a  different  arm  from 
that  chosen  on  the  preceding  trial.  As  a  result,  alternation  of  sides 
is  often  exhibited  on  successive  trials.  Apparently  this  is  not  a 
result  of  fatigue  or  inhibition  specific  to  a  particular  response,  since 
the  same  reaction,  e.g.,  right  turning,  will  be  repeated  if  the  stimuli 
are  changed  from  trial  to  trial  (Montgomery,  1952).  The  rat 
seems  to  get  tired  of  looking  at  the  same  environment,  not  tired 
of  making  the  same  response.  The  fact  that  percentage  alternation 
increases  when  rats  are  detained  in  the  goal  box  of  the  chosen 
T  maze  arm  (Glanzer,  1953),  supports  this  "stimulus  satiation" 
hypothesis,  especially  since  increases  in  intertrial  intervals  pro- 
duced by  detention  outside  the  maze  typically  reduce  alternation. 
Moreover,  response  alternation  is  observed  whether  food  is  pro- 
vided for  either  choice,  or  for  neither.  Also  related  to  the  alterna- 
tion phenomenon  is  the  finding  that  rats  are  more  likely  to  enter 
and  explore  a  compartment  if  it  contains  a  variety  of  objects 
such  as  wooden  blocks  than  if  it  contains  few  or  none  (Berlyne, 
1955). 

Not  only  do  animals  exhibit  preferences  for  new  as  opposed  to 
old  environments  and  sources  of  stimulation,  but  the  opportunity 
to  explore  new  situations  appears  to  have  rewarding  value  for  the 
learning  of  instrumental  responses.  Thus  Montgomery  (1954) 
reports  that  rats  will  learn  to  choose  the  arm  of  a  Y  maze  leading 
to  a  large  open  box  containing  numerous  rectangular  blocks  (the 
Dashiell  maze)  or,  for  the  same  reward,  will  learn  a  black- white 
discrimination    (Montgomery    and    Segall,    1955).    Myers    and 


332  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Miller  (1954),  moreover,  found  that  rats  would  learn  to  touch  a 
door  in  order  to  open  it  to  get  to  the  other  side  of  a  two-compart- 
ment box.  And  Kish  (1955),  among  others,  has  shown  that  rats 
will  learn  to  press  a  lever  if  the  act  is  followed  by  an  increase  in 
illumination. 

One  of  the  most  reliable  findings  of  experiments  on  exploration 
is  that  with  repeated  exposures  novel  objects  rather  quickly  lose 
their  power  to  elicit  approach  and  exploration.  When  periods  of 
rest  are  introduced  following  the  "extinction"  of  exploration,  a 
kind  of  "spontaneous  recovery"  takes  place,  though  recovery  is 
seldom  complete.  Moreover,  the  decrement  in  exploration  result- 
ing from  frequent  presentations  of  one  set  of  objects  or  situations 
generalizes  to  other  similar  objects  (Montgomery,  1953). 

The  most  dramatic  experiments  on  the  rewarding  properties  of 
visually  presented  stimuli  are  probably  those  of  Butler  (1953)  and 
of  Butler  and  Harlow  (1954).  In  these  investigations,  monkeys 
were  placed  one  at  a  time  in  a  dimly  lighted,  opaque-walled  box. 
Two  small  doors  were  situated  on  one  wall  of  the  box,  and  if  either 
of  these  was  unlatched,  the  monkey  could  push  it  open  and  look 
out  into  the  surrounding  monkey-laboratory  world.  When  the 
doors  were  painted  yellow  and  blue,  and  the  blue  door  was  always 
unlocked,  the  monkeys  learned  to  open  the  blue  door  and  ignore 
the  other,  the  only  apparent  reward  for  this  response  being  the 
opportunity  to  look  through  the  door  for  about  30  seconds.  This 
door-pushing  behavior  was  remarkably  persistent,  most  monkeys 
showing  a  willingness  to  perform  the  response  for  many  hours 
without  flagging  (Butler  and  Harlow,  1954).  Harlow  (1953)  has 
suggested  that  this  exemplifies  the  operation  of  a  "drive  to  ex- 
plore the  visual  world  outside  the  box"  and  that  the  opportunity  to 
do  so  is  reinforcing.  He  has  also  stated  that  this  is  an  instance  of 
the  arousal  of  a  drive  by  an  external  stimulus.  In  other  experiments 
Butler  (1957)  has  shown  that  the  frequency  of  door-pushing  re- 
sponses increases  with  hours  of  deprivation  of  visual  experience, 
and  that  auditory  stimuli  may  also  serve  as  incentives  and/or 
rewards. 

Manipulatory  activity  is  similar,  in  certain  respects,  to  the  kinds 
of  exploratory  behavior  we  have  just  been  considering.  If  sticks, 
mechanical  puzzles,  or  other  manipulatable  objects  are  presented 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  333 

to  a  monkey,  it  will  sooner  or  later  approach  and  handle  them.  If 
the  object  consists  of  several  separable  components,  the  monkev 
will  eventually  disassemble  it  and  in  this  way  "solve"  the  problem. 
Moreover,  as  with  visual  exploratory  actions,  these  disassembling 
reactions  can  be  elicited  over  and  over  again  (Harlow,  1953) .  Typi- 
cally, none  of  the  conventional  appetitive  or  social  rewards  is  ad- 
ministered following  a  successful  puzzle-disassembling  response, 
and  yet  proficiency  in  this  activity  may  increase  significantly  over 
trials.  The  persistence  of  the  behavior  and  its  improvement  with 
practice  are  considered  to  support  the  contentions  that  the  animal 
has  a  manipulatory  drive  and  is  rewarded  by  performing  manipula- 
tions. The  greater  perseveration  of  manipulatory  activities  in 
monkeys,  as  compared  with  exploratory  behavior  in  rats,  may  be 
ascribed  to  species  differences  or  perhaps  to  the  greater  reinforcing 
power  of  manual  manipulation  as  compared  with  mere  visual  in- 
spection. 

That  the  research  findings  are  not  always  as  consistent  as  the 
foregoing  experiments  might  suggest  is  indicated  by  reports  of  oc- 
casional failures  to  obtain  approach  and  exploration  with  respect 
to  strange  objects.  Young  chimpanzees,  for  instance,  do  not  look 
at  novel  objects  and  do  not  approach  and  explore  them  until  they 
have  been  exposed  to  such  objects  for  prolonged  periods  (Welker, 
1956).  Rats  also  resist  leaving  the  home  cage  in  order  to  explore 
an  elevated  runway  (Montgomery,  1955),  and  monkeys  will  not 
learn  to  open  a  door  to  look  out  at  a  large  dog  or  to  hear  recorded 
vocalizations  of  a  monkey  colony  whose  members  are  being 
molested  (Butler,  1958).  Some  stimuli,  therefore,  even  though  un- 
familiar, do  not  elicit  exploratory  behavior  or  function  as  rein- 
forcers  for  the  acquisition  of  new  responses.  In  some  experiments 
repeated  presentations  of  such  avoidance-eliciting  objects  are  ac- 
companied by  an  initial,  progressive  increase  in  exploration,  fol- 
lowed by  a  terminal  decline.  This  has  been  interpreted  to  mean 
that  exploration  increases  as  fear  is  extinguished,  with  exploration 
then  declining  in  the  usual  manner  as  stimulus  novelty  wears  off. 

Though  advocates  of  the  concepts  of  exploratory  and  curiosity 
drives  have  pressed  their  views  with  vigor  and  enthusiasm,  numer- 
ous problems  remain  to  be  solved  before  their  interpretations  can 
be  said  to  carry  complete  conviction.  For  one  thing,  the  conditions 


334  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

under  which  these  alleged  special  drives  are  aroused  have  not  been 
carefully  specified.  As  a  consequence,  one  cannot  be  certain  which 
bits  of  behavior  require  the  postulation  of  these  special-purpose 
drives  and  which  do  not.  The  topographical  properties  of  the 
so-called  exploratory  behaviors  and  of  other,  nonexploratory  activi- 
ties are  in  many  respects  identical.  For  example,  if  a  rat  moves 
from  one  end  of  a  box  to  the  other,  one  has  no  way  of  knowing, 
from  the  behavior  alone,  whether  the  rat  is  motivated  by  the 
sight  of  the  other  end  of  the  box,  by  dissatisfaction  with  the  end 
where  he  is,  or  simply  by  a  tendency  to  become  active.  Moreover, 
as  Berlyne  (1958)  has  pointed  out,  a  specific  behavior  pattern  may 
be  scored  as  exploratory  if  it  is  exhibited  in  one  part  of  the  test 
apparatus  but  not  if  it  appears  in  another.  If  a  rat  runs  down  an 
alley  and  sniffs  at  an  object  at  the  end,  he  is  usually  said  to  be 
exploring,  but  if  he  stays  in  the  starting  compartment  and  sniffs  at 
the  walls,  he  is  not  exploring  (by  the  usual  criteria)  since  he  hasn't 
gone  anywhere. 

Most  frequently  the  label  "exploratory"  is  applied  when  an 
animal  does  something  in  a  situation  where  he  receives  no  obvious 
reward  for  his  performance.  But  the  presence  or  absence  of  an  ex- 
ploratory drive  is  not  announced  until  after  the  behavior  has  been 
observed  to  occur.  If  a  strange  object  is  approached,  curiosity  drive 
is  invoked;  but  if  the  same  object  is  not  approached,  the  existence 
of  a  fear  drive  is  asserted.  Thus  the  presence  of  a  drive  to  explore 
is  sometimes  inferred  from,  and  at  the  same  time  used  to  explain, 
behavior  of  moving  from  one  place  to  another,  especially  if  there 
is  no  other  apparent  reason  for  the  movement.  The  postulation  of 
an  exploratory  drive  in  this  way  is  quite  circular,  and  therefore  of 
questionable  worth  as  a  scientific  explanation.  Not  all  assertions 
concerning  the  presence  of  exploratory  or  curiosity  drives  are  as 
clearly  circular  as  this,  but  the  problem  has  not  been  squarely 
faced  nor  adequately  solved. 

Another  difficulty  arises  when  one  attempts  to  define  stimulus 
novelty.  Is  a  block  of  wood  a  novel  object  for  the  rat?  If  so,  how 
novel?  Probably  if  a  rat  has  been  raised  in  the  usual  way  in  the 
laboratory,  it  has  seen  other  objects  resembling,  to  a  greater  or 
less  degree,  a  block  of  wood.  Pellets  of  laboratory  chow  are  often 
fashioned  in  rectangular  form,  and  their  color  is  similar  to  that  of 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  335 

natural  wood.  So  when  a  rat  approaches  and  sniffs  at  a  small  block 
of  wood  in  a  maze,  how  can  we  be  certain  that  this  is  not  an 
instance  of  transfer  of  training,  mediated  by  stimulus  similarity?  If 
so,  need  we  worry  either  about  stimulus  novelty  or  about  the 
curiosity  drive  that  novelty  is  alleged  to  arouse?  As  with  explora- 
tory drive,  the  specification  of  stimulus  novelty  rests,  to  an  unsatis- 
factory degree,  upon  the  observation  that  the  expected  behavior 
has  indeed  occurred.  Novel  objects  are  supposed  to  arouse  a  drive 
to  explore  such  objects,  but  degree  of  novelty  is  typically  not 
evaluated  independently  of  exploration. 

Of  extant  theories  of  exploratory  and  curiosity  behavior,  Ber- 
lyne's  (1955)  is  probably  the  most  carefully  and  precisely  struc- 
tured. According  to  this  theory,  which  in  its  formal  properties 
resembles  the  Hull-Spence  r^-Sg  formulation,  when  novel  stimuli 
fall  upon  an  organism's  receptors,  a  drive-stimulus-producing  re- 
sponse labeled  "curiosity"  will  be  evoked.  The  "drive-to-explore" 
or  the  drive  of  "perceptual  curiosity"  acts,  apparently,  to  facilitate 
behavior  of  exploring  the  objects  that  generate  the  response-pro- 
duced drive.  Exploratory  activities  reduce  the  drive  to  explore,  and 
when  this  occurs  following  a  response,  that  response  will  tend  to 
be  learned.  In  addition  to  functioning  as  a  reinforcing  agent,  ex- 
posures to  novel  stimuli  through  exploratory  activities,  bring  about 
a  weakening  of  the  curiosity  drive.  According  to  Berlyne,  the  proc- 
ess of  curiosity  diminution  can  be  described  by  Hull's  model  for 
the  extinction  of  conditioned  responses,  a  model  in  which  perma- 
nent decrements  are  explained  by  the  concept  of  conditioned  in- 
hibition and  temporary  diminutions  by  reactive  inhibition. 

Because  of  the  similarity  of  this  conception  to  the  Ty-Sy  expect- 
ancy mechanism,  it  is  of  interest  to  compare  the  two  in  more  de- 
tail. First,  whereas  the  Tg-Sg  configuration  clearly  refers  to  a  learned 
reaction,  the  drive-producing  curiosity  response  must  be  instinc- 
tive, since  only  novel  stimuli  can  arouse  curiosity,  and  only  objects 
that  the  organism  has  never  seen  are  really  novel.  Second,  although 
expectancy-produced  drive  becomes  stronger  as  a  function  of  the 
number  of  encounters  with  a  rewarding  object,  curiosity  drive  is 
weakened  by  the  same  variable.  Repeated  experiences  with  food 
that  is  assumed  to  be  drive  reducing  strengthen  the  expectancy 
mechanism;  but  repeated  exposures  to  a  novel  stimulus,  which  in 


336  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

a  comparable  manner  reduces  the  curiosity  drive,  weaken  the  power 
of  the  stimulus  to  arouse  the  drive.  Conversely,  anticipatory  goal 
responses  are  extinguished  when  the  rewarding  object  is  omitted, 
while  curiosity  is  extinguished  when  the  rewarding  object  is  kept 
in  the  situation. 

Although  Berlyne  has  tried  to  cast  his  views  into  a  form  consist- 
ent with  Hullian  theory  and  to  extend  it  into  the  general  area  of 
perception,  his  usage  of  the  term  drive  is  not  coordinate  with 
Hull's.  Berlyne's  curiosity  drive  is  apparently  a  drive  to  perform  a 
specific  act  or  a  specific  group  of  acts.  Conceived  in  this  manner, 
it  is  a  special-purpose  drive  incorporating  directive  properties,  and 
is  therefore  not  the  same  as  Hull's  general  D.  Perhaps  Berlyne 
adopted  this  position  because  one  cannot  explain  why  a  subject  ap- 
proaches a  novel  object  instead  of  doing  something  else,  if  one 
assumes  that  the  sight  of  the  object  leads  only  to  heightened  D. 
An  increase  in  D  does  not  activate  or  multiply  approach  tendencies 
alone,  and  reactions  of  exploring  and  manipulating  would  not  be 
facilitated  by  intensified  D  unless  these  responses  were,  for  other 
reasons,  the  dominant  members  of  the  response  hierarchy.  Never- 
theless, in  the  typical  exploratory  situation,  approaching  may  often 
be  the  dominant  response.  An  animal,  when  placed  into  a  maze 
at  the  starting  point,  obviously  cannot  back  up.  If  he  moves  at  all 
it  must  be  away  from  his  initial  position  and  therefore  toward  the 
remotely  located,  to-be-explored  objects. 

Another  account  of  exploratory  behavior  requiring  analysis  is 
that  proposed  by  Butler  and  Harlow  in  conjunction  with  their 
experiments  on  the  "visual-exploration  drive."  According  to  these 
writers,  visual  exploratory  responses  are  members  of  a  broad  family 
of  curiosity  or  exploratory  drives  (including  manipulatory  drives) 
that  are  elicited  by  external  stimuli.  This  interpretation  has  been 
suggested  as  an  explanation  of  the  behavior  of  the  monkeys  who 
learned  new  discriminatory  reactions  for  visual  rewards. 

That  this  view  leads  to  difficulties  should  be  clear  from  the 
following:  If  the  act  of  looking  out  of  the  window  at  the  outside 
(laboratory)  world  is  the  specific  event  that  arouses  the  visual-ex- 
ploration drive,  then  the  monkeys  do  not  have  this  drive  until  they 
have  succeeded  in  opening  the  correct  window.  The  drive  aroused 
by  the  final  act  of  visual  exploration  cannot,  therefore,  provide 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  337 

the  impetus  for  the  response  of  window  opening.  External  stimuh, 
when  seen,  may  indeed  incite  a  drive  to  explore  with  the  eyes,  but 
it  is  illogical  to  say  that  those  stimuli,  while  they  are  invisible  to 
the  monkey,  actively  function  to  arouse  the  drive  to  work  in 
order  to  see. 

But  the  panel-pushing  and  latch-manipulating  activities  of 
Butler's  monkeys  were  presumably  motivated  in  some  way,  and 
the  motivating  agency  must  have  been  functioning  prior  to  the 
time  the  monkeys  obtained  their  visual  rewards.  Several  possibil- 
ities suggest  themselves.  For  one,  being  unable  to  see  may  be  the 
crucial  variable.  This  possibility  is  supported  by  Butler's  study 
(1957),  in  which  visual  exploratory  responses  were  found  to  in- 
crease in  frequency  as  a  function  of  the  amount  of  visual  depriva- 
tion. Or  since,  in  the  typical  experimental  setup,  auditory  stimuli 
are  not  excluded,  and  the  confined  monkey  can  hear  the  sounds 
produced  by  other  members  of  the  colony  and  by  numerous  people 
in  the  laboratory,  these  noises  could  serve  as  drive-producing  in- 
centive stimuli.  Still  another  view  is  that  confinement  in  an  opaque 
box  is  a  mild  anxiety-inducing  variable  for  the  monkey  (Brown, 
1953Z)).  When  coupled  with  the  auditory  cues,  this  might  be 
sufficiently  motivating  to  explain  the  observed  behavior.  And 
finally,  it  might  even  be  supposed  that  if  seeing  is  rewarding,  for 
whatever  reasons,  then  eye  movements  and  other  components  of 
the  sequence  of  looking  responses  could  become  conditioned  to 
environmental  stimuli  in  much  the  same  way  as  consummatory 
responses.  Were  this  the  case,  then  generalized,  fractional,  anticipa- 
tory seeing  responses  (rg-Sg)  might  be  elicited  in  visually  restrictive 
environments  and,  like  the  analogous  rg-Sg  mechanism,  might  add 
an  increment  to  drive.  Perhaps  in  this  way  one  could  speak  more 
precisely  of  the  motivating  properties  of  the  "expectation  of  see- 
ing." 

Harlow  (1953)  has  maintained  that  exploratory  and  manipula- 
tory activities  weigh  strongly  against  a  drive-reduction  theory  of 
reinforcement,  since  these  actions  do  not  produce  immediate 
diminutions  in  any  of  the  primary  physiological  needs.  There  is 
no  existing  experiment,  however,  in  which  the  possibility  that 
some  kind  of  drive  reduction  has  occurred  has  been  completely 
ruled  out.  Thus  if  a  monkey  becomes  anxious  when  confined  in  a 


338  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

dimly  lighted  box,  a  reinforcing  reduction  in  anxiety  may  occur 
when  it  gets  a  chance  to  see  other  monke^^s  and/or  the  familiar 
laboratory  environment.  Supporting  this  view  are  the  previously 
cited  observations  that  monkeys  will  not  learn  responses  that  are 
followed  by  such  stimuli  as  the  sight  of  a  large  dog  or  the  sounds 
of  other  monkeys  being  molested  (Butler,  1958).  It  is  also  ap- 
parent, in  this  connection,  that  if  a  confined  monkey  has  a  drive 
to  see,  as  Harlow  asserts,  then  the  act  of  seeing  must  reduce  this 
drive.  One  might  thus  be  led,  oddly  enough,  to  a  drive-reduction 
theory,  albeit  not  a  need-reduction  theory,  of  the  reinforcing  effects 
of  visual  exploration.  On  these  grounds  the  external  stimulus  be- 
comes a  drive-to-see  reducer,  not  a  drive-to-see  arouser.  Incidentally, 
Berlyne  holds  that  external  cues  play  both  of  these  roles,  arousing 
a  drive  when  first  seen  and  reducing  that  drive  with  further  see- 
ing. 

It  seems  justifiable  to  conclude  from  this  analysis  that  while 
animals  do  indeed  engage  in  activities  of  approaching  and  explor- 
ing biologically  neutral  objects,  it  is  far  from  certain  that  a  special- 
purpose  exploratory  drive  need  be  invoked  to  explain  such  activi- 
ties. Moreover,  though  monkeys  and  other  animals  do  learn  new 
responses  for  rewards  of  visual  stimulation,  the  nature  of  the  mo- 
tivation underlying  the  evocation  of  these  responses  remains  un- 
clear. Before  the  visually  rewarding  events  are  seen,  motivational 
processes  other  than  those  aroused  by  to-be-seen  stimuli  must  be  in 
operation.  Apprehension  due  to  isolation  and  confinement,  an- 
ticipation of  seeing,  or  auditory  stimuli  may  serve  in  this  role  as 
motivators.  Lastly,  although  there  are  many  reports  of  instances 
in  which  animals  will  learn  to  solve  a  T  maze  or  a  discrimination 
problem  for  an  exploratory  reward,  alternative  explanations  have 
seldom  been  carefully  ruled  out.  Thus  the  presentation  of  novel, 
reinforcing  stimuli  has  typically  been  confounded  with  an  increase 
in  space  (cf.  Montgomery,  1954),  and  hence  the  reinforcement 
may  have  been  provided  by  escape  from  confinement  or  by  the 
opportunity  to  run,  which  is  known  to  be  reinforcing  (Kagan  and 
Berkun,  1954),  rather  than  by  the  sight  of  unfamiliar  objects. 
Experimenters  such  as  Chapman  and  Levy  (1957)  have  con- 
sidered this  problem  and  have  concluded  that  novelty  may  be 
reinforcing  even  when  increased  space  is  controlled,  although  the 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  339 

effect  disappears  when  tlie  animals  are  made  hungry.  Consider- 
able research  remains  to  be  done,  therefore,  before  we  can  be 
entirely  certain  that  novel  stimuli  per  se  are  reinforcing  and  that 
no  negative  factors  such  as  confinement,  anxiety,  or  stimulus 
deprivation  are  also  involved.  Nearly  all  currently  available  studies 
can  be  interpreted  as  supporting  either  the  hypothesis  that  the 
animals  are  tired  of  looking  at  one  portion  of  their  world  (stimulus 
satiation)  and  hence  are  relieved  to  get  out,  or  that  they  are 
excited  and  pleased  (curiosity  drive)  to  see  something  new. 

On  the  Conditioning  of  Emotional   Responses 

As  we  have  noted,  principally  in  Chapter  5,  there  is  reason  to 
suppose  that  fears  and  other  emotional  reactions  can  become  as- 
sociated, through  learning,  with  biologically  neutral  stimuli  and 
may  thereby  come  to  serve  as  acquired  sources  of  drive.  But  the 
problem  of  how  such  emotional  responses  are  learned  has  been 
postponed  to  the  present  chapter.  Since  most  of  the  written  mate- 
rial on  this  topic  deals  with  the  learning  of  fear,  we  shall  restrict 
our  discussion  to  this  emotion,  omitting  the  problem  of  whether 
positive  affective  responses  are  acquired  by  processes  other  than 
those  involved  in  fear  conditioning. 

Theories  of  Fear  Conditioning.  Theorists  who  have  concerned 
themselves  with  the  question  of  how  emotional  reactions  are 
learned  may  be  divided  into  two  broad  groups  on  the  basis  of  the 
answers  they  have  suggested.  One  group  consists  of  those  who  hold 
that  the  acquisition  of  conditioned  emotional  responses  is  gov- 
erned by  the  same  processes  that  control  the  learning  of  nonemo- 
tional  responses.  The  members  of  the  second  group  maintain  that 
different  processes  control  the  learning  of  the  two  kinds  of  reac- 
tions. The  members  of  both  groups,  however,  disagree  among 
themselves  as  to  which  mechanisms  should  be  assigned  positions 
of  central  importance. 

Probably  the  best-known  members  of  the  first  group  are  Guthrie 
(1935)  and  Hull  (1943,  1951,  1952).  According  to  Guthrie,  an 
association  is  formed  between  a  stimulus  and  a  response,  whether 
the  response  is  a  skeletal  movement  or  an  internal  emotional  activ- 
ity, whenever  the  response  occurs  in  the  presence  of  the  stimulus. 


340  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

The  mere  contiguity,  or  the  occurrence  together  in  time,  of  stimulus 
and  response  is  sufficient  to  produce  the  associative  bonding  that  is 
the  essence  of  learning.  For  Hull  also,  stimuli  and  responses  must 
be  contiguous  if  stimuli  are  to  acquire  tendencies  to  elicit  reac- 
tions. But  in  addition  to  contiguity,  a  reduction  in  drive  following 
the  elicitation  of  the  response  is  regarded  by  Hull  as  an  essential 
condition  for  the  formation  of  associations.  During  the  condition- 
ing of  fear,  the  noxious  UCS  is  assumed  to  serve  as  a  primary 
source  of  drive,  and  its  termination,  therefore,  constitutes  a  reduc- 
tion in  drive.  Both  Hull  and  Guthrie  thus  agree  that  contiguity 
is  a  necessary  condition  for  the  growth  of  associations.  They  dis- 
agree in  that  Hull  considers  drive  reduction  to  be  an  additional 
necessary  condition,  whereas  Guthrie  does  not.  As  members  of  the 
"same-processes"  group,  these  theorists  believe  that  the  learning 
both  of  emotional  and  nonemotional  responses  can  be  explained 
in  terms  of  one  set  of  principles. 

Notable  members  of  the  second,  or  "different-processes,"  group 
are  Schlosberg  (1937),  Skinner  (1938),  and  Mowrer  (1947).  For 
Mowrer,  whose  views  we  have  chosen  to  examine  in  detail,  S-R 
contiguity  is  both  the  necessary  and  the  sufficient  condition  for 
the  learning  of  emotional  responses.  Instrumental  reactions  in- 
volving skeletal  muscles  are  not  learned,  however,  unless  a  reduc- 
tion in  drive  follows  such  acts.  The  fear-conditioning  aspect  of 
Mowrer's  interpretation,  which  in  general  closely  resembles  the 
views  of  Schlosberg  and  Skinner,  is  thus  seen  to  be  essentially 
Guthrian,  whereas  Mowrer's  position  with  respect  to  instrumental 
learning  is  identical  with  Hull's.  Although  Spence  (1956)  has  not 
seriously  concerned  himself  with  this  problem,  he  has  tentatively 
proposed  a  different-process  theory  that  is  the  exact  opposite 
of  Mowrer's.  According  to  Spence,  instrumental  actions  are  per- 
haps learned  through  the  operation  of  contiguity  alone,  whereas 
the  acquisition  of  autonomically  controlled  reactions  may  rest 
upon  the  occurrence  of  drive  reduction  in  addition  to  contiguity. 

Apparently,  then,  learning  theorists,  at  least  those  who  regard 
learning  as  involving  associations  between  responses  and  stimuli, 
concur  in  the  belief  that  contiguity  is  an  indispensable  condition 
for  the  acquisition  of  emotional  reactions.  They  do  not  agree,  how- 
ever, as  to  whether  additional  variables,  particularly  those  upon 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  341 

which  the  immediacy  or  completeness  of  drive  reduction  might 
depend,  are  also  necessary.  Thus  the  issue  is  reduced  to  this  basic 
question:  What  empirical  variables  determine  the  conditioning 
of  emotional  responses? 

Those  who,  like  Mowrer,  hold  to  a  strict  contiguity  view  of  emo- 
tional conditioning  would  probably  maintain  that  the  following 
experimental  variables  are  of  primary  importance  for  the  growth  of 
emotional  associative  strengths:  (1)  the  interval  between  the 
onset  of  the  CS  and  the  onset  of  the  UCS  (degree  of  contiguity); 
(2)  the  intensities  of  the  CS  and  the  UCS;  and  (3)  the  frequency 
and  recency  of  S-R  pairings.  Presumably,  any  variable  that  might 
affect  the  time  of  occurence,  or  the  abruptness  or  the  complete- 
ness of  the  drive-reduction  process  would  be  rejected  as  of  no  sig- 
nificance for  emotional  conditioning.  One  such  variable  is  UCS 
duration.  If  drive  reduction  occurs  when  the  UCS  is  terminated 
and  if  drive  reduction  is  reinforcing,  then  the  more  protracted 
the  UCS  the  greater  the  delay  of  reinforcement.  From  the  view- 
point of  a  contiguity  theorist,  however,  varying  the  interval  be- 
tween the  emotional  response  and  a  reduction  in  the  drive,  other 
things  constant,  should  have  no  effect  upon  the  strength  of  the 
conditioned  emotional  associative  tendency. 

Theorists  who  do  not  hold  that  mere  contiguity  is  a  sufficient 
condition  for  the  formation  of  emotional  associations  would 
nevertheless  grant  the  importance  of  the  above  variables  of  con- 
tiguity, stimulus  intensity,  frequency,  and  recency.  But  in  addition 
they  would  maintain  that  variables  such  as  UCS  duration,  which 
might  affect  the  drive-reduction  process,  should  not  be  dismissed 
until  careful  experiments  have  shown  them  to  be  irrelevant  or  in- 
significant. 

If  isolating  significant  variables  lies  at  the  heart  of  the  problem 
of  emotional  conditioning,  then  it  would  appear  that  definitive 
answers  could  be  obtained  from  straightforward  experimental  in- 
vestigations. But  such  inquiries  could  provide  us  with  a  complete 
list  of  relevant  variables  without  resolving  the  issue.  Those  con- 
cerned with  this  problem  might  agree  on  a  group  of  variables  and 
yet  disagree  as  to  the  nature  of  the  mechanisms  activated  by  those 
variables.  For  example,  the  time  at  which  an  electric  shock  is 
terminated  might  be  shown  to  affect  emotional  conditioning,  but 


342  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

the  question  could  still  be  raised  as  to  whether  drive  reduction  does 
or  does  not  accompany  shock  termination.  Perhaps  for  the 
masochist,  shock  cessation  is  drive  arousing  rather  than  drive  re- 
ducing. Similarly,  an  increase  in  the  duration  of  an  electric  shock 
may  result  in  augmented  pain,  or,  if  adaptation  occurs,  in  dimin- 
ished pain.  And  the  variable  of  degree  of  S-R  contiguity  may  affect 
learning  through  any  one  of  a  variety  of  mechanisms  of  which  we 
know  nothing  as  yet. 

Mowrer,  for  example,  made  no  distinction  between  empirical 
variables  and  the  hypothetical  mechanisms  underlying  those  vari- 
ables. Consequently,  in  rejecting  the  assumption  that  the  mech- 
anism of  drive  reduction  was  necessary  for  emotional  conditioning, 
he  also  rejected  all  of  the  empirical  variables  on  which  drive  reduc- 
tion might  depend.  This  he  need  not  have  done.  Like  Guthrie,  he 
could  have  maintained  that  certain  of  the  "law-of-effect"  or  drive- 
reduction  variables  influence  the  strength  of  an  emotional  response 
by  protecting  associations  from  unlearning  rather  than  by  strength- 
ening them  in  the  first  place.  By  this  stratagem  Mowrer  could  have 
retained  any  of  the  empirical  drive-reduction  variables  while  reject- 
ing the  drive-reduction  mechanism. 

Illustrative  Investigations.  Concerning  experimental  attempts 
to  determine  whether  contiguity  alone  is  sufficient  for  the  learn- 
ing of  fear  reactions,  none  has  thus  far  yielded  unambiguous  re- 
sults. This  is  a  difficult  field,  however,  in  which  to  design  crucial 
experiments,  since  none  of  the  alternative  hypotheses  has  been 
stated  with  sufficient  precision  to  make  exact  tests  possible. 

To  illustrate  the  vexing  nature  of  the  problem,  let  us  examine 
the  procedures  used  in  studies  purporting  to  bear  on  the  issue. 
One  of  the  experimental  designs  often  used  to  evaluate  the  rela- 
tive merits  of  the  contiguity-alone  versus  the  contiguity-plus-drive- 
reduction  conceptions  is  shown  in  Fig.  9:1.  Here  it  will  be  seen 
that  the  classical  aversive  conditioning  procedures  used  with  the 
two  groups  are  identical  in  all  respects  save  that  the  duration  of 
the  UCS  is  longer  in  the  case  of  group  II  than  in  the  case  of  group 
I.  That  is  to  say,  the  CSs  are  identical,  and  the  contiguity  variable 
is  also  presumably  identical,  since,  with  the  CS-UCS  intervals 
equal,  the  time  between  the  CS  and  the  unconditioned  response 
must  also  be  the  same  for  the  two  groups. 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  343 

Now  on  a  drive-reduction  hypothesis  it  might  be  predicted  that 
the  members  of  group  I  would  show  more  fear  conditioning  than 
the  members  of  group  II  because  the  drive-reducing  event  (shock 
cessation)  occurs  more  immediately  in  group  I  than  in  group  II. 
The  assumption  that  associative  strength  varies  inversely  with  delay 
of  reinforcement  is,  of  course,  also  involved  in  this  prediction. 
Thus,  if  it  can  be  shown  that  a  short-shock  group  is  no  more 
fearful  than  a  long-shock  group,  this  evidence  would  weigh 
against  Hull's  delay-of-reinforcement  hypothesis  and  against  the 
drive-reduction  view.  But  this  conclusion  would  be  justified  only  if 
one  could  be  sure  that  the  delay-of-reinforcement  variable  had  not 
been  overridden  by  other  factors.  One  such  factor  is  shock  in- 
tensity. Thus,  if  shock  duration  is  permitted  to  vary  while  delay- 
of-reinforcement  is  being  manipulated,  this  variation  may  lead 
to  changes  in  effective  shock  strength.  As  common  sense  would 
seem  to  suggest,  a  CS  that  signals  the  coming  of  a  long  shock 
might  well  arouse  more  fear  than  one  that  is  premonitory  of  brief 
shock  (cf.  Miller  and  Dollard,  1941,  p.  58).  Perhaps  the  uncon- 
ditioned pain  is  more  intense  with  long  shock,  even  with  physical 
intensity  held  constant,  or  the  drive  reduction  occasioned  by  the 
cessation  of  a  longer  shock  may  be  greater  than  that  following  the 
offset  of  brief  shock.  If  a  short-shock  group  shows  more  condi- 
tioned fear  than  a  long-shock  group,  the  drive-reduction  theorist 
may  feel  encouraged.  But  his  theory  is  not  refuted  even  if  a  sig- 
nificant difference  in  the  reverse  direction  is  obtained.  If  long 


On Off 

CS  I  I 


GROUP  On Off 

I  l/CS- Shock  I        I 


On Off 

CS  I  I 


GROUP  On Off 

n  UCS-ShocW  I 


Time 


Fig.  9:1.  A  schematic  representation  of  an  experimental  arrangement  com- 
monly used  to  determine  whether  the  strength  of  a  classically  conditioned 
response  varies  with  the  duration  of  the  UCS. 


344  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

shock  leads  to  more  fear  than  short  shock,  this  effect  may  mean 
that  events  associated  with  the  termination  of  shock  are  affecting 
the  process  of  emotional  conditioning.  And  if  they  are,  then  fear 
conditioning  may  be  a  function  of  other  variables  than  the  mere 
contiguity  of  the  CS  and  the  unconditioned  response. 

Experimental  studies  employing  designs  much  like  that  in  Fig. 
9:1  have  been  reported  by  Sullivan  (1950),  Bitterman,  Reed,  and 
Krauskopf  (1952),  Mowrer  and  Solomon  (1954),  and  Zeaman  and 
Wegner  (1954).  Sullivan's  experiment,  involving  the  conditioning 
of  the  GSR  in  human  subjects,  with  short  and  long  intense  audi- 
tory stimuli  as  UCSs,  provided  suggestive  but  not  conclusive 
evidence  that  the  short-duration  stimulus  was  more  effective  in 
producing  conditioned  GSRs.  Bitterman  et  al.  attempted  to  condi- 
tion GSRs  by  means  of  short  and  long  shocks.  While  the  long- 
shock  procedure  tended  to  yield  responses  of  larger  amplitude  than 
the  short  shock,  the  differences  fell  far  short  of  statistical  signifi- 
cance. Unfortunately,  the  subjects  in  this  study  served  as  their 
own  controls,  the  short  shock  being  paired  with  the  lighting  of 
one  15-watt  lamp  on  one  half  of  the  16  trials  and  the  long  shock 
being  paired  with  the  lighting  of  an  identical  lamp  on  the  other 
half  of  the  trials.  Hence,  the  failure  to  obtain  differences  in  either 
direction,  in  spite  of  the  fact  that  all  subjects  whose  records  were 
used  said  they  knew  one  light  was  followed  by  long  and  the  other 
by  short  shock,  is  not  surprising.  In  the  Mowrer-Solomon  experi- 
ment, rats  given  fear-conditioning  training  with  10-second  shock 
showed  some  indication  (10  per  cent  level  of  confidence)  of  being 
more  fearful  than  rats  for  whom  the  shock  duration  was  only  3 
seconds.  On  the  basis  of  this  evidence  Mowrer  and  Solomon  sug- 
gest that  if  the  short  shock  had  been  as  brief  as  0.5  second,  "... 
it  is  virtually  certain  that  it  would  be  reliably  less  effective  in 
producing  fear  than  would  a  shock  of  long  duration"  (p.  21).  This 
is  consistent  with  the  intuitive  expectation  that  cues  denoting  the 
coming  of  a  short  shock  should  be  less  fear  arousing  than  cues 
that  forewarn  of  long  shock.  Nevertheless,  Mowrer  and  Solomon 
still  maintain  that  these  results  support  their  views  that  the  events 
attending  the  termination  of  a  UCS  have  no  effect  upon  fear  learn- 
ing. This  conclusion  is  puzzling,  since  if  one  group  does  exhibit 
more  fear  than  the  other,  with  S-R  contiguity  equated,  then,  con- 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  345 

trary  to  Mowrer's  interpretation,  contiguity  is  not  the  whole  story. 
If  genuine  differences  in  fear  can  be  produced  by  the  use  of  long 
and  short  shocks,  then  the  variable  of  UCS  duration,  involving  as 
it  does  the  time  at  which  the  noxious  stimulus  goes  off,  may  in- 
deed have  something  to  do  with  fear  learning. 

Zeaman  and  Wegner,  in  a  study  of  conditioned  cardiac  re- 
sponses, have  found  that  a  relatively  short  shock  of  2  seconds  dura- 
tion leads  to  conditioned  acceleration  during  the  CS-UCS  interval. 
With  a  6-second  shock,  however,  the  conditioned  response  is  a 
deceleration  in  heart  rate.  This  difference  in  the  form  of  the  con- 
ditioned responses  is  ascribed  to  the  fact  that  the  heart  is  accelerat- 
ing at  the  time  of  shock  reduction  in  the  short-shock  condition, 
but  is  decelerating  at  the  time  the  long  shock  terminates.  The 
authors  interpret  their  results  as  supporting  the  view  that  drive 
reduction  is  the  mechanism  of  conditioning  in  the  case  of  this 
autonomically  mediated  response. 

In  connection  with  designs  of  the  type  illustrated  in  Fig.  9:1,  it 
should  be  noted  that,  with  the  exception  of  Sullivan's  experiment, 
apparently  none  of  the  investigations  has  been  conducted  with  an 
optimal  CS-UCS  interval.  The  work  of  White  and  Schlosberg 
(1952)  and  of  Moeller  (1954)  indicates  that  a  CS-UCS  interval 
of  about  0.5  second  yields  optimal  GSR  conditioning.  In  the  study 
of  Bitterman  et  al.,  this  interval  was  set  at  5  seconds.  According 
to  White  and  Schlosberg,  this  should  yield  no  conditioning  at  all, 
and  some  question  can  be  raised  whether  in  fact  Bitterman  et  al. 
did  indeed  obtain  conditioned  responses,  since  their  design  in- 
cluded no  controls  for  pseudoconditioning.  It  may  also  be  ob- 
served, as  Miller  (1951)  has  pointed  out,  that  it  is  not  always  cer- 
tain, when  shock  duration  is  being  varied  in  animal  experiments, 
that  drive  reduction  occurs  only  at  the  instant  when  the  experi- 
menter terminates  the  shock.  If  an  animal  is  free  to  move  about  on 
an  electrified  grid,  the  shock  may  actually  be  intermittent,  for  the 
rat  can  momentarily  escape  shock  by  leaping  and  running.  This 
could  mean  that  a  long  shock,  in  effect,  is  a  series  of  short  shocks 
involving  multiple  drive  reductions  and  reinforcements.  In  rat 
experiments  some  control  over  this  factor  has  been  provided  by 
the  use  of  shock  compartments  with  low  ceilings,  but  so  long  as 
the  animals  are  free  to  move  and  the  shock  electrodes  are  not  fixed 


346  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

to  the  animal,  the  control  may  be  less  than  perfect.  In  any  event, 
very  carefully  designed  and  well-controlled  experiments  will  be 
needed  before  we  can  be  sure  that  long  shocks  do  not  produce  a 
degree  of  fear  different  from  that  produced  by  short  shocks,  and 
that  delay  of  reinforcement  is  not  a  significant  factor. 

An  investigation  by  Mowrer  and  Aiken  (1954)  provides  an  addi- 
tional example  of  problems  attending  the  design  of  crucial  experi- 
ments on  the  contiguity-alone  versus  the  contiguity-plus-drive- 
reduction  views.  Figure  9:2  shows  the  various  fear-conditioning 
procedures  used  by  Mowrer  and  Aiken.  As  this  figure  indicates, 
UCS  duration  was  the  same  for  all  groups,  but  the  position  of  the 
CS  with  respect  to  the  UCS  was  varied  progressively  from  group 
I  through  group  IV.  In  a  fifth  group,  not  shown  in  the  figure,  the 
CS  was  withheld  until  two  minutes  after  the  UCS  terminated. 

In  explaining  this  experimental  design,  Mowrer  and  Aiken  state 
that  according  to  Hull,  the  nearer  the  CS  is  in  time  to  the  termina- 
tion of  the  UCS,  the  greater  should  be  the  capacity  of  the  CS  to 


CS 


GROUP 

I  UCS 


CS 


GROUP 

n  UCS 


CS 


GROUP 

m  UCS 


CS \ L_ 


GROUP 

IV  UCS 


Time 


Fig.  9:2.  Four  different  experimental  paradigms  used  in  an  experiment  de- 
signed to  evaluate  the  relative  merits  of  the  contiguity-alone  versus  the 
contiguity-plus-drive-reduction  views  of  emotional  conditioning.  {Adapted 
from  Mowrer  and  Aiken,  J 954.) 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  347 

evoke  fear.  The  alleged  expectation  from  Hull's  views,  therefore,  is 
that  fear  should  be  conditioned  more  strongly  in  group  III,  say, 
than  in  group  I.  Unfortunately,  this  is  a  misinterpretation  of  Hull's 
position,  since  for  him  the  interval  of  importance  for  fear  con- 
ditioning is  not  the  time  between  the  CS  and  the  offset  of  the 
UCS.  Rather,  Hull  holds  that  the  significant  intervals  are  ( 1 )  that 
between  the  CS  and  the  response,  and  (2)  that  between  the  re- 
sponse and  the  reinforcing  state  of  affairs.  In  the  Mowrer-Aiken 
design,  if  it  is  assumed  that  the  response  is  always  aroused  shortly 
after  the  onset  of  the  UCS,  then,  since  the  UCS  duration  is  held 
constant,  the  interval  between  response  and  reinforcement  is  also 
constant.  However,  as  the  position  of  the  CS  relative  to  the  UCS 
is  progressively  shifted  from  that  used  with  group  I  to  that  used 
with  groups  IV  and  V,  there  is  clearly  a  change  in  the  temporal 
separation  of  CS  and  response.  But  on  Hull's  views,  this  change 
in  the  position  of  the  CS  would  be  expected  to  lead  to  poorer  and 
poorer  conditioning,  since  it  involves  a  change  from  a  forward 
conditioning  procedure  to  an  extreme  degree  of  backward  condi- 
tioning. It  is  not  surprising,  therefore,  that  Mowrer  and  Aiken 
found  group  I  to  be  the  most  fearful,  with  fear  becoming  progres- 
sively less  in  the  groups  for  whom  the  procedure  became  more  and 
more  "backward."  It  is  well  known  to  students  of  conditioning 
that  backward  conditioning  arrangements  yield  little  if  any  stable 
conditioned  responses.  Davitz  (1955),  using  stimulus  presentation 
orders  like  those  of  Mowrer  and  Aiken's  groups  I  and  III,  also 
reports  that  more  fear  is  conditioned  when  the  CS  precedes  the 
onset  of  the  UCS  than  when  it  coincides  with  UCS  termination. 
However,  Davitz  also  fails  to  note  that  the  manipulation  of  the 
position  of  the  CS  relative  to  the  UCS  involves  a  shift  from 
forward  to  backward  conditioning.  Strouthes  and  Hamilton  (1959) 
have  also  employed  experimental  procedures  like  those  used  with 
groups  I  and  II  of  the  Mowrer-Aiken  study.  Their  animals,  how- 
ever, showed  enhanced  bar  pressing  during  the  presentation  of 
the  fear-arousing  CS  rather  than  inhibition,  as  in  the  Mowrer-Aiken 
investigation.  But  Strouthes  and  Hamilton's  group-II  animals  were 
more  fearful  than  their  group-I  subjects,  as  estimated  by  degree 
of  bar-pressing  facilitation.  Arguing  from  the  position  that  delay 
of  reinforcement  is  shorter  for  group  II  than  for  group  I,  and 


348  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

from  the  further  assumption  that  the  best  index  of  the  delay 
interval  is  provided  by  the  time  from  CS  onset  to  UCS  termina- 
tion, Strouthes  and  Hamilton  conclude  that  their  results  tend  to 
support  the  drive-reduction  position.  Finally,  Gerall,  Sampson, 
and  Boslov  (1957)  have  clearly  shown  that  a  known  reinforcer 
(electric  shock)  affects  the  conditioning  of  pupillary  dilation, 
which  is  a  response  controlled  by  the  autonomic  nervous  system. 
Light  offset  was  found  to  be  an  adequate  UCS  for  the  evocation 
of  the  pupillary  response,  but  no  conditioning  occurred  when  the 
CS  was  paired  with  light  offset  alone.  However,  when  the  UCS 
consisted  of  shock  paired  with  light  offset,  or  shock  alone,  condi- 
tioning of  pupillary  dilation  was  readily  obtained. 

Physiological  Studies  Related  to  the  Concept 
of  General  Drive 

When  Hull  (1943)  outlined  his  concept  of  a  nonspecific  drive 
(D),  his  speculations  rested  entirely  upon  observations  of  gross, 
molar  behavior.  At  that  time  there  were  scant  grounds  for  sup- 
posing that  a  general-purpose  motivating  function  of  this  sort 
could  be  meaningfully  ascribed  to  the  activities  of  any  particular 
neural  system  or  group  of  systems.  In  recent  years,  however,  this 
picture  has  been  altered  as  a  result  of  the  discovery  of  new  facts 
concerning  the  physiological  and  neurological  mechanisms  of 
motivation.  Of  special  relevance  for  the  hypothesis  of  nonspecific 
drive  are  data  that  have  been  interpreted  to  mean  that  the  brain- 
stem reticular  system  has  widespread  motivational  functions.  Addi- 
tional findings,  particularly  those  from  studies  of  intracranial  elec- 
trical stimulation,  have  shed  new  light  on  such  matters  as  the 
drive-reduction  theory  of  reinforcement  and  the  tendencies  of 
organisms  to  avoid  some  stimuli  and  approach  others.  We  shall 
discuss  these  several  matters  in  the  sections  to  follow. 

Drivelike  Functions  of  Reticular  System  Activity.  A  detailed 
elaboration  of  the  anatomical  minutiae  of  the  reticular  formation 
is  clearly  beyond  the  scope  of  this  book,  and  for  such  information 
the  reader  must  consult  other  sources  (e.g.,  Rossi  and  Zanchetti, 
1957,  and  Jasper,  1958).  In  broad  outline,  however,  the  brain- 
stem reticular  formation  consists,  according  to  Lindsley  (1957), 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  349 

".  .  .  of  a  rather  dense  network  of  neurons  which  forms  a  kind  of 
central  core  extending  from  the  medulla  of  the  lower  brain  stem 
to  the  thalamus  in  the  diencephalon.  It  extends  through  the  regions 
of  the  pons  and  the  midbrain  tegmentum  upward  through  the 
caudal  portions  of  the  hypothalamus  and  subthalamus"  (p.  57). 
Activity  in  the  brain-stem  reticular  system  can  affect  the  function 
of  structures  lying  both  below  and  above.  In  particular,  fibers 
passing  downward  from  the  reticular  formation  into  the  spinal 
cord  carry  impulses  that  assist  in  the  regulation  (either  by  inhibi- 
tion or  facilitation)  of  complex  postural  and  phasic  muscular 
reactions  Additionally,  and  perhaps  more  importantly  for  our 
purposes,  other  fiber  systems  composing  the  so-called  ascending 
reticular  activating  system  pass  upward  to  basal  ganglia,  thalamus, 
hypothalamus,  hyppocampus,  and  cortex. 

As  a  consequence,  apparently,  of  the  anatomical  diffusion  of 
these  ascending  reticular  system  fibers,  impulses  from  lower  seg- 
ments of  the  reticular  formation  can  bring  about  widespread 
changes  in  cortical  activity.  This  "activation  effect,"  as  it  has 
been  called,  which  was  first  reported  by  Moruzzi  and  Magoun 
(1949),  is  a  modification  of  the  waveform  pattern  of  the  electrical 
potentials  recorded  from  the  brain.  When  a  subject  is  asleep,  the 
form  of  these  electrical  impulses  differs  markedly  from  that  charac- 
teristic of  waking  or  excited  states.  Electrical  stimulation  in  the 
region  of  the  reticular  system  was  found  by  Moruzzi  and  Magoun 
to  change  the  cortical  brain  wave  from  the  "sleep"  pattern  to  the 
"waking"  or  "excited"  form.  Of  possible  significance,  for  theories 
of  motivation,  is  the  fact  that  this  "electrocortical  activation"  is 
widespread,  being  observed  at  numerous  points  on  the  cortical 
surface.  Moreover,  as  Lindsley,  Bowden,  and  Magoun  (1949)  have 
shown,  a  progressive  decline  in  amount  of  "electrocortical  activa- 
tion" is  associated  with  increasingly  widespread  destruction  of  the 
reticular  system.  At  the  very  least,  then,  the  nonspecific  activating 
effects  of  ascending  reticular  system  activity  appear  to  be  con- 
sistent with  the  construct  of  a  general-purpose  drive. 

That  the  arousal  functions  of  the  ascending  reticular  formation 
are  analogous  to,  if  not  completely  commensurate  with,  the  notion 
of  a  nonspecific  drive  was  apparently  first  noted  by  Hebb  (1955), 
though  Lindsley  (1951)  had  seen  the  broad  implications  of  reti- 


350  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

cular  system  activity  for  problems  of  emotion  and  motivation. 
According  to  Hebb,  activation  produced  by  the  diffuse  bombard- 
ment of  the  cortex  by  the  arousal  system  is  ".  .  .  synonymous  with 
a  general  drive  state,  and  the  conception  of  drive  therefore  assumes 
anatomical  and  physiological  identity"  (p.  249).  Schlosberg  (1954) 
has  also  stressed  the  emotional  and  motivational  aspects  of  arousal 
activity,  but  he  has  not  written  expressly  of  its  possible  relations 
to  Hull's  general-purpose  drive.  These  writers,  and  others  (e.g., 
Malmo,  1958),  have  also  observed  that  performance  decrements 
characteristic  of  "overly  motivated"  subjects  might  reasonably  be 
attributed  to  excessive  bombardment  of  the  cortex  by  the  ascending 
reticular  activating  system.  On  this  view,  performance  is  related 
to  motivation  ( activation )  level  by  an  inverted  U-shaped  function, 
performance  being  optimally  efficient  when  amount  of  activation 
is  neither  too  weak  (the  subject  is  drowsy  or  relaxed)  nor  too 
strong  (the  subject  is  angry,  fearful,  or  enraged). 

Support  for  the  view  that  impulses  in  the  ascending  reticular 
system  function  in  a  relatively  nonspecific  fashion  is  provided 
primarily  by  observed  changes  in  electrocortical  potentials.  But 
scattered  data  of  a  more  molar  nature  are  also  consistent  with 
this  view.  For  example,  it  has  long  been  known  that  responses  of 
flight,  rage,  and  generally  heightened  "emotionality"  can  be  pro- 
duced by  intracranial  stimulation;  and  it  is  responses  of  this  sort 
that  have  often  been  seen  as  reflecting  heightened  drive.  Moreover, 
according  to  Ingram,  Knott,  and  Chiles  (1953)  and  Lindsley 
(1957),  electrical  stimulation  of  the  brain-stem  reticular  system 
has  alerting  or  arousing  effects  upon  overt  behavior  as  well  as  upon 
the  pattern  of  the  electroencephalogram.  Perhaps  the  most  inter- 
esting data  of  this  kind  are  those  reported  by  Fuster  (1958). 
According  to  this  investigator,  stimulation  of  the  reticular  forma- 
tion of  monkeys  (at  the  mesencephalic  level)  while  they  are  en- 
gaged in  the  performance  of  visual  discrimination  tasks  increases 
their  speed  of  reacting,  improves  their  discriminatory  accuracy, 
and  lowers  their  tachistoscopic  recognition  thresholds.  Precisely 
what  the  mechanism  of  this  effect  may  be  is  not  clear,  but  it  seems 
to  be  congruent  with  the  idea  of  a  nonspecific  drive.  In  several 
studies,  however  (e.g.,  Chiles,  1954;  and  Knott,  Ingram,  and  Cor- 
rell,  1960),  lever  pressing  in  cats  tends  to  be  arrested  rather  than 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  351 

augmented  by  electrical  stimulation  in  the  region  of  the  hypo- 
thalamus. 

Several  investigators  (Delgado,  Roberts,  and  Miller,  1954;  Cohen, 
Brown,  and  Brown,  1957;  Roberts,  1958;  Bursten  and  Delgado, 
1958)  have  shown  that  intracranial  stimulation  may  function  in 
much  the  same  way  as  peripheral  shock.  To  take  a  single  example, 
Delgado  and  his  associates  have  noted  that  electrical  stimulation 
of  certain  thalamic,  mesencephalic,  and  rhinencephalic  structures 
elicits  fearlike  responses  in  cats.  The  resultant  emotionality  can 
be  conditioned  to  external  stimuli;  it  can  function  to  motivate 
the  learning  of  instrumental  acts;  and  it  can  serve  as  punishment 
in  training  hungry  cats  to  avoid  food.  Although  part  of  this  effect 
may  have  been  due  to  cerebral  pain,  similar  results  were  not  ob- 
tained from  the  stimulation  of  sensorimotor  areas.  Apparently, 
therefore,  centrally  introduced  stimuli,  when  applied  to  certain 
structures  and  under  certain  learning  conditions,  play  a  role  in 
the  determination  of  behavior  comparable  to  that  of  peripheral 
shocks  or  other  drive-arousing  unconditioned  stimuli. 

The  above  discussion  has  stressed  the  nonspecific  consequences 
of  central  stimulation,  but  quite  specific  responses  are  also  fre- 
quently evoked.  According  to  Samuels  (1959),  relatively  specific 
effects  of  central  stimulation  are  more  probably  reflections  of 
activity  in  the  thalamic  reticular  system  than  of  action  in  the  brain- 
stem reticular  system.  As  an  example  of  such  effects.  Miller  (1958) 
reports  the  elicitation  of  well-integrated  eating  and  drinking  re- 
sponses in  satiated  rats  as  the  result  of  central  (hypothalamic) 
stimulation.  This  specificity  of  action  is  not  of  primary  concern 
here,  but  it  may  constitute  the  physiological  basis  for  such  behavior- 
directing  effects  as  are  commonly  ascribed  to  drive-variable  stimuli 
{SnS). 

Considered  as  a  receiving  station  for  incoming  impulses,  the 
reticular  system  is  thought  to  be  affected  primarily  by  signals 
diverted  via  collaterals  from  the  primary  sensory  pathways  and, 
in  addition,  by  impulses  descending  from  the  cortex.  This  means, 
as  Lindsley  (1957),  Samuels  (1959),  and  others  have  indicated, 
that  the  activity  level  of  the  multineuronal,  multisynaptic  reticular 
formation  can  be  modified  by  both  exteroceptive  and  interoceptive 
stimuli  and  even  by  "ideational"  impulses  presumed  to  originate 


352  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

in  the  higher  cortical  centers.  From  this  the  conclusion  may  be 
drawn  that,  in  so  far  as  the  alerting  and  arousing  effects  of  reticular 
system  discharges  can  be  equated  to  nonspecific  drive,  then  level 
of  drive  is  under  the  control  of  external  and/or  internal  stimuli. 
The  implications  of  this  suggestion  are  widespread  and  of  con- 
siderable importance,  since,  if  this  is  indeed  the  case,  plausible 
mechanisms  are  provided  for  (1)  increasing  drive  by  presenting 
the  CS  for  an  aversive  response  or  by  presenting  an  incentive 
object,  (2)  reducing  drive  by  presenting  a  secondarily  reinforcing 
stimulus,  or  (3)  changing  drive  in  almost  any  manner  by  verbal 
instructions  or  self-induced  ideations.  As  we  have  previously  ob- 
served in  our  discussion  of  the  concepts  of  drive  and  need  (Chap- 
ter 3),  the  possibility  that  drive  strength  can  be  changed  by 
exteroceptive  or  proprioceptive  stimuli  may  clarify  some  of  the 
problems  posed  by  the  view  that  drive  reduction  is  essential  for 
learning. 

It  also  seems  probable  that  activity  in  the  reticular  system  can 
control  the  sensitivity  of  peripheral  receptors  and,  at  a  more 
central  level,  can  integrate  and  coordinate  receptor-generated 
information.  The  verification  of  these  functions  by  further  research 
may  provide  us  with  mechanisms  by  which  drive  can  affect  sensa- 
tion, perception,  memory,  and  a  variety  of  other  processes. 

Reinforcing  Properties  of  Intracerebral  Stimuli.  Although  the 
behavioral  effects  of  electrical  stimulation  of  the  brain  have  been 
studied  in  both  acute  and  chronic  preparations  for  many  years. 
Olds  and  Milner  (1954)  were  apparently  the  first  to  show  that 
such  stimuli  can  function  as  reinforcers  for  instrumental  acts.  This 
finding  has  provided  the  impetus  both  for  considerable  further 
research  and  for  theoretical  reappraisals  of  the  mechanisms  of 
reinforcement. 

In  the  Olds-Milner  demonstrations,  electrodes  were  perma- 
nently implanted  in  the  brains  of  rats  in  such  a  manner  as  not  to 
interfere  with  normal  daily  activities.  A  pair  of  thin,  flexible  wires 
could  be  attached,  as  desired,  to  the  electrodes  where  they  emerged 
from  the  skull.  These  wires  were  suspended  from  above  and  hence 
did  little  to  hamper  the  rat's  movements  in  a  Skinner  box  or 
through  simple  mazes.  This  arrangement  made  it  possible  for  the 
experimenters  to  administer  intracerebral  electric  stimuli  of  any 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  353 

strength  or  duration,  at  any  moment,  and  in  any  relation  to  the 
overt  actions  of  the  rat. 

The  most  interesting  finding  reported  by  Olds  and  Milner  was 
that  after  appropriate  conditions  of  pretraining,  some  subjects, 
particularly  those  having  electrode  tips  in  the  limbic  system, 
would  press  a  Skinner-box  lever  repeatedly  and  for  long  periods 
of  time,  even  though  each  lever-pressing  response  was  accompanied 
by  an  intracranial  shock.  In  some  cases  the  shocks  lasted  until 
the  lever  was  released,  but  usually  their  duration  was  fixed  at  0.5 
or  I.O  second.  Under  these  conditions,  with  no  rewards  other  than 
electrical  stimuli  being  provided,  rats  would  continue  to  press  the 
lever  for  periods  of  several  hours  and  at  rates  as  high  as  approxi- 
mately 30  responses  per  minute.  Unquestionably,  "masochistic" 
behavior  of  this  kind  is  puzzling,  since  electric  shock  has  been  so 
widely  used  as  an  aversive  or  punishing  stimulus.  Nevertheless, 
the  phenomenon  is  now  well  authenticated,  having  been  repeatedly 
demonstrated  in  rats  (Olds,  1956ci,  1956/?;  Reynolds,  1958;  Bower 
and  Miller,  1958),  in  cats  (Sidman,  Brady,  Boren,  Conrad,  and 
Schulman,  1955;  Roberts,  1958),  and  in  monkeys  (Bursten  and 
Delgado,  1958).  There  is  also  fairly  general  agreement  that  stimu- 
lation of  the  limbic  system,  and  especially  in  the  ventral  region 
of  the  anterior  hypothalamus,  is  more  likely  to  yield  positive 
reinforcement  effects  than  the  stimulation  of  other  regions.  The 
effect  is  not  confined,  however,  to  a  single  sharply  circumscribed 
area,  and  since  rather  high  intensities  of  shock  are  often  used, 
structures  other  than  those  adjacent  to  the  electrode  tips  may  be 
involved. 

When  consideration  is  given  to  the  question  of  why  these  sub- 
cortical stimuli  function  as  reinforcers,  no  entirely  convincing 
answers  are  forthcoming.  One  suggestion  is  that  pleasurable  sensa- 
tions or  experiences  are  aroused  when  known  reinforcing  areas  are 
excited.  On  this  view,  certain  portions  of  the  brain  are  seen  as 
"pleasure  centers,"  since  organisms  do  perform  responses  accom- 
panied by  the  stimulation  of  these  regions.  Other  areas,  the  stim- 
ulation of  which  seems  to  evoke  avoidance  and  withdrawal  rather 
than  approach,  would  qualify  as  "pain  centers."  This  conception 
is  attractive  to  advocates  of  hedonistic  theories  of  reinforcement 
and  is  supported  by  introspective  reports  of  "pleasurable"  sensa- 


354  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

tions  by  human  subjects  who,  while  conscious,  have  been  stimu- 
lated in  or  near  the  septal  region  (Heath,  1954).  The  view  is  also 
consistent  with  the  notion  that  some  of  the  reinforcing  areas  of 
the  brain  may  exert  a  quieting  or  inhibiting  effect  on  behavior. 
Thus  Brady  and  Nauta  (1953)  have  shown  that  extirpation  of  the 
septal  area  leads  to  an  increase  in  activity,  and  that  perhaps,  there- 
fore, the  normal  function  of  that  area  is  generally  inhibitory.  As 
Olds  (1955)  remarks,  ongoing  activity  usually  stops  abruptly  when 
the  septal  region  is  stimulated  electrically. 

Weighing  against  this  pleasure-center  view  are  the  findings  of 
Roberts  (1958),  Bower  and  Miller  (1958),  and  Brown  and  Cohen 
(1959).  All  these  investigators  have  shown  that  stimulation  of  a 
given  region,  even  with  intensity  held  constant,  may  be  either 
reinforcing  or  inhibiting  depending  upon  the  training  procedures 
used  and  upon  such  factors  as  stimulation  duration  and  the  testing 
environment.  Roberts,  for  instance,  reports  that  cats  in  a  Y  maze 
will  learn  to  enter  one  arm  of  the  maze  where  shock  to  the  pos- 
terior hypothalamus  is  turned  on  but  will  also  learn  to  enter  a 
second  arm  to  turn  off  the  shock.  Apparently  the  onset  of  excita- 
tion is  reinforcing,  since  the  animals  repeatedly  enter  the  maze 
arm  where  shock  is  turned  on;  but  continuation  of  the  stimulus 
seemingly  becomes  aversive,  because  the  cats  also  learn  to  enter 
the  only  arm  of  the  maze  where  the  shock  is  always  terminated. 
Of  special  interest  is  Roberts's  finding  that  increases  in  stimulus 
intensity  affect  the  approach  and  escape  responses  differentially. 
With  relatively  weak  shocks  the  response  leading  to  shock  onset 
is  readily  learned,  whereas  the  turning-off  response  is  not.  But  with 
high-voltage  stimulation  marked  improvement  is  shown  in  the 
learning  of  the  turning-off  response  while  the  turning-on  reaction 
is  performed  more  slowly  and  with  clear  indications  of  conflict. 

Qualitative  reports  of  the  behavior  of  animals  stimulated  in 
reinforcing  areas  also  weigh  against  any  simple  pleasure-center 
interpretation.  Thus  Olds  (1955)  observes  that,  following  pro- 
longed periods  of  reinforcing  self-stimulation  in  the  septal  area, 
rats  become  vicious  and  are  dangerous  to  handle.  This  seems  to 
contradict  the  notion  that  septal  stimulation  has  pleasurable  or 
soothing  consequences.  Moreover,  the  typical  behavior  pattern 
exhibited  by  both  rats  and  cats  during  periods  of  intermittent  self- 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  355 

Stimulation  is  often  described  as  "agitated  searching"  or  even  as 
"flight,"  which  scarcely  suggests  relaxation  and  contentment.  If 
the  self-stimulation  of  the  sort  investigated  in  these  studies  is 
pleasurable,  it  is  the  frenetic,  compulsive  pleasure  of  the  masochist 
or  the  neurotic.  Apparently  neither  rats  nor  cats,  when  stimulus 
duration  is  made  to  coincide  with  bar-depression  time,  hold  the 
bar  down  for  protracted  periods  so  that  the  self-stimulation  can 
be  prolonged.  Were  this  the  case,  rate  of  lever  pressing  should  be 
extremely  low,  since  the  subject  should  have  little  tendency  to 
release  the  lever  and  thereby  terminate  the  "pleasant"  experience. 
High  rates  of  lever  pressing  are  usually  obtained  with  high  voltages, 
indicating  that  the  subjects,  though  they  repeatedly  approach  and 
depress  the  lever,  must  be  releasing  it  quickly  and  thus  terminating 
the  shock.  Why  should  the  lever  be  released  if  this  act  eliminates 
a  genuinely  pleasurable  stimulus?  The  answer  to  this  question  is  no 
clearer  than  that  to  the  question  of  why  the  rat  depresses  the 
lever  in  the  first  place.  In  any  event,  although  rats  certainly  develop 
a  strong  tendency  to  approach  and  press  the  lever,  they  also  learn 
to  release  it  after  experiencing  a  relatively  brief  shock. 

It  is  also  quite  probable  that  the  success  of  self-stimulation 
demonstrations  depends  in  considerable  degree  upon  the  voltage 
levels  used  during  early  training  trials,  upon  the  rapidity  with 
which  the  voltage  is  increased  over  trials,  and  upon  other  aspects 
of  the  training  and  testing  procedures.  Olds  (1955),  for  instance, 
reports  that  his  rats  were  manually  placed  upon  the  bar  to  receive 
their  first  shock,  that  they  were  replaced  thereon  whenever  they 
were  not  responding  regularly,  and  that  the  progressive  upward 
shifting  of  voltages  had  to  be  carefully  executed  in  order  to  achieve 
maximum  response  rates.  As  yet  no  one  seems  to  have  set  the 
shock  at  a  high  level  initially  and  then  left  the  animals  alone  to 
see  whether  they  would  then  learn  to  press  the  lever  to  stimulate 
themselves.  Judging  from  Roberts's  results,  if  strong  shock  were 
used  from  the  outset,  it  would  probably  not  be  reinforcing,  though 
the  same  intensity  of  stimulation,  if  arrived  at  through  a  series  of 
carefully  graded  steps,  might  so  function.  Such  an  experiment  has 
apparently  not  even  been  done  with  mild  shock,  and,  to  the  writer's 
knowledge,  no  learning  curves  have  been  published  in  which  data 
from  every  shock  trial  (including  the  first)  have  been  presented. 


356  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

The  importance  of  training  and  testing  procedures  is  further  high- 
hghted  by  the  work  of  Bursten  and  Delgado  (1958),  who  failed 
in  a  preliminary  attempt  to  teach  monkeys  to  press  a  lever  for 
intracranial  shock  reward  but  succeeded  in  demonstrating  the  rein- 
forcing effects  of  shock  by  the  use  of  a  shuttle  box. 

There  is  also  merit  in  an  interpretation  proposed  by  Cohen, 
Brown,  and  Brown  (1957).  These  investigators  have  observed 
that  stimulation  of  intracranial  structures  such  as  the  hypothala- 
mus, though  it  may  produce  motivational  increments,  does  not 
immediately  and  consistently  evoke  directed  escape  responses.  The 
fearlike  or  ragelike  emotionality  cannot  be  referred  by  the  animal 
to  any  specific  objects  or  regions  in  his  environment.  Central 
shock  is  thus  unlike  grid  shock,  since  the  latter,  because  of  the 
direction-giving  peripheral  pain  cues,  regularly  elicits  movements 
of  leaping,  hopping,  or  running  that  are  directed  away  from  the 
source  of  irritation.  On  this  view,  when  animals  are  reinforced 
with  central  stimuli,  as  in  the  Olds-Milner  study,  they  do  not 
avoid  the  lever,  because  the  central  shock  provides  the  animal 
with  no  information  to  indicate  that  the  lever  or  any  other  par- 
ticular feature  of  the  testing  environment  is  the  source  of  the 
stimulus.  Or  to  phrase  it  differently,  mild  central  shock  does  not 
elicit  lever-escape  responses,  and  until  these  are  evoked  and  are 
reinforced,  the  animals  have  no  reason  to  refrain  from  approaching 
the  lever.  The  fact  that  animals  learn  to  press  the  lever  is  not,  of 
course,  explained  by  this  interpretation.  It  is  conceivable  that  fac- 
tors such  as  those  operating  in  studies  of  experimental  masochism 
(see  below)  may  be  of  significance  in  connection  with  this  prob- 
lem. 

In  the  early  flush  of  enthusiasm  generated  by  studies  of  intra- 
cranial reinforcing  stimuli,  the  fact  that  quite  similar  effects  have 
been  reported  for  externally  administered  shock  and  other  strong 
stimuli  seems  to  have  escaped  notice.  Masserman  (1946),  for 
instance,  in  his  studies  of  "experimental  masochism,"  trained  cats 
to  obtain  food  by  operating  a  lever.  Blasts  of  air  of  gradually 
increasing  intensity  were  then  administered  each  time  the  lever 
was  depressed.  At  the  end  of  training,  the  cats  were  not  only  not 
disturbed  by  airblasts  intense  enough  to  evoke  violent  avoidance 
in  nontrained  animals,  but  they  even  operated  the  switch  lever  in 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  357 

the  absence  of  food  reward,  the  airblast  having  apparently  acquired 
the  properties  of  a  substitute  reward.  Likewise,  Farber  (1948)  and 
Miller  and  Davis  (1943)  have  demonstrated  that  after  rats  have 
been  trained  to  run  down  an  alley  for  food,  mild  electric  grid 
shock  can  be  introduced  in  the  middle  of  the  alley  without  disrupt- 
ing the  approach  behavior.  The  latter  investigators  also  report  that 
if  shock  strength  is  then  increased  gradually  over  trials,  it  can  even- 
tually reach  a  very  high  level  without  causing  the  animals  to  cease 
running,  and  that,  in  fact,  their  speed  of  running  is  increased. 
But  if  the  voltage  is  raised  precipitously,  abrupt  cessation  of  run- 
ning is  the  result.  A  comparable  phenomenon,  observed  a  number 
of  years  ago  by  the  writer,  has  been  described  as  the  "vicious- 
circle"  phenomenon  by  Mowrer  (1950).  Rats  were  trained  initially 
to  run  down  a  short  straight  alley  to  escape  shock  by  reaching  a 
nonelectrified  section  at  the  end.  After  this  behavior  was  firmly 
established,  the  electrical  connections  to  the  first  three  feet  of  the 
grid  were  removed  to  make  it  "safe,"  while  the  last  three  feet  were 
left  electrified.  Some  rats,  when  placed  into  the  safe  section  at  the 
start,  continued  to  run  from  the  no-shock  starting  section  and 
across  the  shock  section  to  the  safe  goal  region.  With  some 
animals  this  behavior  persisted  for  literally  hundreds  of  trials 
without  the  slightest  sign  of  abatement.  Mowrer  has  suggested 
that  conditioned  fear  provides  the  motivation  for  running  out  of 
the  safe  starting  section,  that  strength  of  fear  is  maintained  by 
the  shock  encountered  on  the  way  to  the  safe  goal,  and  that  fear 
reduction,  operating  through  the  law  of  effect,  continues  to  rein- 
force running.  If  to  this  is  added  the  consideration  that  shock 
reduction  also  provides  a  powerful  and  continuing  reinforcement 
for  running,  the  plausibility  of  the  theory  is  enhanced.  Be  that 
as  it  may,  when  rats  exhibit  this  "vicious-circle"  behavior  they  are 
responding  quite  like  the  animals  in  the  intracranial  self-stimula- 
tion experiments.  It  is  even  possible  that  an  interpretation  such 
as  Mowrer's,  which  seems  to  provide  a  satisfactory  explanation  for 
one  of  these  phenomena,  can  be  extended  to  encompass  the  other. 
We  have  already  noted  in  discussing  the  so-called  manipulatory 
and  exploratory  drives  that  rats  will  learn  to  press  a  lever  when 
each  press  is  followed  by  the  onset  of  a  light  (Kish,  1955).  This 
phenomenon,  sometimes  described  by  the  phrase  "sensory-change 


358  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

reinforcement,"  has  been  amply  confirmed  by  Marx,  Henderson, 
and  Roberts  (1955),  by  Kling,  Horowitz,  and  Delhagen  (1956), 
and  by  Barnes  and  Kish  (1957).  It  is  of  interest  here  because  of 
the  ways  in  which  it  parallels  the  phenomena  of  reinforcement 
by  central  stimulation.  For  one  thing,  if  the  light  is  made  too 
bright,  its  onset  ceases  to  be  reinforcing  and  becomes  aversive 
(Marx  et  al.).  Clearly,  this  is  similar  to  Roberts's  (1958)  observa- 
tion that  when  a  central  stimulus  is  intense,  "turning-off"  responses 
are  easily  learned  but  "turning-on"  responses  are  not.  Moreover, 
lever  pressing  both  for  central  stimulation  ( Brady,  Boren,  Conrad, 
and  Sidman,  1957;  Olds,  1958)  and  for  light  onset  (Forgays  and 
Levin,  1959)  is  increased  by  food  deprivation.  And  both  types 
of  stimulation,  if  administered  under  the  proper  conditions,  can 
apparently  reinforce  more  complicated  responses  than  lever  press- 
ing, for  example,  maze  behavior  (Olds,  1955)  and  discrimination 
learning  (Forgays  and  Levin,  1959).  In  the  light  of  these  similari- 
ties, it  is  conceivable  that  both  types  of  experiments  involve  the 
operation  of  basically  similar  mechanisms  of  reinforcement. 

The  implications  of  findings  like  these  for  the  drive-reduction 
hypothesis  of  reinforcement  have  been  pointed  out  elsewhere 
(Brown,  1955).  The  fact  that  organisms  will  perform  responses 
leading  to,  or  accompanied  by,  increased  intensity  of  stimulation 
is  not  especially  damaging  to  this  hypothesis.  In  the  first  place, 
there  are  many  instances  in  which  enhanced  physical  stimulation 
need  not,  and  probably  should  not,  be  described  as  leading  to  or 
generating  increments  in  magnitude  of  drive.  In  each  particular 
case  one  must  consider  not  only  the  amount  of  physical  change 
but  also  the  adaptation  level  of  the  subject's  sense  organs,  the 
nature  of  his  ongoing  responses,  his  homeostatic  balances,  and  his 
previous  experiences  with  the  stimulus.  If,  when  evaluated  in  terms 
of  these  and  other  factors,  a  stimulus  does  not  qualify  as  a  source 
of  drive,  then  the  continued  appearance  of  responses  that  are 
followed  by  that  stimulus  is  not  conclusive  evidence  against  the 
drive-reduction  position.  In  the  second  place,  we  must  insist  once 
more  that  the  concepts  of  drive  and  need  are  not  identical  or  at 
least  do  not  have  to  be  identical.  A  bodily  need  may  function  as  a 
source  of  drive,  but  the  class  of  drive-reducing  operations  contains 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  359 

more  members  than  the  class  of  need-reducing  conditions.  The 
body's  need  for  water  can  be  eliminated  only  by  water  or  by  fluids 
containing  water,  but  the  drive  arising  from  that  need  can  perhaps 
be  partially  reduced,  at  least  temporarily,  by  such  activities  as 
turning  one's  attention  to  other  matters,  by  chewing  a  stick  of  gum, 
by  swallowing  repeatedly,  and  so  on.  Inasmuch  as  all  these  activities 
involve  an  increase  in  stimulation,  it  again  becomes  apparent  that 
drive  level  can  probably  be  modified  by  either  external  or  internal 
stimuli.  It  would  be  premature,  therefore,  to  insist  that  drive  is  not 
reduced  in  self-stimulation  demonstrations  simply  because  no 
biological  need  is  apparently  satisfied.  But  it  would  be  equally 
unwise  to  hold  stubbornly  to  a  drive-reduction  view  until  one  can 
point  with  some  assurance  to  the  source  of  the  drive  that  is  being 
reduced  by  self-stimulation  and  to  the  mechanisms  by  which  this 
reduction  might  be  achieved. 

As  a  third  and  final  point,  one  must  bear  in  mind  that  neither 
self-administered  intracranial  stimuli  nor  exteroceptive  stimuli  can 
serve  to  motivate  the  behavior  of  approaching  and  pressing  a  bar, 
if,  as  is  usually  the  case,  they  are  not  turned  on  until  after  the 
to-be-learned  response  has  been  initiated.  In  this  respect,  the  self- 
stimulation  studies  are  like  the  Butler-Harlow  experiments  on 
visual  rewards  with  monkeys.  The  motivation  underlying  prestimu- 
lation  behavior  may  be  a  kind  of  conditioned  anxiety,  or  a  positive 
expectancy  (rg-Sg)  of  anticipated  pleasure,  or  perhaps  simply 
the  animal's  normally  present  general  drive.  The  first  of  these 
possibilities  is  consistent  with  Mowrer's  interpretation  of  the 
"vicious-circle"  phenomenon,  and  the  second  with  the  view  that 
the  onset  of  some  stimuli  may  be  "pleasurable"  and  that  classically 
conditioned  fractional  responses  anticipatory  of  such  pleasure  might 
serve  as  sources  of  drive.  As  to  the  third  possibility,  little  need  be 
said  save  that  normal,  healthy,  awake  organisms  may  always  be 
operating  under  moderate  drive  even  when  no  extreme  biological 
imbalances  exist.  Taken  in  conjunction  with  the  manifold  stimuli 
provided  by  the  usual  environment,  this  persisting  drive  may 
suffice  to  activate  a  wide  variety  of  behaviors,  whose  probabilities 
of  appearance  are  subsequently  modified  by  reinforcements  of  one 
sort  or  another. 


360  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


Summary 


It  has  been  our  puq)ose  in  this  final  chapter  to  expand  our  treat- 
ment of  motivation  by  considering  several  topics  that  could  not 
conveniently  have  been  included  in  earlier  chapters. 

One  of  these  topics  involves  the  problem  of  whether  nonnoxious 
stimuli  that  evoke  responses  of  approaching,  exploring,  and  manip- 
ulating also  tend  to  function  as  motivational  variables.  Spence  and 
Hull  hold  that  such  stimuli  may  indeed  generate  increments  to 
drive,  provided  they  have  been  closely  associated  in  the  past  with 
reinforcing  events.  Thus  responses  composing  appetitive  consum- 
matory  sequences  are  thought  to  become  conditioned  to  any  stimuli 
present  when  those  responses  occur,  and  fractional  components  of 
the  sequences  can  also  be  evoked  by  similar  stimuli  even  prior  to 
the  time  the  goal  is  reached.  These  fractional  anticipatory  goal 
reactions  {rgs)  are  said  to  affect  behavior  both  associatively,  because 
of  the  characteristic  stimuli  {SgS)  they  are  assumed  to  provide, 
and  motivationally,  by  adding  an  increment  to  drive. 

Since  organisms  may  approach,  inspect,  and  manipulate  unfamil- 
iar as  well  as  familiar  objects,  the  possibility  must  be  entertained 
that  novel  stimuli  also  function  motivationally.  With  unfamiliar 
stimuli,  however,  interpretations  involving  acquired,  anticipatory 
responses  are  clearly  inappropriate.  As  a  result,  various  writers 
(Montgomery,  Harlow,  Berlyne,  and  others)  have  urged  that  the 
postulation  of  special-purpose  exploratory,  curiosity,  or  manipula- 
tory drives  is  desirable.  These  drives,  however,  are  drives  to  perform 
only  those  specific  kinds  of  acts  that  are  evoked  by  the  presentation 
of  novel  stimulus  objects.  Thus  they  involve  both  behavior-direct- 
ing and  motivating  functions;  and  in  the  role  of  systematic  con- 
cepts, these  behavior-specific  drives  suffer  from  the  fact  that  they 
are  seldom  defined  in  terms  of  observable  events  other  than  the 
particular  actions  they  are  alleged  to  produce. 

Representative  experiments  dealing  with  exploratory,  investiga- 
tive, and  manipulatory  behavior  indicate  that  rats,  as  well  as  higher 
organisms,  do  approach  and  investigate  some,  though  by  no  means 
all,  strange  or  novel  objects.  However,  when  such  behavior  is  not 
evoked,  or  when  actual  withdrawal  occurs,  a  fear  drive  is  invoked 
in  lieu  of  an  exploratory  drive.  Nevertheless,  numerous  investiga- 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  361 

tions  can  be  cited  which  support  the  conclusion  that  organisms 
often  behave  so  as  to  increase  their  contacts  with  unfamihar  stimuh 
or  locales  and  to  reduce  their  contacts  with  familiar  objects  or 
regions.  And  although  exploratory  and  investigative  behavior  weak- 
ens rather  quickly  as  novelty  diminishes,  manipulatory  behavior  in 
monkeys  is  remarkably  persistent.  In  addition,  some  students  of 
behavior  have  concluded  that  an  opportunity  to  investigate  a 
strange  environment  serves  as  a  reinforcing  agent  for  the  learning 
of  new  responses. 

Our  analyses  of  these  experiments  and  their  interpretations 
indicate  that  in  most  instances  it  is  difficult  to  reject  the  hypothesis 
that  motivational  factors  of  an  aversive  nature  have  been  present 
in  addition  to,  or  instead  of,  the  alleged  investigative  or  manipula- 
tory drives.  Continued  contact  with,  or  confinement  in,  one  seg- 
ment of  a  maze  may  be  an  aversive  condition  that  is  alleviated 
by  movement  to  other  segments.  It  is  also  uncertain,  in  the  case 
of  experiments  in  which  monkeys  are  reinforced  by  the  act  of 
looking  out  of  an  opaque-walled  box,  whether  appeal  must  be 
made  to  the  drive-arousing  attributes  of  the  external  cues.  At  the 
very  least,  the  drive  underlying  the  performance  of  responses 
occurring  prior  to  seeing  cannot  be  ascribed  to  the  effects  of  stimuli 
encountered  only  after  seeing  is  permitted.  However,  mild  anxiety 
due  to  isolation  and  confinement,  or  auditory  stimuli,  might  func- 
tion in  such  situations  as  motivators  of  preseeing  behavior.  It 
remains  to  be  demonstrated,  therefore,  that  special-purpose  drives 
must  be  invoked  to  explain  the  variety  of  actions  usually  described 
as  exploratory  and/or  manipulatory. 

Learned  emotional  reactions  are  said  by  many  to  have  significant 
motivational  properties.  The  question  of  how  such  responses  are 
learned,  therefore,  merits  consideration  in  any  theory  of  motivation. 
Some  theorists  (e.g.,  Guthrie  and  Hull)  find  no  reasons  for  sup- 
posing that  the  learning  of  autonomically  governed  reactions  is 
due  to  factors  or  processes  different  from  those  involved  in  the 
learning  of  skeletal  (instrumental)  responses.  Others,  however, 
maintain  that  different  principles  apply  to  the  learning  of  the  two 
classes  of  reactions.  For  example,  Mowrer  regards  stimulus-response 
contiguity  as  both  the  necessary  and  the  sufficient  condition  for 
the  learning  of  fears,  but  drive  reduction  is  seen  as  a  further  neces- 


362  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

sary  condition  for  the  acquisition  of  instrumental  acts.  This  view 
contrasts  with  Hull's  supposition  that  both  drive  reduction  and 
S-R  contiguity  are  necessary  for  the  learning  of  all  reactions. 

Our  analysis  of  these  views  and  of  experiments  designed  to 
support  them  reveals  that  a  lack  of  precision  in  the  structure  of 
all  extant  theories  makes  crucial  tests  difficult.  Experiments  that 
have  been  reported  appear  to  be  unusually  susceptible  to  interpre- 
tations other  than  those  presented  by  the  investigators  and  are 
marred  by  misconstructions  of  opposing  theories  and  by  the  con- 
founding effects  of  uncontrolled  variables. 

In  the  third  major  section  of  the  chapter,  evidence  from  phys- 
iological studies  of  central  nervous  system  activity  is  reviewed  with 
respect  to  its  implications  for  a  concept  of  general  drive.  Here  the 
most  significant  finding  appears  to  be  that  stimulation  in  the 
region  of  the  brain-stem  reticular  formation  can  change  electrical 
potentials  at  many  parts  of  the  cortex  from  a  pattern  characteristic 
of  sleep  to  one  associated  with  alert  wakefulness.  The  motivational 
implications  of  this  widespread  bombardment  of  the  cortex  by  the 
ascending  reticular  activating  system  have  been  widely  noted,  and 
Hebb  has  specifically  identified  this  activity  with  a  general-drive 
state.  Apparently,  these  alerting  functions  can  be  modified  by  a 
wide  variety  of  influences,  including  internal  and  external  stimuli, 
and  even  the  so-called  ideational  and  attitudinal  factors  presum- 
ably mediated  largely  by  cortical  processes.  It  thus  appears  that 
drive  level,  to  the  extent  that  it  may  be  identified  with  arousal 
activity  of  the  ascending  reticular  system,  can  either  be  raised  or 
lowered  by  a  multiplicity  of  events.  The  potential  significance  of 
this  possibility  for  such  problems  as  those  of  secondary  reinforce- 
ment, perceptual  defense  or  vigilance,  and  the  drive-reduction 
theory  of  reinforcement  remains  to  be  explored. 

The  final  section  of  the  chapter  deals  with  studies  of  the  rein- 
forcing and  inhibiting  effects  of  centrally  administered  brain 
stimuli.  The  fact  that  animals  can  learn  to  perform  acts  such  as 
lever  pressing  when  the  only  consequence  of  the  act  is  a  sub- 
cortical electric  shock  is  the  empirical  phenomenon  of  central 
interest.  The  basic  finding  has  been  repeatedly  confirmed  in  rats 
and  cats  and,  with  some  success,  in  monkeys.  Some  investigators 
have  been  led  to  the  conclusion  that  reinforcing  regions  of  the 


MISCELLANEOUS  MOTIVATIONAL  PROBLEMS  363 

brain  might  be  construed  as  "pleasure  centers,"  whereas  other 
areas,  the  stimulation  of  which  leads  to  inhibition  of  activity, 
might  be  termed  "pain  centers."  Support  for  this  view  has  been 
provided  by  introspective  reports  from  human  subjects  who  have 
been  stimulated  while  undergoing  brain  surgery  under  local  anes- 
thesia. In  a  variety  of  studies,  however,  it  has  been  found  that  an 
animal  can  be  taught  either  to  perform  an  act  to  turn  the  brain 
stimulus  on,  or  to  perform  a  different  act  to  turn  it  off.  Since  in 
these  demonstrations  the  electrode  placement  and  shock  intensity 
is  the  same,  any  simple  concept  of  pleasure  or  pain  centers  becomes 
relatively  untenable.  Apparently  brain  stimuli  can  have  either 
rewarding  or  punishing  effects,  depending  upon  the  kinds  of 
behavior  that  are  elicited  by  the  test  situation  and  upon  temporal 
and  other  relations  between  the  stimuli  and  the  behavior. 


REFERENCES 

iiiiiniiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiH^ 


Adolph,  E.  F.  (1941):  The  internal  environment  and  behavior:  III. 
Water  content.  Amer.  J.  Psychiat.,  97,  1365-1373. 

Adolph,  E.  F.  (1943):  Physiological  regulations.  New  York:  The 
Ronald  Press  Company. 

Amsel,  A.  (1950a):  The  combination  of  a  primary  appetitional  need 
with  primary  and  secondary  emotionally  derived  needs.  /.  exp. 
Psychol,  40,  1-14. 

Amsel,  A.  (1950b):  The  effect  upon  level  of  consummatory  response 
of  the  addition  of  anxiety  to  a  motivational  complex.  /.  exp. 
Psychol,  40,  709-715. 

Amsel,  A.  (1951):  A  three-factor  theory  of  inhibition:  an  addition  to 
Hull's  two-factor  theory.  Amer.  Psychologist,  6,  487.  (Abstract.) 

Amsel,  A.  (1958) :  The  role  of  frustrative  nonreward  in  noncontinuous 
reward  situations.  Psychol.  Bull,  SS,  102-119. 

Amsel,  A.,  and  W,  Hancock  (1957):  Motivational  properties  of 
frustration:  III.  Relation  of  frustration  effect  to  antedating  goal 
factors.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  53,  126-131. 

Amsel,  A.,  and  I.  Maltzman  (1950):  The  effect  upon  generalized 
drive  strength  of  emotionality  as  inferred  from  the  level  of  con- 
summatory response.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  40,  563-569. 

Amsel,  A.,  and  J.  Roussel  (1952):  Motivational  properties  of  frustra- 
tion: I.  Effect  on  a  running  response  of  the  addition  of  frustration 
to  the  motivational  complex.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  43,  363-368. 

Anand,  B.  K.,  and  J.  R.  Brobeck  (1951):  Hypothalamic  control  of 
food  intake  in  rats  and  cats.  Yale  J.  Biol,  and  Med.,  24,  123-140. 

Anderson,  E.  E.  (1941):  The  externalization  of  drive:  III.  Maze 
learning  by  non-rewarded  and  by  satiated  rats.  J.  genet.  Psychol, 
59,  397-426. 

Armus,  H.  L.  (1954) :  The  effect  of  percentage  of  reinforcement  and 
distribution  of  trials  on  resistance  to  extinction  of  a  conditioned 
fear  response.  Unpublished  doctoral  dissertation.  State  University 
of  Iowa. 

365 


366  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Aronson,  E.  (1956):  The  need  for  achievement  as  measured  by 
graphic  expression.  Unpublished  master's  thesis,  Wesleyan  Uni- 
versity. Cited  in  McClelland,  1956. 

Ashley,  W.  R.,  R.  S.  Harper,  and  D.  L.  Runyon  (1951):  The  per- 
ceived size  of  coins  in  normal  and  hypnotically  induced  economic 
states.  Amer.  J.  Psychol,  64,  564-572. 

Atkinson,  J.  W.  (1950) :  Studies  in  projective  measurement  of  achieve- 
ment motivation.  University  of  Michigan.  Abstract  in  University 
Microfilms,  Vol.  X,  N.  4;  Publication  No.  1945.  Cited  in  McClel- 
land, Atkinson,  Clark,  and  Lowell,  1953. 

Atkinson,  J.  W.  (1954):  Explorations  using  imaginative  thought  to 
assess  the  strength  of  human  motives.  In  M.  R.  Jones  (ed.), 
Nebraska  symposium  on  motivation.  Lincoln,  Nebr.:  University 
of  Nebraska  Press. 

Atkinson,  J.  W.,  and  D.  C.  McClelland  (1948):  The  projective  ex- 
pression of  needs.  II.  The  effect  of  different  intensities  of  the 
hunger  drive  on  thematic  apperception.  J.  exp.  Psychol.,  38, 
643-658. 

Bahrick,  H.  P.  (1953) :  Sensory  preconditioning  under  two  degrees  of 
deprivation.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  46,  39-42. 

Bakan,  D.  (1953):  Learning  and  the  scientific  enterprise.  Psychol. 
Rev.,  60,  45-49. 

Baker,  R.  A.  (1955):  The  effects  of  repeated  deprivation  experience 
on  feeding  behavior.  J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  48,  37-42. 

Barnes,  G.  W.,  and  G.  B.  Kish  (1957) :  Reinforcing  properties  of  the 
termination  of  intense  auditory  stimulation.  /.  comp.  physiol. 
Psychol,  50,  40-43. 

Barry,  H.,  Ill  (1958):  Effects  of  strength  of  drive  on  learning  and 
extinction.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  55,  473-481. 

Bass,  Bettina  (1958) :  The  effect  of  drive  variation  within  and  between 
subjects  on  conditioning  performance.  Unpublished  doctoral  dis- 
sertation, State  University  of  Iowa. 

Beams,  H.  L.  (1954):  Affectivity  as  a  factor  in  the  apparent  size  of 
pictured  food  objects.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  47,  197-200. 

Bechtoldt,  H.  P.,  and  J.  S.  McDonough  (1958):  The  effects  of 
motivating  instructions  upon  visual  identification  thresholds.  (Un- 
published. Personal  communication.) 

Bergmann,  G.  (1944):  An  empiricist's  system  of  the  sciences.  Sci. 
Monthly,  59,  140-148. 

Berkun,  M.  M.,  M.  L.  Kessen,  and  N.  E.  Miller,  (1952):  Hunger- 
reducing  effects  of  food  by  stomach  fistula  versus  food  by  mouth 
measured  by  a  consummatory  response.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol, 
45,  550-554. 

Berlyne,  D.  E.  (1955) :  The  arousal  and  satiation  of  perceptual  curios- 
ity in  the  rat.  /.  comp.  physiol  Psychol,  48,  238-246, 


REFERENCES  367 

Berlyne,  D.  E.  (1958):  The  present  status  of  research  on  exploratory 
and  related  behavior.  /.  indiv.  Psychol.,  14,  121-126. 

Bills,  A.  G.  (1927):  The  influence  of  muscular  tension  on  the  effi- 
ciency of  mental  work.  Amer.  J.  Psychol.,  38,  227-251. 

Bindra,  D.  (1959) :  Stimulus  change,  reactions  to  novelty,  and  response 
decrement.  Psychol.  Rev.,  66,  96-103. 

Bindra,  D.,  A.  L.  Paterson,  and  J.  Strzelecki  (1955) :  On  the  relation 
between  anxiety  and  conditioning.  Canad.  J.  Psychol.,  9,   1-6. 

Birch,  D.,  E.  Burnstein,  and  R.  A.  Clark  (1958) :  Response  strength  as 
a  function  of  food  deprivation  under  a  controlled  maintenance 
schedule.  J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  SI,  350-354. 

Bitterman,  M.  E.,  and  W.  H.  Holtzman  (1952):  Conditioning  and 
extinction  of  the  galvanic  skin  response  as  a  function  of  anxiety. 
/.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  47,  615-623. 

Bitterman,  M.  E.,  and  C.  W.  KnifEn  (1953):  Manifest  anxiety  and 
"perceptual  defense."  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  48,  248-252. 

Bitterman,  M.  E.,  P.  Reed,  and  J.  Krauskopf  (1952):  The  effect  of 
the  duration  of  the  unconditioned  stimulus  upon  conditioning 
and  extinction.  Amer.  J.  Psychol.,  65,  256-262. 

Bolles,  R.  C.  (1958) :  Comments  on  Professor  Estes'  paper.  In  M.  R. 
Jones  (ed.),  Nebraska  symposium  on  motivation.  Lincoln,  Nebr.: 
University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Bower,  G.  H.,  and  N.  E.  Miller  (1958):  Rewarding  and  punishing 
effects  from  stimulating  the  same  place  in  the  rat's  brain.  /.  comp. 
physiol.  Psychol,  51,  669-674. 

Brady,  J.  V.,  }.  J.  Boren,  D.  Conrad,  and  M.  Sidman  (1957):  The 
effect  of  food  and  water  deprivation  upon  intracranial  self-stimu- 
lation. /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  50,  134-137. 

Brady,  J.  V.,  and  W.  J.  H.  Nauta  (1953) :  Subcortical  mechanisms  in 
emotional  behavior:  affective  changes  following  septal  forebrain 
lesions  in  the  albino  rat.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  46,  339-346. 

Brady,  J.  V.,  W.  C.  Stebbins,  and  R.  Galambos  (1953) :  The  effect  of 
audiogenic  convulsions  on  a  conditioned  emotional  response. 
J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  46,  363-367. 

Brandauer,  C.  M.  (1953):A  confirmation  of  Webb's  data  concerning 
the  action  of  irrelevant  drives.  /.  exp.  Psychol.,  45,  150-152. 

Braunstein,  E.  P.  (1923):  Zur  Lehre  von  den  kurzdauernden  Lich- 
treizen  der  Netzhaut.  Zsc/i.  /.  Sinnesphysiol.,  55,  185-229.  Cited 
by  S.  Hecht  (1934):  The  nature  of  the  photoreceptor  process. 
In  C.  Murchison  (ed.).  Handbook  of  general  experimental  psy- 
chology. Worcester,  Mass.:  Clark  University  Press,  1934. 

Bricker,  P.  D.,  and  A.  Chapanis  (1953):  Do  incorrectly  perceived 
tachistoscopic  stimuli  convey  some  information?  Psychol.  Rev., 
60,  181-188. 

Broadhurst,  P.  L.  (1957):  Emotionality  and  the  Yerkes-Dodson  law. 
/.  exp.  Psychol,  54,  345-352. 


368  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Brobeck,  J.  R.  (1955):  Neural  regulation  of  food  intake.  In  R.  W. 
Miner  (ed.),  The  regulation  of  hunger  and  appetite.  Ann.  N.  Y. 
Acad.  Sci.,  63,  Art.  1,  New  York:  N.Y.  Acad.  Sci. 

Brown,  D.  R.,  and  J.  Adams  (1954) :  Word  frequency  and  the  meas- 
urement of  value  areas.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  49,  427-430. 

Brown,  G.  W.,  and  B.  D.  Cohen  (1959):  Avoidance  and  approach 
learning  motivated  by  stimulation  of  identical  hypothalamic 
nuclei.  Amer.  J.  Physiol,  197,  153-157. 

Brown,  J.  S.  (1948):  Gradients  of  approach  and  avoidance  responses 
and  their  relation  to  level  of  motivation.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol., 
41,  450-465. 

Brown,  J.  S.  (1953(z) :  Problems  presented  by  the  concept  of  acquired 
drives.  In  Current  theory  and  research  in  motivation:  a  sym- 
posium. Lincoln,  Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Brown,  J.  S.  (1953b):  Comments  on  Professor  Harlow's  paper.  In 
Current  theory  and  research  in  motivation:  a  symposium.  Lincoln, 
Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Brown,  J.  S.  (1955) :  Pleasure-seeking  behavior  and  the  drive-reduction 
hypothesis.  Psychol.  Rev.,  62,  169-179. 

Brown,  J.  S.  (1957):  Principles  of  intrapersonal  conflict.  Conflict 
Resolution,  1,  135-154. 

Brown,  J.  S.,  and  I.  E.  Farber  (1951):  Emotions  conceptualized  as 
intervening  variables — with  suggestions  toward  a  theory  of  frus- 
tration. Psychol.  Bull,  48,  465-495. 

Brown,  J.  S.,  and  A.  Jacobs  (1949) :  The  role  of  fear  in  the  motivation 
and  acquisition  of  responses.  J.  exp.  Psychol,  39,  747-759. 

Brown,  J.  S.,  H.  I.  Kalish,  and  I.  E.  Farber  (1951) :  Conditioned  fear 
as  revealed  by  magnitude  of  startle  response  to  an  auditory 
stimulus.  J.  exp.  Psychol,  41,  317-328. 

Brown,  J.  S.,  J.  W.  Meryman,  and  F.  N.  Marzocco  (1956):  Sound- 
induced  startle  response  as  a  function  of  time  since  shock.  /. 
comp.  physiol  Psychol,  49,  190-194. 

Brown,  W.  L.,  and  G.  Gentry  (1948) :  The  effects  of  intra-maze  delay. 
II.  Various  intervals  of  delay.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  41,  403- 
407. 

Brozek,  J.,  H.  Guetzkow,  and  M.  V.  Baldwin  (1951):  A  quantitative 
study  of  perception  and  association  in  experimental  semistarva- 
tion.  /.  Pers.,  19,  245-264. 

Bruner,  J.  S.,  and  C.  C.  Goodman  (1947) :  Value  and  need  as  organ- 
izing factors  in  perception.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol,  42,  33-44. 

Bruner,  J.  S.,  and  L.  Postman  (1947):  Emotional  selectivity  in  per- 
ception and  reaction.  /.  Pers.,  16,  69-77. 

Bruner,  J.  S.,  and  L.  Postman  (1948) :  Symbolic  value  as  an  organizing 
factor  in  perception.  /.  soc.  Psychol,  27,  203-208. 

Bruner,  J.  S.,  and  J.  S.  Rodrigues  (1953):  Some  determinants  of 
apparent  size.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol,  48,  17-24. 


REFERENCES  369 

Bugelski,  R.,  and  N.  E.  Miller  (1938):  A  spatial  gradient  in  the 
strength  of  avoidance  responses.  /.  exp.  Psychol.,  23,  494-505. 

Burros,  R.  H.  (1949):  Quantitative  studies  in  secondary  drive.  Un- 
published doctoral  dissertation,  Yale  University. 

Bursten,  B.,  and  J.  M.  R.  Delgado  (1958):  Positive  reinforcement 
induced  by  intracerebral  stimulation  in  the  monkey.  /.  comp. 
physiol.  Psychol.,  5 J,  6-10. 

Butler,  R.  A.  (1953):  Discrimination  learning  by  rhesus  monkeys  to 
visual-exploration  motivation.  J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  46, 
95-98. 

Butler,  R.  A.  (1957):  The  eflFect  of  deprivation  of  visual  incentives 
on  visual  exploration  motivation  in  monkeys.  /.  comp.  physiol. 
Psychol,  SO,  177-179. 

Butler,  R.  A.  (1958):  Exploratory  and  related  behavior:  a  new  trend 
in  animal  research.  J.  indiv.  Psychol.,  14,  111-120. 

Butler,  R.  A.,  and  H.  F.  Harlow  (1954):  Persistence  of  visual  ex- 
ploration in  monkeys.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  47,  258- 
263. 

Calvin,  J.  S.,  E.  A.  Bicknell,  and  D.  S.  Sperling  (1953):  Establish- 
ment of  a  conditioned  drive  based  on  the  hunger  drive.  /.  comp. 
physiol.  Psychol,  46,  173-175. 

Campbell,  B.  A.,  and  D.  Kraeling  (1953):  Response  strength  as  a 
function  of  drive  level  and  amount  of  drive  reduction.  /.  exp. 
Psychol,  4S,  97-101. 

Campbell,  B.  A.,  and  D.  Kraeling  (1954):  Response  strength  as  a 
function  of  drive  level  during  training  and  extinction.  /.  comp. 
physiol  Psychol,  47,  101-103. 

Campbell,  N.  R.  (1921) :  What  is  science?  London:  Methuen  &  Co., 
Ltd. 

Cannon,  W.  B.  (1929):  Bodily  changes  in  pain,  hunger,  fear,  and 
rage,  2d  ed.  New  York:  Appleton-Century-Crofts,  Inc. 

Carlton,  P.  L.  (1955):  The  effect  of  time  of  food  deprivation  on 
selective  learning.  Unpublished  doctoral  dissertation,  State  Uni- 
versity of  Iowa. 

Carter,  L.  F.,  and  K.  Schooler  (1949) :  Value,  need,  and  other  factors 
in  perception.  Psychol.  Rev.,  S6,  200-207. 

Castaneda,  A.,  B.  R.  McCandless,  and  D.  S.  Palermo  (1956):  The 
children's  form  of  the  manifest  anxiety  scale.  Child  Develpm., 
17,  317-326. 

Castaneda,  A.,  D.  S.  Palermo,  and  B.  R.  McCandless  (1956):  Com- 
plex learning  and  performance  as  a  function  of  anxiety  in  children 
and  task  difficulty.  Child  Develpm.,  27,  327-332. 

Champion,  R.  A.  (1954):  Drive-strength  and  competing  response 
tendencies.  Unpublished  master's  thesis,  State  University  of  Iowa. 

Chapanis,  A.,  W.  R.  Garner,  and  C.  T.  Morgan  (1949)':  Applied 
experimental  psychology.  New  York:  John  Wiley  &  Sons,  Inc. 


370  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Chapman,  R.  M.,  and  N.  Levy  (1957) :  Hunger  drive  and  reinforcing 
effect  of  novel  stimuli.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  SO,  233-238. 

Child,  I.  L.,  and  I.  K.  Waterhouse  (1953):  Frustration  and  the 
quality  of  performance:  II.  A  theoretical  statement.  Psychol. 
Rev.,  60,  127-139. 

Chiles,  W.  D.  (1954):  Performance  during  stimulation  of  the  dien- 
cephalic activating  system.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  47,  412- 
415. 

Chodorkoff,  B.  (1956):  Anxiety,  threat,  and  defensive  reactions.  /. 
gen.  Psychol,  54,  191-196. 

Clark,  R.  A.  (1952):  The  projective  measurement  of  experimentally 
induced  levels  of  sexual  motivation.  J.  exp.  Psychol.,  44,  391-399. 

Clark,  R.  A.,  and  D.  C.  McClelland  (1950) :  A  factor  analytic  integra- 
tion of  imaginative,  performance,  and  case  study  measures  of 
the  need  for  achievement.  Unpublished  paper,  cited  in  McClel- 
land, Atkinson,  Clark,  and  Lowell,  1953. 

Clark,  R.  E.  (1958) :  Size  estimation  limens  as  a  function  of  level  of 
motivation.    (Unpublished.    Personal    communication.) 

Cohen,  B.  D.,  G.  W.  Brown,  and  M.  L.  Brown  (1957):  Avoidance 
learning  motivated  by  hypothalamic  stimulation.  /.  exp.  Psychol., 
53,  228-233. 

Cohen,  M.  R.,  and  E.  Nagel  (1934):  An  introduction  to  logic  and 
scientific  method.  New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace  and  Company,  Inc. 

Conger,  J.  J.  (1951):  The  effects  of  alcohol  on  conflict  behavior  in 
the  albino  rat.  Quart.  J.  Stud.  Alcohol,  12,  1-29. 

Cooper,  J.  B.  (1938):  The  effect  upon  performance  of  introduction 
and  removal  of  a  delay  within  the  maze.  J.  comp.  Psychol.,  25, 
457-462. 

Cotton,  J.  W.  (1953):  Running  time  as  a  function  of  amount  of 
food  deprivation.  /.  exp.  Psychol.,  46,  188-198. 

Courts,  F.  A.  (1942):  Relations  between  muscular  tension  and  per- 
formance. Psychol.  Bull,  39,  347-367. 

Cowles,  J.  T.  (1937) :  Food- tokens  as  incentives  for  learning  by  chim- 
panzees. Comp.  Psychol.  Monogr.  14,  No.  5  (Whole  No.  71). 

Crespi,  L.  P.  (1944):  Amount  of  reinforcement  and  level  of  per- 
formance. Psychol.  Rev.,  51,  341-357. 

Davenport,  J.  W.  (1956):  Choice  behavior  as  a  function  of  drive 
strength  and  rate  of  learning.  Unpublished  doctoral  dissertation, 
State  University  of  Iowa. 

Davis,  J.  D.  (1958):  The  reinforcing  effect  of  weak-light  onset  as  a 
function  of  amount  of  food  deprivation.  J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol, 
51,  496-498. 

Davis,  R.  C.  (1953):  Physical  psychology.  Psychol  Rev.,  60,  7-14. 

Davis,  R.  H.  (1957):  The  effect  of  drive  reversal  on  latency,  ampli- 
tude, and  activity  level.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  53,  310-315. 


REFERENCES  371 

Davitz,  J.  R.  (1955):  Reinforcement  of  fear  at  the  beginning  and  at 
the  end  of  shock.  J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  48,  152-155. 

Deese,  J.,  and  J.  A.  Carpenter  (1951) :  Drive  level  and  reinforcement. 
/.  exp.  Psychol,  42,  236-238. 

Deese,  J.,  R.  S.  Lazarus,  and  }.  Keenan  (1953):  Anxiety,  anxiety  re- 
duction, and  stress  in  learning.  /.  exp.  Psychol.,  46,  55-60. 

Delgado,  J.  M.  R.,  W.  W.  Roberts,  and  N.  E.  Miller  (1954) :  Learn- 
ing motivated  by  electrical  stimulation  of  the  brain.  Amer.  J. 
Physiol,  179,  587-593. 

Dember,  W.  N.,  and  H.  Fowler  (1958):  Spontaneous  alteration 
behavior.  Psychol  Bull,  SS,  412-428. 

Dinsmoor,  J.  A.  (1952):  The  effect  of  hunger  on  discriminated  re- 
sponding. /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol,  47,  67-72. 

Dodson,  J.  D.  (1917):  Relative  values  of  reward  and  punishment  in 
habit  formation.  Psychobiology,  1,  231-276. 

Dollard,  J.,  and  N.  E.  Miller  (1950):  Personality  and  psychotherapy. 
New  York:  McGraw-Hill  Book  Company,  Inc. 

Dollard,  J.,  L.  W.  Doob,  N.  E.  Miller,  O.  H.  Mowrer,  and  R.  R.  Sears 
(1939):  Frustration  and  aggression.  New  Haven,  Conn.:  Yale 
University  Press. 

Duffy,  E.  (1934) :  Emotion:  an  example  of  the  need  for  reorientation 
in  psychology.  Psychol.  Rev.,  41,  184-198. 

Duffy,  E.  (1951) :  The  concept  of  energy  mobilization.  Psychol  Rev., 
SB,  30-40. 

Duffy,  E.  (1957):  The  psychological  significance  of  "arousal"  or 
"activation."  Psychol  Rev.,  64,  265-275. 

Dukes,  W.  F.,  and  W.  Bevan,  Jr.  (1952) :  Size  estimation  and  mone- 
tary value:  a  correlation.  J.  Psychol,  34,  43-53. 

Eisman,  E.  (1956):  An  investigation  of  the  parameters  defining  drive 
(D).  J.  exp.  Psychol,  52,  85-89. 

Eisman,  E.,  A.  Asimow,  and  I.  Maltzman  (1956) :  Habit  strength  as  a 
function  of  drive  in  a  brightness  discrimination  problem.  /.  exp. 
Psychol,  S2,  58-64. 

Eriksen,  C.  W.  (1951):  Some  implications  for  TAT  interpretation 
arising  from  need  and  perception  experiments.  /.  Pers.,  19, 
282-288. 

Eriksen,  C.  W.  (1954):  The  case  for  perceptual  defense.  Psychol 
Rev.,  61,  175-182. 

Estes,  W.  K.  (1950) :  Toward  a  statistical  theory  of  learning.  Psychol. 
Rev.,  57,  94^107. 

Estes,  W.  K.  (1958):  Stimulus-response  theory  of  drive.  In  M.  R. 
Jones  (ed.),  Nebraska  symposium  on  motivation.  Lincoln,  Nebr.: 
University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Estes,  W.  K.,  and  B.  F.  Skinner  (1941) :  Some  quantitative  properties 
of  anxiety.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  29,  390-400. 


372  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Farber,  I.  E.  (1948) :  Response  fixation  under  anxiety  and  non-anxiety 
conditions.  J.  exp.  Psychol.,  38,  111-131. 

Farber,  I.  E.  (1954d) :  Anxiety  as  a  drive  state.  In  M.  R.  Jones  (ed.), 
Nebraska  symposium  on  motivation.  Lincoln,  Nebr.:  University 
of  Nebraska  Press. 

Farber,  I.  E.  (1945b):  Comments  on  Professor  Atkinson's  paper. 
In  M.  R.  Jones  (ed.),  Nebraska  symposium  on  motivation.  Lin- 
coln, Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Farber,  I.  E.  (1955):  The  role  of  motivation  in  verbal  learning  and 
performance.  Psychol.  Bull.,  52,  311-327. 

Farber,  1.  E.,  and  K.  W.  Spence  (1953) :  Complex  learning  and  condi- 
tioning as  a  function  of  anxiety.  /.  exp.  Psychol.,  4S,  120-125. 

Finch,  G.  (1942):  Chimpanzee  frustration  responses.  Psychosom. 
Med.,  4,  233-251. 

Forgays,  D.  G.,  and  H.  Levin  (1959):  Discrimination  and  reversal 
learning  as  a  function  of  change  of  sensory  stimulation.  /.  comp. 
physiol.  Psychol,  SI,  191-194. 

Franks,  CM.  (1957) :  Effect  of  food,  drink,  and  tobacco  deprivation 
on  the  conditioning  of  the  eyeblink  response.  J.  exp.  Psychol.,  S3, 
117-120. 

Fredenburg,  N.  C.  (1956):  Response  strength  as  a  function  of  alley 
length  and  time  of  deprivation.  Unpublished  master's  thesis,  State 
University  of  Iowa. 

Freeman,  J.  T.  (1954) :  Set  or  perceptual  defense?  /.  exp.  Psychol,  48, 
283-288. 

French,  E.  G.  (1956) :  Development  of  a  measure  of  complex  motiva- 
tion. Research  Report  TN-56-48,  AF  Personnel  and  Training 
Research  Center,  Lackland  AF  base,  Texas. 

French,  J.  R.  P.,  Jr.  (1944) :  Organized  and  unorganized  groups  under 
fear  and  frustration.  In  R.  R.  Sears  (ed.),  Authority  and  frustra- 
tion: Studies  in  topological  and  vector  psychology.  HI.  University 
Iowa  Stud.  Child  Welfare,  20,  231-308. 

Freud,  S.  (1905,  First  German  ed.):  Three  essays  on  sexuality.  In 
Standard  Edition.  Vol.  VII.  London:  Hogarth  Press,  Ltd.,  1953. 

Freud,  S.  (1936) :  The  problem  of  anxiety.  New  York:  W.  W.  Norton 
&  Company,  Inc. 

Fuster,  J.  M.  (1958) :  Effects  of  stimulation  of  brain  stem  on  tachisto- 
scopic  perception.  Science,  127,  150. 

Gardiner,  H.  M.,  R.  C.  Metcalf,  and  J.  G.  Beebe-Center  (1937): 
Feeling  and  emotion.  New  York:  American  Book  Company, 

Gerall,  A.  A.,  P.  B.  Sampson,  and  G.  L  Boslov  (1957):  Classical 
conditioning  of  human  pupillary  dilation.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  S4, 
467-474. 

Ghent,  L.  (1957) :  Some  effects  of  deprivation  on  eating  and  drinking 
behavior.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  SO,  172-176. 

Gilbert,  R.  W.   (1936):  The  effect  of  noninformative  shock  upon 


REFERENCES  373 

maze  learning  and  retention  with  human  subjects.  J.  exp.  Psychol., 
19,  456-466. 

Gilbert,  R.  W.  (1937):  A  further  study  of  the  effect  of  noninforma- 
tive  shock  upon  learning.  J.  exp.  Psychol.,  20,  396-407. 

Gilchrist,  J.  C.,  and  L.  S.  Nesberg  (1952):  Need  and  perceptual 
change  in  need-related  objects.  /.  exp.  Psychol.,  44,  369-376. 

Gilhousen,  H.  C.  (1938) :  Temporal  relations  in  anticipatory  reactions 
of  the  white  rat  in  a  maze.  /.  comp.  Psychol.,  26,  163-175. 

Glanzer,  M.  (1953):  The  role  of  stimulus  satiation  in  spontaneous 
alternation.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  45,  387-393. 

Glanzer,  M.  (1958):  Curiosity,  exploratory  drive,  and  stimulus  satia- 
tion. Psychol.  Bull,  55,  302-315. 

Grice,  G.  R.,  and  J.  D.  Davis  (1957):  Effect  of  irrelevant  thirst 
motivation  on  a  response  learned  with  food  reward.  J.  exp. 
Psychol,  53,  347-352. 

Grice,  G.  R.,  and  E.  Saltz  (1950):  The  generalization  of  an  instru- 
mental response  to  stimuli  varying  in  the  size  dimension.  J.  exp. 
Psychol,  40,  702-708. 

Grossman,  M.  I.  (1955):  Integration  of  current  views  on  the  regula- 
tion of  hunger  and  appetite.  In  R.  W.  Miner  (ed.).  The  regula- 
tion of  hunger  and  appetite.  Ann.  N.  Y.  Acad.  Sci.,  63,  Art.  1, 
New  York:  N.  Y.  Acad.  Sci. 

Guthrie,  E.  R.  (1935) :  The  psychology  of  learning.  New  York:  Harper 
&  Brothers. 

Guthrie,  E.  R.,  and  G.  P.  Horton  (1946) :  Cats  in  a  puzzle  box.  New 
York:  Holt,  Rinehart  and  Winston,  Inc. 

Gwinn,  G.  T.  (1951):  Resistance  to  extinction  of  learned  fear-drives. 
/.  exp.  Psychol,  42,  6-12. 

Haigh,  G.  V.,  and  D.  W.  Fiske  (1952):  Corroboration  of  personal 
values  as  selective  factors  in  perception.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol, 
47,  394-398. 

Hall,  C.  S.,  and  G.  Lindzey  (1957):  Theories  of  personality.  New 
York:  John  Wiley  &  Sons,  Inc. 

Hall,  J.  F.,  and  P.  V.  Hanford  (1954):  Activity  as  a  function  of  a 
restricted  feeding  schedule.  /.  comp.  physiol  Psychol,  47,  362- 
363. 

Hamilton,  G.  V.  (1916):  A  study  of  perseverance  reactions  in  pri- 
mates and  rodents.  Behav.  Monogr.,  3,  No.  2  (Whole  No.  13). 

Haner,  C.  F.,  and  P.  A.  Brown  (1955) :  Clarification  of  the  instigation 
to  action  concept  in  the  frustration-aggression  hypothesis.  /. 
abnorm.  soc.  Psychol,  51,  204-206. 

Harlow,  H.  F.  (1953):  Motivation  as  a  factor  in  the  acquisition  of 
new  responses.  In  Current  theory  and  research  in  motivation:  a 
symposium.  Lincoln,  Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Heath,  R.  G.  (1954) :  Behavioral  changes  following  destructive  lesions 
in  the  subcortical  structures  of  the  forebrain  in  cats.  In  R.  G. 


374  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

Heath  (ed.),  Studies  in  schizophrenia;  a  multidisciplinary  ap- 
proach to  mid-brain  relationships.  Cambridge,  Mass.:  Harvard 
University  Press. 

Heathers,  G.  L.,  and  P.  Arakehan  (1941):  The  relation  between 
strength  of  drive  and  rate  of  extinction  of  a  bar-pressing  reaction 
in  the  rat.  /.  gen.  Psychol,  24,  243-258. 

Hebb,  D.  O.  (1949) :  The  organization  of  behavior.  New  York:  John 
Wiley  &  Sons,  Inc. 

Hebb,  D.  O.  (1955):  Drives  and  the  c.n.s.  (conceptual  nervous  sys- 
tem). Psychol.  Rev.,  62,  243-254. 

Hedlund,  J.  L.  (1953):  Construction  and  evaluation  of  an  objective 
test  of  achievement  imagery.  Unpublished  doctoral  dissertation. 
State  University  of  Iowa. 

Hilden,  A.  H.  (1937):  An  action  current  study  of  the  conditioned 
hand  withdrawal.  In  L.  E.  Travis  (ed.),  Studies  in  Clinical  Psy- 
chology. Psychol.  Monogr.,  49,  No.  1  (Whole  No.  217). 

Hilgard,  E.  R.,  and  D.  G.  Marquis  (1935):  Acquisition,  extinction, 
and  retention  of  conditioned  lid  responses  to  light  in  dogs.  /. 
comp.  Psychol,  19,  29-58. 

Hilgard,  E.  R.,  and  D.  G.  Marquis  (1940):  Conditioning  and  learn- 
ing. New  York:  Appleton-Century-Crofts,  Inc. 

Hilgard,  E.  R.,  L.  V.  Jones,  and  S.  J.  Kaplan  (1951):  Conditioned 
discrimination  as  related  to  anxiety.  J.  exp.  Psychol,  42,  94-99. 

Hillman,  B.,  W.  S.  Hunter,  and  G.  A.  Kimble  (1953) :  The  effect  of 
drive  level  on  the  maze  performance  of  the  white  rat.  /.  comp. 
physiol  Psychol,  46,  87-89. 

Holder,  E.  (1951):  Response  strength  as  a  function  of  changes  in 
the  length  of  the  delay  interval.  Unpublished  master's  thesis. 
New  Mexico  State  College.  Cited  in  Holder,  Marx,  Holder  and 
Collier,  1957. 

Holder,  W.  B.,  M.  H.  Marx,  E.  E.  Holder,  and  G.  Collier  (1957): 
Response  strength  as  a  function  of  delay  of  reward  in  a  runway. 
/.  exp.  Psychol,  53,  316-323. 

Hollenberg,  E.,  and  M.  Sperry  (1951):  Some  antecedents  of  aggres- 
sion and  effects  of  frustration  in  doll  play.  Personality:  topical 
symposia,  1,  32-43. 

Holton,  R.  B.  (1956) :  Variables  affecting  the  change  in  instrumental 
response  magnitude  after  reward  cessation.  Unpublished  doctoral 
dissertation,  State  University  of  Iowa. 

Horenstein,  B.  R.  (1951):  Performance  of  conditioned  responses  as  a 
function  of  strength  of  hunger  drive.  /.  comp.  physiol  Psychol, 
44,  210-224. 

Hovland,  C.  I.  (1936) :  "Inhibition  of  reinforcement"  and  phenomena 
of  experimental  extinction.  Proc.  Nat.  Acad.  Sci.,  Washington,  22, 
430-433. 


REFERENCES  375 

Hovland,  C.  I.,  and  A.  H.  Riesen  (1940) :  Magnitude  of  galvanic  and 
vasomotor  response  as  a  function  of  stimulus  intensity.  /.  gen. 
Psychol,  23,  103-121. 

Howes,  D.  H.,  and  R.  L.  Solomon  (1950):  A  note  on  McGinnies' 
"Emotionality  and  perceptual  defense."  Psychol.  Rev.,  S7,  229- 
234. 

Hughes,  J.  B.,  II,  J.  L.  Sprague,  and  A.  W.  Bendig  (1954):  Anxiety 
level,  response  alternation,  and  performance  in  serial  learning.  /. 
Psychol,  38,  421-426. 

Hull,  C.  L.  (1931):  Goal  attraction  and  directing  ideas  conceived  as 
habit  phenomena.  Psychol  Rev.,  38,  487-506. 

Hull,  C.  L.  (1937) :  Mind,  mechanism,  and  adaptive  behavior.  Psychol 
Rev.,  44,  1-32. 

Hull,  C.  L.  (1943) :  Principles  of  behavior.  New  York:  Appleton-Cen- 
tury-Crofts,  Inc. 

Hull,  C.  L.  (1951):  Essentials  of  behavior.  New  Haven,  Conn.:  Yale 
University  Press. 

Hull,  C.  L.  (1952) :  A  behavior  system.  New  Haven,  Conn.:  Yale  Uni- 
versity Press. 

Hunt,  H.  F.,  and  J.  V.  Brady  (1951):  Some  effects  of  electroconvul- 
sive shock  on  a  conditioned  emotional  response  ("anxiety"). 
/.  comp.  physiol  Psychol,  44,  88-98. 

Hunt,  H.  F.,  and  L.  S.  Otis  (1953):  Conditioned  and  unconditioned 
emotional  defecation  in  the  rat.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  46, 
378-382. 

Hurley,  J.  R.  (1955) :  The  Iowa  picture  interpretation  test:  a  multiple- 
choice  variation  of  the  TAT.  /.  consult.  Psychol,  19,  372-376. 

Hurley,  J.  R.  (1957):  Achievement  imagery  and  motivational  instruc- 
tions as  determinants  of  verbal  learning.  /.  Pers.,  25,  274-282. 

Ingram,  W.  R.,  J.  R.  Knott,  and  W.  D.  Chiles  (1953):  Behavioral 
and  electrocortical  effects  of  diencephalic  stimulation  in  un- 
anesthetized,  unrestrained  cats.  XJX  Internat.  Physiol.  Congr., 
487-488. 
anowitz,  H.  D.,  and  M.  I.  Grossman  (1949):  Some  factors  affecting 
the  food  intake  of  normal  dogs  and  dogs  with  esophagostomy 
and  gastric  fistula.  Amer.  J.  Physiol,  159,  143-148. 
asper,  H.  H.,  (ed.)  (1958) :  Reticular  formation  of  the  brain.  Boston: 

Little,  Brown  &  Company, 
enkin,  N.  (1957):  Affective  processes  in  perception.  Psychol.  Bull, 

54,  100-127. 
erome,  E.  A.,  J.  A.  Moody,  T.  J.  Connor,  and  M.  B.  Fernandez 
(1957):    Learning   in   a   multiple-door   situation    under   various 
drive  states.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  50,  588-591. 
ohanson,  A.  M.  (1922) :  The  influence  of  incentive  and  punishment 
upon  reaction  time.  Arch.  Psychol,  8,  No.  54. 


376  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Johnston,   R.   A.    (1955):   The   effects   of   achievement   imagery   on 

maze-learning  performance.  J.  Pers.,  24,  145-152. 
Johnston,  R.  A.  (1957):  A  methodological  analysis  of  several  revised 

forms  of  the  Iowa  Picture  Interpretation  Test.  J.  Pers.,  25,  283- 

293. 
Jones,  M.  C.    (1924):   The  elimination  of  children's  fears.  J.  exp. 

Psychol,  7,  382-390. 
Kabrick,  R.  P.,  and  I.  E.  Farber  (1952):  Effect  of  electric  shock  on 

speed  of  reaction.  Amer.  Psychologist,  7,  586.  (Abstract.) 
Kagan,  J.,  and  M.   Berkun    (1954):   The  reward  value  of  running 

activity.  J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  47,  108. 
Kalish,  H.  I.   (1954):  Strength  of  fear  as  a  function  of  the  number 

of  acquisition  and  extinction  trials.  /.  exp.  Psychol.,  47,  1-9. 
Kaplan,  M.    (1952):  The  effects  of  noxious  stimulus  intensity  and 

duration  during  intermittent  reinforcement  of  escape  behavior. 

J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  45,  538-549. 
Kendler,  H.  H.  (1945):  Drive  interaction:  I.  Learning  as  a  function 

of  the  simultaneous  presence  of  the  hunger  and  thirst  drives. 

/.  exp.  Psychol,  35,  96-109. 
Ketchel,  R.  G.   (1955):  Performance  in  instrumental  learning  as  a 

function  of  shock  intensity.  Unpublished  master's  thesis,  State 

University  of  Iowa. 
Kimble,  G.  A.  (1951) :  Behavior  strength  as  a  function  of  the  intensitv 

of  the  hunger  drive.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  41,  341-348. 
Kish,  G.  B.  (1955):  Learning  when  the  onset  of  illumination  is  used 

as   reinforcing   stimulus.   /.   comp.   physiol.   Psychol,   48,    261- 

264. 
Klein,  G.  S.,  H.  J.  Schlesinger,  and  D.  E.  Meister  (1951):  The  effect 

of  personal  values  on  perception:  an  experimental  critique.  Psy- 
chol Rev.,  58,  96-112. 
Kling,  J.  W.,  L.  Horowitz,  and  J.  E.  Delhagen   (1956):  Light  as  a 

positive  reinforcer  for  rat  responding.  Psychol.  Rep.,  2,  537-340. 
Knott,  J.  R.,  W.  R.  Ingram,  and  R.  E.  Correll  (I960):  Some  effects 

of  subcortical  stimulation  on  the  bar  press  response.  A.  M.  A. 

Arch.  Neurol,  2,  476-484. 
Koch,  S.,  and  W.  J.  Daniel   (1945):  The  effect  of  satiation  on  the 

behavior  mediated   by  a   habit   of   maximum   strength.   J.   exp. 

Psychol,  35,  167-187. 
Lacy,  O.  W.,  N.  Lewinger,  and  J.  F.  Adamson  (1953):  Foreknowl- 
edge as  a  factor  affecting  perceptual  defense  and  alertness.  /.  exp. 

Psychol,  45,  169-174. 
Lambert,  W.  W.,  R.  L.  Solomon,  and  P.  D.  Watson  (1949):  Rein- 
forcement and  extinction  as  factors  in  size  estimation.  /.  exp. 

Psychol,  39,  637-641. 
Lawrence,  D.   LI.,   and  W.  A.  Mason    (1955):    Intake  and  weight 


REFERENCES  377 

adjustments  in  rats  to  changes  in   feeding  schedule.  J.  comp. 
physiol  Psychol,  48,  43-46. 

Lawson,  R.,  and  M.  H.  Marx  (1958) :  Frustration:  theory  and  experi- 
ment. Genet.  Psychol.  Monogr.,  SI,  393-464. 

Lazarus,  R.  S.,  J.  Deese,  and  S.  F.  Osier  (1952):  The  effects  of  psy- 
chological stress  upon  performance.  Psychol.  Bull,  49,  293-317. 

Lazarus,  R.  S.,  C.  W.  Eriksen,  and  C.  P.  Fonda  (1951):  Personality 
dynamics  and  auditory  perceptual  recognition.  J.  Pers.,  19,  471- 
482. 

Lazarus,  R.  S.,  and  R.  A.  McCleary  (1951) :  Autonomic  discrimination 
without  awareness:  a  study  of  subception.  Psychol.  Rev.,  S8, 
113-122. 

Lazarus,  R.  S.,  H.  Yousem,  and  D.  Arenberg  (1953):  Hunger  and 
perception.  J.  Pers.,  21,  312-328. 

Levine,  R.,  L  Chein,  and  G.  Murphy  (1942):  The  relation  of  the 
intensity  of  a  need  to  the  amount  of  perceptual  distortion:  a 
preliminary  report.  /.  Psychol.,  13,  283-293. 

Lewin,  K.  (1931):  Environmental  forces  in  child  behavior  and  devel- 
opment. In  C.  Murchison  (ed.),  A  handbook  of  child  psychology. 
Worcester,  Mass.:  Clark  University  Press. 

Lewin,  K.  (1938):  The  conceptual  representation  and  the  measure- 
ment of  psychological  forces.  Contr.  Psychol.  Theor.,  I,  No.  4. 

Libby,  A.  (1951):  Two  variables  in  the  acquisition  of  depressant 
properties  by  a  stimulus.  J.  exp.  Psychol.,  42,  100-107. 

Lindsley,  D.  B.  (1951):  Emotion.  In  S.  S.  Stevens  (ed.),  Handbook 
of  experimental  psychology.  New  York:  John  Wiley  &  Sons,  Inc. 

Lindsley,  D.  B.  (1957):  Psychophysiology  and  motivation.  In  M.  R. 
Jones  (ed.),  Nebraska  symposium  on  motivation.  Lincoln,  Nebr.: 
University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Lindsley,  D.  B.,  J.  Bowden,  and  H.  W.  Magoun  (1949) :  Effect  upon 
EEG  of  acute  injury  to  the  brain  stem  activating  system.  EEC 
din.  Neurophysiol,  I,  475-486. 

Lindzev,  G.  (ed.)  (1959) :  Assessment  of  human  motives.  New  York: 
Holt,  Rinehart  and  Winston. 

Loess,  H.  B.  (1952) :  The  effect  of  variation  of  motivational  level  and 
changes  in  motivational  level  on  performance  in  learning.  Unpub- 
lished doctoral  dissertation.  State  University  of  Iowa. 

Logan,  F.  A.  (1952) :  The  role  of  delay  of  reinforcement  in  determin- 
ing reaction  potential.  J.  exp.  Psychol,  43,  393-399. 

Logan,  F.  A.,  D.  L.  Olmstead,  B.  S.  Rosner,  R.  D.  Schwartz,  and 
C.  M.  Stevens  (1955):  Behavior  theory  and  social  science.  New 
Haven,  Conn.:  Yale  University  Press. 

Lowell,  E.  L.  (1952cz):  The  effect  of  conflict  on  motivation.  Unpub- 
lished doctoral  dissertation.  Harvard  University.  Cited  in  Whit- 
ing and  Child,  1953. 


378  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Lowell,  E.  L.  (1952b) :  The  effect  of  need  for  achievement  on  learning 
and  speed  of  performance.  J.  Psychol.,  33,  31-40. 

Ludvigson,  W.  H.  (1958) :  Visual  identification  thresholds  as  a  func- 
tion of  attitude.   (Unpublished.  Personal  communication.) 

Lysak,  W.  (1954):  The  effects  of  punishment  upon  syllable  recogni- 
tion thresholds.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  47,  343-350. 

Lysak,  W.,  and  J.  C.  Gilchrist  (1955):  Value,  equivocality,  and  goal 
availability  as  determinants  of  size  judgments.  /.  Pers.,  23, 
500-501. 

McAllister,  W.  R.  (1953) :  The  effect  on  eyehd  conditioning  of  shift- 
ing the  CS-US  interval.  J.  exp.  Psychol.,  4S,  423-428. 

McCandless,  B.  R.,  and  A.  Castaneda  (1956):  Anxiety  in  children, 
school  achievement,  and  intelligence.  Child  Develpm.,  27,  379- 
382. 

McClelland,  D.  C.  (1951):  Personality.  New  York:  William  Sloane 
Associates. 

McClelland,  D.  C.  (1956) :  The  measurement  of  human  needs.  Final 
Report,  Contract  N7  onr  463,  NR  171-363,  OfEce  of  Naval  Re- 
search, Aug.  31,  1956. 

McClelland,  D.  C,  and  J.  W.  Atkinson  (1948):  The  projective  ex- 
pression of  needs:  I.  The  effects  of  different  intensities  of  the 
hunger  drive  on  perception.  /.  Psychol.,  2S,  205-222. 

McClelland,  D.  C,  J.  W.  Atkinson,  R.  A.  Clark,  and  E.  L.  Lowell 
(1953) :  The  achievement  motive.  New  York:  Appleton-Century- 
Crofts,  Inc. 

McClelland,  D.  C,  and  A.  M.  Liberman  (1949):  The  effect  of  need 
for  achievement  on  recognition  of  need-related  words.  /.  Pers.,  18, 
236-251. 

MacCorquodale,  K.,  and  P.  E.  Meehl  (1953):  Preliminary  sugges- 
tions as  to  a  formalization  of  expectancy  theory.  Psychol.  Rev., 
60,  55-63. 

McDougall,  W.  (1917):  An  introduction  to  social  psychology,  12th 
ed.  Boston:  Luce. 

McGinnies,  E.  (1949) :  Emotionality  and  perceptual  defense.  Psychol. 
Rev.,  S6,  244-251. 

McGinnies,  E.  (1950):  Discussion  of  Howes'  and  Solomon's  note  on 
"Emotionality  and  perceptual  defense."  Psychol.  Rev.,  57,  235- 
240. 

McGinnies,  E.,  and  H.  Sherman  (1952) :  Generalization  of  perceptual 
defense.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  47,  81-85. 

Madsen,  K.  B.  (1959):  Theories  of  motivation.  Copenhagen:  Munks- 
gaard. 

Malmo,  R.  B.  (1957):  Anxiety  and  behavioral  arousal.  Psychol.  Rev., 
64,  276-287. 

Malmo,  R.  B.  (1958) :  Measurement  of  drive:  an  unsolved  problem  in 


REFERENCES  379 

psychology.  In  M.  R.  Jones  (ed.),  Nebraska  symposium  on  mo- 
tivation. Lincoln,  Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Marx,  M.  H.  (1956):  Some  relations  between  frustration  and  drive. 
In  M.  R.  Jones  (ed.),  Nebraska  s}>mposium  on  motivation.  Lin- 
coln, Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Marx,  M.  H.,  R.  L.  Henderson,  and  C.  L.  Roberts  (1955):  Positive 
reinforcement  of  the  bar-pressing  response  by  a  light  stimulus 
following  dark  operant  pretests  with  no  aftereffect.  /.  comp. 
physiol.  Psychol,  48,  73-76. 

Marzocco,  F.  N.  (1951):  Frustration  effect  as  a  function  of  drive 
level,  habit  strength,  and  distribution  of  trials  during  extinction. 
Unpublished  doctoral  dissertation.  State  University  of  Iowa. 

Masserman,  J.  H.  (1946):  Principles  of  dynamic  psychiatry.  Philadel- 
phia: W.  B.  Saunders  Company. 

Mausner,  B.,  and  A.  Siegel  (1950) :  The  effect  of  variation  in  "value" 
on  perceptual  thresholds.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  45,  760-763. 

Melton,  A.  W.  (1941):  Learning.  In  W.  S.  Monroe  (ed.).  Encyclo- 
pedia of  educational  research.  New  York:  The  Macmillan  Com- 
pany. 

Meryman,  J.  J.  (1952) :  Magnitude  of  startle  response  as  a  function  of 
hunger  and  fear.  Unpublished  master's  thesis.  State  University  of 
Iowa. 

Meryman,  J.  J.  (1953) :  The  magnitude  of  an  unconditioned  GSR  as 
a  function  of  fear  conditioned  at  a  long  CS-UCS  interval.  Unpub- 
lished doctoral  dissertation.  State  University  of  Iowa. 

Meyer,  D.  R.  (1951):  Food  deprivation  and  discrimination  reversal 
learning  by  monkeys.  /.  exp.  Psychol.,  41,  10-16. 

Meyer,  D.  R.  (1953):  On  the  interaction  of  simultaneous  responses. 
Psychol.  Bull,  SO,  204-220. 

Meyer,  D.  R.,  and  M.  E.  Noble  (1958):  Summation  of  manifest 
anxiety  and  muscular  tension,  /.  exp.  Psychol,  SS,  599-602. 

Miller,  N.  E.  (1944):  Experimental  studies  of  conflict.  In  J.  McV. 
Hunt  (ed.).  Personality  and  the  behavior  disorders.  Vol.  I.  New 
York:  The  Ronald  Press  Company. 

Miller,  N.  E.  (1948d):  Studies  of  fear  as  an  acquirable  drive:  I.  Fear 
as  motivation  and  fear-reduction  as  reinforcement  in  the  learning 
of  new  responses.  J.  exp.  Psychol,  38,  89-101. 

Miller,  N.  E.  (1948b) :  Tlieory  and  experiment  relating  psychoanabtic 
displacement  to  stimulus-response  generalization.  /.  abnorm. 
soc.  Psychol,  43,  155-178. 

Miller,  N.  E.  (1951):  Learnable  drives  and  rewards.  In  S.  S.  Stevens 
(ed.).  Handbook  of  experimental  psychology.  New  York:  John 
Wiley  &  Sons,  Inc. 

Miller,  N.  E.  (1958):  Central  stimulation  and  other  new  approaches 
to  motivation  and  reward.  Amer.  Psychologist,  13,  100-108. 


380  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Miller,  N.  E.  (1959) :  Liberalization  of  basic  S-R  concepts:  Extensions 
to  conflict  behavior,  motivation,  and  social  learning.  In  S.  Koch 
(ed.).  Psychology:  a  study  of  a  science.  Vol.  2.  General  sys- 
tematic formulations,  learning,  and  special  processes.  New  York: 
McGraw-Hill  Book  Companv,  Inc. 

Miller,  N.  E.,  and  M.  Davis  (1943):  A  theoretical  and  experimental 
analysis  of  conflict  behavior:  IV.  The  influence  of  the  positions  of 
reward  and  punishment  in  the  response  sequence.  (Unpublished 
paper.  Cited  in  Miller,  1944.) 

Miller,  N.  E.,  and  J.  Dollard  (1941):  Social  learning  and  imitation. 
New  Haven,  Conn.:  Yale  University  Press. 

Miller,  N.  E.,  and  D.  H.  Lawrence  (1950):  Studies  of  fear  as  an  ac- 
quirable drive:  III.  Effect  of  strength  of  electric  shock  as  a  pri- 
mary drive  and  of  number  of  trials  with  the  primarv  drive  on 
the  strength  of  fear.  (Unpublished  paper.  Cited  in  Miller,  19 5 1.) 

Miller,  N.  E.,  R.  I.  Sampliner,  and  P.  Woodrow  (1957):  Thirst- 
reducing  effects  of  water  by  stomach  fistula  vs.  water  by  mouth 
measured  by  both  a  consummatory  and  an  instrumental  response. 
/.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  SO,  1-5. 

Miller,  N.  E.,  and  S.  S.  Stevenson.  (1936):  Agitated  behavior  of  rats 
during  experimental  extinction  and  a  curve  of  spontaneous  re- 
covery. /.  comp.  Psychol.,  21,  205-231. 

Miller,  W.  C,  and  J.  E.  Greene  (1954) :  Generalization  of  an  avoid- 
ance response  to  varving  intensities  of  sound.  J.  comp.  physiol. 
Psychol,  47,  136-139. 

Miner,  R.  W.  (ed.)  (1955):  The  regulation  of  hunger  and  appetite. 
Ann.  N.Y.  Acad.  Sci.,  63,  Art.  1.,  New  York:  N.Y.  Acad.  Sci. 

Moeller,  G.  (1954):  The  CS-UCS  interval  in  GSR  conditioning.  /. 
exp.  Psychol,  48,  162-166. 

Montgomery,  K.  C.  (1952):  A  test  of  two  explanations  of  spon- 
taneous alternation.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  4S,  287-293. 

Montgomery,  K.  C.  (1953):  Exploratory  behavior  as  a  function  of 
"similarity"  of  stimulus  situations.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol, 
46,  129-133. 

Montgomery,  K.  C.  (1954) :  The  role  of  the  exploratory  drive  in  learn- 
ing. J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  47,  60-64. 

Montgomery,  K.  C.  (1955):  The  relation  between  fear  induced  by 
novel  stimulation  and  exploratory  behavior.  /.  comp.  physiol. 
Psychol,  48,  254-260. 

Montgomery,  K.  C,  and  M.  Segall  (1955):  Discrimination  learning 
based  upon  the  exploratory  drive.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  48, 
225-228. 

Morgan,  C.  T.  (1943):  Physiological  psychology.  New  York:  Mc- 
Graw-Hill Book  Company,  Inc. 


REFERENCES  381 

Morgan,  C.  T.  (1957):  Physiological  mechanisms  of  motivation.  In 
M.  R.  Jones  (ed.),  Nebraska  symposium  on  motivation.  Lincoln, 
Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Morgan,  C.  T.,  and  E.  Stellar  (1950):  Physiological  psychology,  2d 
ed.  New  York:  McGraw-Hill  Book  Company,  Inc. 

Moruzzi,  G.,  and  H.  W.  Magoun  (1949) :  Brain  stem  reticular  forma- 
tion and  activation  of  the  EEG.  EEG  din.  Neurophysiol.,  1, 
455-473. 

Mowrer,  O.  H.  (1939):  A  stimulus-response  analysis  of  anxiety  and 
its  role  as  a  reinforcing  agent.  Psychol.  Rev.,  46,  553-565. 

Mowrer,  O.  H.  (1947) :  On  the  dual  nature  of  learning — a  re-interpre- 
tation of  "conditioning"  and  "problem-solving."  Harvard  Educ. 
Rev.,  17,  102-148. 

Mowrer,  O.  H.  (1950):  Learning  theory  and  personality  dynamics. 
New  York:  The  Ronald  Press  Company. 

Mowrer,  O.  H.  (1951):  Two-factor  learning  theory:  summary  and 
comment.  Psychol.  Rev.,  58,  350-354. 

Mowrer,  O.  H.,  and  E.  G.  Aiken  (1954):  Contiguity  vs.  drive-reduc- 
tion in  conditioned  fear:  temporal  variations  in  conditioned  and 
unconditioned  stimulus.  Amer.  J.  Psychol.,  67,  26-38. 

Mowrer,  O.  H.,  and  R.  R.  Lamoreaux  (1942):  Avoidance  condition- 
ing and  signal  duration — a  study  of  secondary  motivation  and  re- 
ward. Psychol.  Monogr.,  S4,  No.  5  (Whole  No.  247). 

Mowrer,  O.  H.,  and  L.  N.  Solomon  (1954):  Contiguity  vs.  drive- 
reduction  in  conditioned  fear:  the  proximity  and  abruptness  of 
drive-reduction.  Amer.  J.  Psychol.,  67,  15-25. 

Muenzinger,  K.  F.  (1934):  Motivation  in  learning.  II.  The  function 
of  electric  shock  for  right  and  wrong  responses  in  human  subjects. 
/.  exp.  Psychol,  17,  439-448. 

Murfin,  F.  L.  (1954) :  The  relationship  of  fear  to  the  CS-UCS  interval 
in  acquisition  and  the  CS-duration  in  extinction.  Unpublished 
doctoral  dissertation.  State  University  of  Iowa. 

Murphy,  D.  B.  (1953):  Recognition  and  recall  as  a  function  of  fre- 
quency, shock,  and  individual  differences  variables.  Unpublished 
doctoral  dissertation.  State  University  of  Iowa. 

Murray,  H.  A.  (1938) :  Explorations  in  personality.  New  York:  Oxford 
University  Press. 

Myers,  A.  K.,  and  N.  E.  Miller  (1954) :  Failure  to  find  a  learned  drive 
based  on  hunger;  evidence  for  learning  motivated  by  "explora- 
tion." J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  47,  428-436. 

Myers,  T.  I.  (1952):  An  experimental  investigation  of  the  effect  of 
hunger  drive  upon  the  brightness  discrimination  learning  of 
the  rat.  Unpublished  doctoral  dissertation.  State  University 
of  Iowa. 


382  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Nagaty,  M.  O.  (1951) :  The  effect  of  reinforcement  on  closely  follow- 
ing S-R  connections:  I.  The  effect  of  a  backward  conditioning 
procedure  on  the  extinction  of  conditioned  avoidance.  /.  exp. 
Psychol,  42,  239-246. 

Neel,  A.  F.  (1954) :  Conflict,  recognition  time  and  defensive  behavior. 
Amer.  Psychologist,  9,  437-438.  (Abstract.) 

Nissen,  H.  W.  (1954) :  The  nature  of  the  drive  as  innate  determinant 
of  behavioral  organization.  In  M.  R.  Jones  (ed.),  Nebraska  sym- 
posium on  motivation.  Lincoln,  Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska 
Press. 

Olds,  J.  (1955) :  Physiological  mechanisms  of  reward.  In  M.  R.  Jones 
(ed.),  Nebraska  symposium  on  motivation.  Lincoln,  Nebr.: 
University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Olds,  J.  (1956d):  A  preliminary  mapping  of  electrical  reinforcing  ef- 
fects in  the  rat  brain.  J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  49,  281-285. 

Olds,  J.  ( 1956b) :  Runway  and  maze  behavior  controlled  by  basomedial 
forebrain  stimulation  in  the  rat.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  49, 
507-512. 

Olds,  J.  (1958):  Effects  of  hunger  and  male  sex  hormone  on  self- 
stimulation  of  the  brain.  J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  SI,  320-324. 

Olds,  J.,  and  P.  Milner  (1954):  Positive  reinforcement  produced  by 
electrical  stimulation  of  septal  area  and  other  regions  of  rat  brain. 
/.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  47,  419-427. 

Osgood,  C.  E.  (1953) :  Method  and  theory  in  experimental  psychology. 
New  York:  Oxford  University  Press. 

Palermo,  D.  S.,  A.  Castaneda,  and  B.  R.  McCandless  (1956):  The 
relationship  of  anxiety  in  children  to  performance  in  a  complex 
learning  task.  Child  Develpm.,  27,  333-337. 

Passey,  G.  E.  (1948):  The  influence  of  intensity  of  unconditioned 
stimulus  upon  acquisition  of  a  conditioned  response.  /.  exp.  Psy- 
chol, 38,  420-428. 

Pavlov,  I.  P.  (1927) :  Conditioned  reflexes.  London:  Oxford  University 
Press. 

Perin,  C.  T.  (1942):  Behavior  potentially  as  a  joint  function  of  the 
amount  of  training  and  the  degree  of  hunger  at  the  time  of  ex- 
tinction. /.  exp.  Psychol,  30,  93-113. 

Postman,  L.  (1947):  The  history  and  present  status  of  the  law  of 
effect.  Psychol  Bull,  44,  489-563. 

Postman,  L.  (1953d):  The  experimental  analysis  of  motivational  fac- 
tors in  perception.  In  Current  theory  and  research  in  motivation: 
a  symposium.  Lincoln,  Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Postman,  L.  (1953jb) :  Comments  on  papers  by  Professors  Brown  and 
Harlow.  In  Current  theory  and  research  in  motivation:  a  sym- 
posium. Lincoln,  Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Postman,  L.,  W.  C.  Bronson,  and  G.  L.  Cropper  (1953):  Is  there 


REFERENCES  383 

a  mechanism  of  perceptual  defense?  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  48, 
215-224. 

Postman,  L.,  J.  S.  Bruner,  and  E.  McGinnies  (1948) :  Personal  values 
as  selective  factors  in  perception.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  43, 
142-154. 

Postman,  L.,  and  R.  S.  Crutchfield  (1952):  The  interaction  of  need, 
set  and  stimulus-structure  in  a  cognitive  task.  Amer.  J.  Psychol., 
65,  196-217. 

Powloski,  R.  F.  (1953):  The  effects  of  combining  hunger  and  thirst 
motives  in  a  discrimination  habit.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  46, 
434-437. 

Proshansky,  H.,  and  G.  Murphy  (1942):  The  effects  of  reward  and 
punishment  on  perception.  J.  Psychol.,  13,  293-305. 

Pustell,  T.  E.  (1957):  The  experimental  induction  of  perceptual 
vigilance  and  defense.  J.  Pers.,  25,  425-438. 

Ramond,  C.  K.  (1954):  Performance  in  selective  learning  as  a  func- 
tion of  hunger.  /.  exp.  Psychol.,  48,  265-270. 

Reece,  M.  M.  (1954) :  The  effect  of  shock  on  recognition  thresholds. 
/.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  49,  165-172. 

Reese,  T.  W.  (1943) :  The  application  of  the  theory  of  physical  meas- 
urement to  the  measurement  of  psychological  magnitudes,  with 
three  experimental  examples.  Psychol.  Monogr.,  55,  No.  3 
(Whole  No.  251). 

Reynolds,  R.  W.  (1958):  The  relationship  between  stimulation  volt- 
age and  rate  of  hypothalamic  self-stimulation  in  the  rat.  J.  comp. 
physiol.  Psychol,  51,  193-198. 

Richter,  C.  P.  (1933):  The  effect  of  early  gonadectomy  on  the  gross 
bodily  activity  of  rats.  Endocrinology,  17,  445-450. 

Roberts,  W.  W.  (1958):  Both  rewarding  and  punishing  effects  from 
stimulation  of  posterior  hypothalamus  of  cat  with  same  electrode 
at  same  intensity.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol.,  51,  400-407. 

Rohrer,  J.  H.  (1949) :  A  motivational  state  resulting  from  non-reward. 
/.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  42,  476-485. 

Rosenbaum,  G.  (1953) :  Stimulus  generalization  as  a  function  of  level 
of  experimentally  induced  anxiety.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  45,  35-43. 

Rosenthal,  B.  G.  (1951):  Attitude  towards  money,  need,  and  meth- 
ods of  presentation  as  determinants  of  perception  of  coins  from 
six  to  ten  years  of  age.  Amer.  Psychologist,  6,  317.  (Abstract.) 

Rossi,  G.  F.,  and  A.  Zanchetti  (1957):  The  brain  stem  reticular  for- 
mation: anatomy  and  physiology.  Arch,  ital  Biol,  95,  199-435. 

Roussel,  J.  (1952):  Frustration  effect  as  a  function  of  repeated  non- 
reinforcements  and  as  a  function  of  the  consistency  of  reinforce- 
ment prior  to  the  introduction  of  nonreinforcement.  Unpub- 
lished master's  thesis,  Tulane  University.  Cited  in  Amsel,  1958. 

Saltzman,  I.,  and  S.  Koch  (1948):  The  effect  of  low  intensities  of 


384  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

hunger  on  the  behavior  mediated  by  a  habit  of  maximum 
strength.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  38,  347-370.' 

Samuels,  I.  (1959):  Reticular  mechanisms  and  behavior.  Psvchol. 
Bull,  56,  1-25. 

Sanford,  R.  N.  (1936):  The  effects  of  abstinence  from  food  upon 
imaginal  processes:  a  preliminary  experiment.  /.  Psychol,  2,  129- 
136. 

Sanford,  R.  N.  (1937):  The  effects  of  abstinence  from  food  upon 
imaginal  processes:  a  further  experiment.  /.  Psychol,  3,  145- 
159. 

Schlosberg,  H.  (1937) :  The  relationship  between  success  and  the  laws 
of  conditioning.  Psychol  Rev.,  44,  379-394. 

Schlosberg,  H.  (1954):  Three  dimensions  of  emotion.  Psychol  Rev., 
61,  81-88. 

Seward,  }.  P.  (1951) :  Experimental  evidence  for  the  motivating  func- 
tion of  reward.  Psychol  Bull,  48,  130-149. 

Seward,  J.  P.  (1956) :  A  neurological  approach  to  motivation.  In  M.  R. 
Jones  (ed.),  Nebraska  symposium  on  motivation.  Lincoln,  Nebr.: 
University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Sheffield,  V.  F.  (1950):  Resistance  to  extinction  as  a  function  of  the 
distribution  of  extinction  trials.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  40,  305-313. 

Sheriffs,  A.  C.  (1948):  The  "intuition  questionnaire":  a  new  projec- 
tive test.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol,  43,  326-331 . 

Shirley,  M.  (1928):  Studies  in  activity.  II.  Activity  rhythms;  age  and 
activity;  activity  after  rest.  /.  comp.  Psychol,  8,  159-186. 

Sidman,  M.,  |.  V.  Brady,  }.  J.  Boren,  D.  G.  Conrad,  and  A.  Schul- 
man  (1955):  Reward  schedules  and  behavior  maintained  by  in- 
tracranial self-stimulation.  Science,  122,  830-831. 

Siegel,  P.  S.  (1943) :  Drive  shift,  a  conceptual  and  experimental  analy- 
sis. /.  comp.  Psychol,  35,  139-148. 

Siegel,  P.  S.  (1947) :  The  relationship  between  voluntary  water  intake, 
body  weight  loss,  and  number  of  hours  of  water  privation  in  the 
rat.  /.  comp.  physiol  Psychol,  40,  231-238. 

Siegel,  P.  S.,  and  J.  J.  Brantley  (1951):  The  relationship  of  emotion- 
ality to  the  consummatory  response  of  eating.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  42, 
304-306. 

Siegel,  P.  S.,  and  M.  F.  MacDonnell  (1954) :  A  repetition  of  the  Cal- 
vin-Bicknell-Sperling  study  of  conditioned  drive.  J.  comp.  physiol 
Psychol,  47,  250-252. 

Siegel,  P.  S.,  and  M.  Steinberg  (1949) :  Activity  level  as  a  function  of 
hunger.  /.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  42,  413-416. 

Skinner,  B.  F.  (1932):  Drive  and  reflex  strength.  /.  gen.  Psychol,  6, 
22-37. 

Skinner,  B.  F.  (1933):  The  measurement  of  spontaneous  acti\ity.  /. 
gen.  Psvchol,  9,  3-24. 


REFERENCES  385 

Skinner,  B.  F.  (1938) :  The  behavior  of  organisms.  New  York:  Apple- 
ton-Century-Crofts,  Inc. 

Slonaker,  J.  R.  (1912):  The  normal  activity  of  the  albino  rat  from 
birth  to  natural  death,  its  rate  of  growth  and  the  duration  of  life. 
/.  anim,  Behav.,  2,  20-42. 

Smith,  M.,  R.  Pool,  and  H.  Weinberg  (1959):  The  effect  of  pe- 
ripherally induced  shifts  in  water  balance  on  eating.  J.  comp. 
physiol.  Psychol,  S2,  289-293. 

Smith,  M.  P.,  and  P.  J.  Capretta  (1956):  Effects  of  drive  level  and 
experience  on  the  reward  value  of  saccharine  solutions.  J.  comp. 
physiol.  Psychol,  49,  553-557. 

Solley,  C.  M.,  and  R.  Lee  (1955) :  Perceived  size:  closure  versus  sym- 
bolic value.  Amer.  J.  Psychol,  68,  142-144. 

Solomon,  R.  L.,  and  D.  H.  Howes  (1951):  Word  frequency,  per- 
sonal values,  and  visual  duration  thresholds.  Psychol  Rev.,  58, 
256-270. 

Solomon,  R.  L.,  L.  J.  Kamin,  and  L.  C.  Wynne  (1953):  Traumatic 
avoidance  learning:  the  outcomes  of  several  extinction  procedures 
with  dogs.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol,  48,  291-302. 

Solomon,  R.  L.,  and  L.  C.  Wynne  (1953) :  Traumatic  avoidance  learn- 
ing: acquisition  in  normal  dogs.  Psychol  Monogr.,  67,  No.  4 
(Whole  No.  354). 

Solomon,  R.  L.,  and  L.  C.  Wynne  (1954):  Traumatic  avoidance 
learning:  the  principles  of  anxiety  conservation  and  partial  ir- 
reversibility. Psychol  Rev.,  61,  353-385. 

Sorokin,  P.  A.  (1942) :  Men  and  society  in  calamity.  New  York:  E.  P. 
Button  &  Co.,  Inc. 

Spence,  K.  W.  (1944) :  The  nature  of  theory  construction  in  contem- 
porary psychology.  Psychol.  Rev.,  SI,  47-68. 

Spence,  K.  W.  (1948) :  The  postulates  and  methods  of  'behaviorism.' 
Psychol.  Rev.,  SS,  67-78. 

Spence,  K.  W.  (1951d):  Theoretical  interpretations  of  learning.  In 
C.  P.  Stone  (ed.).  Comparative  psychology.  Englewood  Cliffs, 
N.J.:  Prentice-Hall,  Inc. 

Spence,  K.  W.  (1951b):  Theoretical  interpretations  of  learning.  In 
S.  S.  Stevens  (ed.).  Handbook  of  experimental  psychology.  New 
York:  John  Wiley  &  Sons,  Inc. 

Spence,  K.  W.  (1956):  Behavior  theory  and  conditioning.  New 
Haven,  Conn.:  Yale  University  Press. 

Spence,  K.  W.  (1958) :  A  theory  of  emotionally  based  drive  (D)  and 
its  relation  to  performance  in  simple  learning  situations.  Amer. 
Psychologist,  13,  131-141. 

Spence,  K.  W.,  and  I.  E.  Farber  (1953) :  Conditioning  and  extinction 
as  a  function  of  anxiety.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  45,  116-119. 


386  THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 

Spence,  K.  W.,  I.  E.  Farber,  and  E.  Taylor  (1954):  The  relation  of 
electric  shock  and  anxiety  to  level  of  performance  in  eyelid  con- 
ditioning. /.  exp.  Psychol,  48,  404-408. 

Spence,  K.  W.,  and  L.  E.  Ross  (1957) :  Experimental  evidence  on  the 
relation  between  performance  level  in  eyelid  conditioning  and 
anxiety  (drive)  level.  Technical  Report  5,  Studies  of  influence 
of  motivation  on  performance  in  learning,  Contract  N9  onr 
93802,  Project  NR  154-107,  Office  of  Naval  Research. 

Spence,  K.  W.,  and  J.  A.  Taylor  (1951) :  Anxiety  and  strength  of  the 
UCS  as  determiners  of  the  amount  of  eyelid  conditioning.  J.  exp. 
Psychol,  42,  183-188. 

Stein,  K.  B.  (1953):  Perceptual  defense  and  perceptual  sensitization 
under  neutral  and  involved  conditions.  /.  Pers.,  21,  467-478. 

Stellar,  E.  (1954):  The  physiology  of  motivation.  Psychol  Rev.,  61, 
5-22. 

Stevens,  S.  S.  (1946):  The  science  of  noise.  Atlantic  Monthly,  178, 
96-102,  July,  1946. 

Stevens,  S.  S.  (1951):  Mathematics,  measurement,  and  psycho- 
physics.  In  S.  S.  Stevens  (ed.),  Handbook  of  experimental  psy- 
chology. New  York:  John  Wiley  &  Sons.,  Inc. 

Strouthes,  A.,  and  H.  C.  Hamilton  (1959):  Fear  conditioning  as  a 
function  of  the  number  and  timing  of  reinforcements.  J.  Psychol, 
48,  131-139. 

Sullivan,  J.  J.  (1950) :  Some  factors  affecting  the  conditioning  of  the 
galvanic  skin  response.  Unpublished  doctoral  dissertation,  State 
University  of  Iowa. 

Switzer,  S.  A.  (1930) :  Backward  conditioning  of  the  lid  reflex.  /.  exp. 
Psychol,  13,  76-97. 

Tandler,  B.  F.  (1958) :  Judgments  of  circular  area  and  of  line  length 
under  high  and  low  levels  of  motivation.  (Unpublished.  Personal 
communication.) 

Taylor,  J.  A.  (1951):  The  relationship  of  anxiety  to  the  conditioned 
eyelid  response.  J.  exp.  Psychol,  41,  81-92. 

Taylor,  J.  A.  (1956d):  Drive  theory  and  manifest  anxiety.  Psychol. 
Bull,  53,  303-320. 

Taylor,  J.  A.  (1956b):  Physiological  need,  set,  and  visual  duration 
threshold.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol,  S2,  96-99. 

Taylor,  J.  A.,  and  K.  W.  Spence  (1952) :  The  relationship  of  anxiety 
level  to  performance  in  serial  learning.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  44,  61-64. 

Teel,  K.  S.  (1952) :  Habit  strength  as  a  function  of  motivation  during 
learning.  /.  comp.  physiol  Psychol,  4S,  188-191. 

Teel,  K.  S.,  and  W.  B.  Webb  (1951) :  Response  evocation  on  satiated 
trials  in  the  T-maze.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  41,  148-152. 

Thorndike,  E.  L.  (1898):  Animal  intelligence;  an  experimental  study 
of  the  associative  processes  in  animals.  Psychol.  Rev.  Monogr. 
Suppl,  2,  No.  4  (Whole  No.  8). 


REFERENCES  387 

Thorndike,  E.  L.,  and  I.  Lorge  (1944):  The  teacher's  word  book  of 

30,000  words.  New  York:  Teachers  College,  Columbia  University. 

Tolmaii,  E.  C.  (1932) :  Purposive  behavior  in  animals  and  men.  New 

York:  Appleton-Century-Crofts,  Inc. 
Tolman,  E.  C.  (1942) :  Drives  toward  war.  New  York:  Appleton-Cen- 
tury-Crofts, Inc. 
Tolman,  E.  C.   (1948):  Cognitive  maps  in  rats  and  men.  Psychol. 

Rev.,  SS,  189-208. 
Tolman,  E.  C.  (1949) :  There  is  more  than  one  kind  of  learnmg.  Psy- 
cho?. Rev.,  56,  144-155. 
Tolman,  E.  C.   (1951):  A  psychological  model.  In  T.  Parsons  and 
E.  A.  Shils  (eds.).  Toward  a  general  theory  of  action.  Cambridge, 
Mass.:  Harvard  University  Press. 
Tolman,  E.  C.  (1952) :  A  cognition  motivation  model.  Psychol.  Rev., 

59,'  389-400. 
Tolman,  E.  C,  and  H.  Gleitman   (1949):  Studies  in  spatial  learn- 
ing: VII.  Place  and  response  learning  under  different  degrees  of 
motivation.  J.  exp.  Psychol,  39,  653-659. 
Tolman,  E.  C,  C.  S.  Hall,  and  E.  P.  Bretnall  (1932) :  A  disproof  of 
the  law  of  effect  and  a  substitution  of  the  laws  of  emphasis,  mo- 
tivation, and  disruption.  J.  exp.  Psychol,  IS,  601-614. 
Tolman,  E.  C,  and  L.  Postman   (1954):  Learning.  In  C.  P.  Stone 
(ed.).  Annual  review  of  psychology.  Palo  Alto,  Calif.:  Annual 
Reviews,  Inc. 
Troland,  L.  T.    (1928):    The  fundamentals  of  human  motivation. 

Princeton,  N.J.:  D.  Van  Nostrand  Company,  Inc. 
Veroff,  J.,  S.  Wilcox,  and  J.  W.  Atkinson  (1953):  The  achievement 
motive  in  high  school  and  college  age  women.  J.  abnorm.  soc. 
Psychol,  48,  108-119. 
Verplanck,  W.  S.,  and  J.  R.  Hayes  (1953) :  Eating  and  drinking  as  a 
function  of  maintenance  schedule.  J.  comp.  physiol  Psychol,  46, 
327-333. 
Wagner,  A.  R.  (1959):  The  role  of  reinforcement  and  nonremforce- 
ment  in  an  "apparent  frustration  effect."  /.  exp.  Psychol,  SI,  130- 

136. 
Warden,  C.  J.  (1931):  Animal  motivation.  Experimental  studies  on 

the  albino  rat.  New  York:  Columbia  University  Press. 
Warner,  L.  H.  (1927) :  A  study  of  sex  behavior  in  the  white  rat  by 

means  of  the  obstruction  method.  Comp.  Psychol  Monogr.,  4, 

No.  5  (Whole  No.  22). 
Webb,  W.  B.  (1949) :  The  motivational  aspect  of  an  irrelevant  drive 

in  the  behavior  of  the  white  rat.  J.  exp.  Psychol,  39,  1-14. 
Welker,  W.  I.   (1956):  Effects  of  age  and  experience  on  play  and 

exploration  of  young  chimpanzees.  J.  comp.  physiol.  Psychol,  49, 

223-226. 
Wenar,  C.  (1954):  Reaction  time  as  a  function  of  manifest  anxiety 


388  THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 

and  stimulus  intensity.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  49,   335-340. 

White,  C.  T.,  and  H.  Schlosberg  (1952):  Degree  of  conditioning  of 
the  GSR  as  a  function  of  the  period  of  delay.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  43, 
357-362. 

Whiting,  J.  W.  M.,  and  I.  L.  Child  (1953):  Child  training  and  per- 
sonality: a  cross-cultural  study.  New  Haven,  Conn.:  Yale  Univer- 
sity Press. 

Whittaker,  E.  M.,  J.  C.  Gilchrist,  and  J.  W.  Fischer  (1952):  Per- 
ceptual defense  or  response  suppression.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol., 
47,  732-733. 

Wiener,  M.  (1955):  Word  frequency  or  motivation  in  perceptual 
defense.  /.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  SI,  214-218. 

Williams,  J.  E.  (1955):  Mode  of  failure,  interference  tendencies  and 
achievement  imagery.  J.  abnorm.  soc.  Psychol.,  SI,  573-580. 

Williams,  M.  (1950):  The  effects  of  experimentally  induced  needs 
upon  retention,  /.  exp.  Psychol.,  40,  139-151. 

Wispe,  L.  G.,  and  N.  C.  Drambarean  (1953):  Physiological  need, 
word  frequency,  and  visual  duration  thresholds.  /.  exp.  Psychol., 
46,  25-31. 

Wolfe,  J.  B.  (1936):  Effectiveness  of  token-rewards  for  chim.panzees. 
Comp.  Psychol.  Monogr.,  12,  No.  5  (Whole  No.  60). 

Woodworth,  R.  S.  (1918):  Dynamic  psychology.  New  York:  Colum- 
bia University  Press. 

Wycoff,  L.  B.,  Jr.  (1952):  The  role  of  observing  responses  in  dis- 
crimination learning.  Part  I.  Psychol.  Rev.,  59,  431-442. 

Yamaguchi,  H.  G.  (1951 ) :  Drive  (D)  as  a  function  of  hours  of  hunger 
(h).  J.  exp.  Psychol,  42,  108-117. 

Yamaguchi,  H.  G.  (1952) :  Gradients  of  drive  stimulus  (S^)  intensity 
generalization.  /.  exp.  Psychol,  43,  298-304. 

Yerkes,  R.  M.,  and  J.  D.  Dodson  (1908) :  The  relation  of  strength  of 
stimulus  to  rapidity  of  habit  formation.  /.  comp.  Neurol,  18, 
459-482. 

Young,  P.  T.  (1936) :  Motivation  of  behavior.  New  York:  John  Wiley 
&  Sons,  Inc. 

Young,  P.  T.  (1949):  Food-seeking  drive,  affective  process,  and  learn- 
ing. Psychol  Rev.,  S6,  98-121. 

Young,  P.  T.  (1955) :  The  role  of  hedonic  processes  in  motivation.  In 
M.  R.  Jones  (ed.),  Nebraska  symposium  on  motivation.  Lincoln, 
Nebr.:  University  of  Nebraska  Press. 

Zatskis,  J.  (1949):  The  effect  of  the  need  for  achievement  on  lin- 
guistic behavior.  Unpublished  master's  thesis.  Wesleyan  Univer- 
sity. Cited  in  McClelland,  Atkinson,  Clark,  and  Lowell,  1953. 

Zeaman,  D.,  and  N.  Wegner  (1954):  The  role  of  drive  reduction  in 
the  classical  conditioning  of  an  autonomically  mediated  response. 
J.  exp.  Psychol,  48,  349-354. 


NAME  INDEX 

llllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllli: 


Adams,  }.,  321 

Adamson,  J.  F.,  315 

Adolph,  E.  F.,  68,  72 

Aiken,  E.  G.,  346 

Amsel,  A.,  83,  84,  108,132,  133,  1 

156,  163,  195,  205,  211-213 
Anand,  B.  K.,  66 
Anderson,  E.  E.,  187 
Arakelian,  P.,  80 
Arenberg,  D.,  283 
Armus,  H.  L.,  167 
Aronson,  E.,  250 
Ashley,  W.  R.,  295,  297 
Asimow,  A.,  91 
Atkinson,  J.  W.,  131,  180,  184,  2 

239,  241-244,  246,  248,  282 


Bahrick,  H.  P.,  132 
Bakan,  D.,  3 
Baker,  R.  A.,  76 
Baldwin,  M.  V.,  226 
Barnes,  G.  W.,  358 
Barry,  H.,  Ill,  120 
Bass,  B.,  78,  120 
Beams,  H.  L.,  298 
Bechtoldt,  H.  P.,  274,  275 
Beebe-Center,  J.  G.,  24 
Bendig,  A.  W.,  260 
Bergmann,  G.,  46 
Berkun,  M.  M.,  65,  338 
Berlvne,  D.  E.,  331,  334,  335 
Bevan,  W.,  Jr.,  297 
Bicknell,  E.  A.,  189 


Bills,  A.  G.,  185 
Bindra,  D.,  131,  258 
Birch,  D.,  178,  179,  187 
Bitterman,  M.  E.,  256,  315,  344 
55,      Bolles,  R.  G.,  131 

Boren,  }.  J.,  132,  353,  358 

Boslov,  G.  L.,  348 

Bowden,  J.,  349 

Bower,  G.  H.,  86,  353,  354 

Brady,  J.  V.,  132,  163,  168,  353,  354, 

358 
Brandauer,  C.  M.,  122 
Brantley,  J.  J.,  132,  156 
Braunstein,  E.  P.,  19 
27,      Bretnall,  E.  P.,  232 
Bricker,  P.  D.,  308 
Broadhurst,  P.  L.,  85 
Brobeck,  J.  R.,  66,  69 
Bronson,  W.  C.,  314 
Brown,  D.  R.,  321 
Brown,  G.  W.,  86,  351,  354,  356 
Brown,  J.  S.,  70,  108,  148,  150,  151, 

156,   157,   166,   172,   182,   195, 

201,  203,  208,  249,  282,   316, 

337,  357 
Brown,  M.  L.,  86,   351,   356 
Brown,  P.  A.,  214 
Brown,  W.  L.,  208,  219 
Brozek,  J.,  226 

Bruner,  J.  S.,  289,  293,  298,  310,  320 
Bugelski,  R.,  148 
Burnstein,  E.,  178,  187 
Burros,  R.  H.,  168 
Bursten,  B.,  351,  353,  356 
Butler,  R.  A.,  331-333,  337,  338 
389 


390 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


Calvin,  J.  S.,  189 

Campbell,  B.  A.,  83,  131 

Campbell,  N.  R.,  51,  54 

Cannon,  W.  B.,  63,  64,  144,  147 

Capretta,  P.  J.,  69 

Carlton,  P.  L.,  90 

Carpenter,  J.  A.,  118,  131 

Carter,  L.  F.,  293,  295 

Castaneda,  A.,  262,  263 

Champion,  R.  A.,  90 

Chapanis,  A.,  235,  308 

Chapman,  R.  M.,  338 

Chein,  I.,  284 

Child,  I.  L.,  131,  220,  261 

Chiles,  W.  D.,  350 

Chodorkoff,  B.,  323 

Clark,  R.  A.,   131,   178,   180,   184, 

187,  239,  241,  242,  245,  253 
Clark,  R.  E.,  279,  280 
Cohen,  B.  D.,  86,  351,  354,  356 
Cohen,  M.  R.,  48,  51 
Collier,  C,  131,  202,  205,  218 
Conger,  J.  J.,  168 
Connor,  T.  J.,  133 
Conrad,  D.,  132,  353,  358 
Cooper,  J.  B.,  219 
Correll,  R.  E.,  350 
Cotton,  J.  W.,  80,  130 
Courts,  F.  A.,  42,  132,  185 
Cowles,  }.  T.,  174 
Crespi,  L.  P.,  178,  208 
Crutchfield,  R.  S.,  228 


Daniel,  W.  J.,  74,  102,  111 
Davenport,  J.  W.,  78,  90 
Davis,  J.  D.,  123,  132 
Davis,  M.,  357 
Davis,  R.  C,  5 
Davis,  R.  H.,  120,  131 
Davitz,  J.  R.,  347 
Deese,  J.,  118,  131,  233,  236 
Delgado,  J.  M.  R.,  351,  353,  356 
Delhagen,  J.  E.,  358 
Dember,  W.  N,  331 
Dinsmoor,  J.  A.,  91,  125 
Dodson,  }.  D.,  91 

Dollard,  }.,  87,  176,  180,  182,  214, 
343 


Doob,  L.  W.,  214 
Drambarean,  N.  C,  284 
Duffy,  E.,  108 
Dukes,  W.  F.,  297 


Eisman,  E.,  91,  93 

Eriksen,  C.  W.,  322 

Estes,  W.  K.,  130,  131,  163,  167 


Farber,  I.  E.,  70,  108,  131,  132,  148, 
151,  152,  156,  166,  168,  195, 
201,  203,  208,  233,  236,  237, 
248,  257,  258,  260,  321,  357 

Fernandez,  M.  B.,  133 

Finch,  C,  201,  208 

Fischer,  J.  W.,  314 

Fiske,  D.  W.,  320 

Fonda,  C.  P.,  322 

Forgays,  D.  C,  358 

Fowler,  H.,   331 

Franks,  C.  M.,  229 

Fredenburg,  N.  C,  77,  79,  126,  128 

Freeman,  J.  T.,  314 

French,  E.  C,  250 

French,  }.  R.  P.,  Jr.,  195 

Freud,  S.,  110,  144,  169 

Fuster,  J.  M.,  132,  350 


Galambos,  R.,  168 

Gardiner,  H.  M.,  24 

Garner,  W.  R.,  235 

Gentry,  G.,  208,  219 

Gerall,  A.  A.,  348 

Ghent,  L.,  76 

Gilbert,  R.  W.,  233 

Gilchrist,  J.  C,  285,  286,  288,  296, 

314 
Gilhousen,  H.  C,  219 
Glanzer,  M,  331 
Gleitman,  H.,  90 
Goodman,  C.  C,  289,  293 
Greene,  }.  E.,  121 
Grice,  G.  R.,  115,  116,  123 
Cropper,  G.  L.,  314 
Grossman,  M.  I.,  64-66,  68 
Guetzkow,  H.,  226 


NAME   INDEX 


391 


Guthrie,  E.  R.,  1,  105,  130,  218,  339 
Gwinn,  G.  T.,  160,  162 


Haigh,  G.  v.,  320 

Hall,  G.  S.,  3,  232 

Hall,  J.  F.,  132 

Hamilton,  G.  V.,  208 

Hamilton,  H.  G.,  347 

Hancock,  W.,  213 

Haner,  G.  F.,  214 

Hanford,  P.  V.,  132 

Harlow,  H.  F.,  329,  332,  333,  337 

Harper,  R.  S.,  295,  297 

Hayes,  }.  R.,  134 

Heath,  R.  G.,  354 

Heathers,  G.  L.,  80 

Hebb,  D.  O.,  110,  131,  349 

Hedlund,  J.  L.,  246,  252 

Henderson,  R.  L.,  358 

Hilden,  A.  H.,  5 

Hilgard,  E.  R.,  208,  256,  259 

Hillman,  G.,  120,  131 

Holder,  E.,  131,  202,  205,  218,  219 

Holder,  W.  B.,  131,  202,  205,  218 

Hollenberg,  E.,  219 

Holton,  R.  B.,  214,  216,  217 

Holtzmann,  W.  H.,  256 

Horenstein,  B.  R.,  73,  74,  80 

Horowitz,  L.,  358 

Horton,  G.  P,  7,  218 

Hovland,  G.  I.,  13,  14,  208 

Howes,  D.  H.,  129,  311,  320,  321 

Hughes,  J.  B.,  II,  260 

Hull,  G.   L.,   33,   57,   60,   99,   116, 

117,  176,   195,  203,  329,  339, 

348 
Hunt,  H.  F.,  155,  163,  168 
Hunter,  W.  S.,  120,  131 
Hurley,  J.  R.,  252 


Ingram,  W.  R.,  350 


Jacobs,  A.,  157,  159,  182,  195 
Janowitz,  H.  D.,  68 
Jasper,  H.  H.,  348 
Jenkin,  N.,  299 


Jerome,  E.  A.,  133 
Johanson,  A.  M.,  132 
Johnston,  R.  A.,  252 
Jones,  L.  V.,  256 
Jones,  M.  C,  168 


Kabrick,  R.  P.,  156 

Kagan,  J.,   338 

Kalish,  H.  I.,  148,  151,  160-162,  166, 

167 
Kamin,  L.  J.,  166,  169 
Kaplan,  M.,  87 
Kaplan,  S.  J.,  256 
Keenan,  J.,  233 
Kendler,  H.  H.,  134 
Kessen,  M.  L.,  65 
Ketchel,  R.  G.,  87 
Kimble,  G.  A.,  78,  120,  131 
Kish,  G.  B.,  332,  357,  358 
Klein,  G.  S.,  298 
Kling,  J.  W.,  358 
Kniffen,  G.  W.,   315 
Knott,  J.  R.,  350 
Koch,  S.,  74,  80,  102,  111 
Kraeling,  D.,   83,   131 
Krauskopf,  J.,  344 


Lacy,  O.  W.,   315 

Lambert,  W.  W.,  298,  301 

Lamoreaux,  R.  R.,  162 

Lawrence,  D.  H.,  76,  160,  162,  166 

Lawson,  R.,  195 

Lazarus,  R.  S.,  233,  236,  283,  306, 

322 
Lee,  R.,  297 
Levin,  H.,  358 
Levine,  R.,  284 
Levy,  N.,  338 
Lewin,  K.,  57,  194 
Lewinger,  N.,   315 
Libby,  A.,  167 
Liberman,  A.  M.,  245 
Lindsley,  D.  B.,  110,  348-351 
Lindzey,  G.,  3,  24 
Loess,  H.  B.,  78,  90,  112,  120,  131 
Logan,  F.  A.,  5,  88 
Lorge,  I.,  312 


392 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


Lowell,   E.   L.,   131,   ISO,   184,   219, 

239,  242-245,  252 
Ludvigson,  W.  H.,  275,  276 
Lysak,  W.,  296,  308 


McAllister,  W.  R.,  234 

McCandless,  B.  R.,  262,  263 

McCleary,  R.  A.,  306 

McClelland,  D.  C,  59,  131,  176, 
180,  184,  227,  239,  241,  242, 
245,  248,  250,  253,  282 

MacCorquodale,  K.,  246 

MacDonnell,  M.  F.,  190 

McDonough,  J.  S.,  274,  275 

McDougall,  W.,  110 

McGinnies,  E.,  305,  307,  312,  313, 
320 

Madsen,  K.  B.,  24 

Magoun,  H.  W.,  349 

Malmo,  R.  B,  109,  350 

Maltzman,  I.,  91,  132,  156 

Marquis,  D.  G.,  208,  259 

Marx,  M.  H.,  59,  131,  195,  202,  205, 
218,  358 

Marzocco,  F.  N.,  156,  208,  210 

Mason,  W.  A.,  76 

Masserman,  }.  H.,  356 

Mausner,  B.,  298 

Meehl,  P.  E.,  246 

Meister,  D.  E.,  298 

Melton,  A.  W.,  198 

Meryman,  J.  J.,  133,  152-154,  156, 
167 

Metcalf,  R.  C,  24 

Meyer,  D.  R.,  93,  131 

Miller,  N.  E.,  33,  65,  86,  87,  90,  109, 
121,  132,  142,  148,  156,  160, 
162,  166,  176,  180,  182,  189, 
195,  208,  214,  248,  316,  331, 
343,  345,  351,  353,  354,  357 

Miller,  W.  C,  121 

Milner,  P.,  352 

Miner,  R.  W.,  63,  64 

Moeller,  G.,  345 

Montgomery,  K.  C.,  331-333,  338 

Moody,  J.  A.,  133 

Morgan,  C.  T.,  63,  68,  70,  109,  235 

Moruzzi,  G.,  349 


Mowrer,  O.  H.,  70,  144,   162,   167, 

182,  214,  340,  344,  346,  357 
Muenzinger,  K.  F.,  232 
Murfin,  F.  L.,  167 
Murphy,  D.  B.,  308 
Murphy,  G.,  284,  301 
Murray,  H.  A.,  184 
Myers,  A.  K.,  189,  331 
Myers,  T.  I.,  94 


Nagaty,  M.  O.,  132 

Nagel,'E.,  48,  51 

Nauta,  W.  J.  H.,  354 

Neel,  A.  F.,  323 

Nesberg,  L.  S.,  285,  286,  288 

Nissen,  H.  W.,  3 

Noble,  M.  E.,  131 


Olds,  }.,  352-355,  358 
Olmstead,  D.  L.,  5 
Osgood,  C.  E.,  70 
Osier,  S.  F.,  236 
Otis,  L.  S.,  155 


Palermo,  D.  S.,  262,  263 

Passey,  G.  E.,  234 

Paterson,  A.  L.,  258 

Pavlov,  I.  P.,  5,  171 

Perin,  C.  T.,  80 

Pool,  P.,  65 

Postman,  L.,  129,  228,  232,  246,  298, 

310,  314,  320,  321 
Powloski,  R.  F.,  134 
Proshansky,  H.,  301 
Pustell,  T.  E.,  309 


Ramond,  C.  K.,  78,  90,  104 
Reece,  M.  M.,  308 
Reed,  P.,  344 
Reese,  T.  W.,  51,  52 
Reynolds,  R.  W.,  353 
Richter,  C.  P.,  103 
Riesen,  A.  H.,  13,  14 
Roberts,  C.  L.,  358 
Roberts,  W.  W.,  86,  351,  353,  354, 
358 


NAME   INDEX 


393 


Rodriques,  }.  S.,  293 
Rohrer,   J.   H.,    195 
Rosenbaum,  G.,  253,  257 
Rosenthal,  B.  G.,  294 
Rosner,  B.  S.,  5 
Ross,  L.  E.,  255 
Rossi,  G.  F.,  348 
Roussel,  }.,  195,  211-213 
Runyon,  D.  L.,  295,  297 


Saltz,  E.,  115,  116 

Saltzman,  I.,  74,  80 

Sampliner,  R.  I.,  65 

Sampson,  P.  B.,  348 

Samuels,  I.,  351 

Sanford,  R.  N.,  227,  284 

Schlesinger,  H.  }.,  298 

Schlosberg,  H.,  340,  345,  350 

Schooler,  K.,  293,  295 

Schulman,  A.,  353 

Schwartz,  R.  D.,  5 

Sears,  R.  R.,  214 

Segall,  M.,  331 

Seward,  J.  P.,  59,  205 

Sheffield,  V.  F.,  195 

Sheriffs,  A.  C.,  251 

Sherman,  H.,  305,  313 

Shirley,  M.,  187 

Sidman,  M.,  132,  353,  358 

Siegel,  A.,  298 

Siegel,  P.  S.,  71,  72,  90,   132,   156, 

188,  190 
Skinner,  B.  F.,  6,  32,  33,  120,  163, 

167,  186,  208,  340 
Slonaker,  }.  R.,  187 
Smith,  M.,  65 
Smith,  M.  P.,  69 
Solley,  C.  M.,  297 
Solomon,  L.  N.,  167,  344 
Solomon,  R.  L.,  129,  166,  167,  169, 

298,   301,   304,   309,   311,   320, 

321 
Sorokin,  P.  A.,  226 
Spence,  K.  W.,  14,  17,  23,  46,   ", 

87,  90,  105-107,  109,  132,  134, 

177,  195,  233,  234,  253,  255- 

262,  329,  340 
Sperling,  D.  S.,  189 


Sperry,  M.,  219 
Sprague,  }.  L.,  260 
Stebbins,  W.  C.,  168 
Stein,  K.  B.,  523 
Steinberg,  M.,   132 
Stellar,  E.,  63,  110 
Stevens,  C.  M.,  5 
Stevens,  S.  S.,  48,  235 
Stevenson,  S.  S.,  195,  2( 
Strouthes,  A.,  347 
Strzelecki,  J.,  258 
Sullivan,  J.  J.,  544 
Switzer,  S.  A.,  208 


Tandler,  B.  F.,  279,  280 
Taylor,  E,   152,  255,  257,  258 
Taylor,  }.  A.,  108,  255-257,  260,  285 
Teel,  K.  S.,  89,  105 
Thorndike,  E.  L.,  208,  312 
Tolman,  E.   C.,   7,   28,   57,   70,  90, 

108,  175,  232,  246,  247 
Troland,  L.  T.,  24 


Veroff,  J.,  246 
Verplanck,  W.  S.,  134 


\\^agner,  A.  R.,  213 
^\'arden,  C.  }.,  72 
Warner,  L.  H.,  17 
Waterhouse,  I.  K.,  151,  261 
Watson,  P.  D.,  298,  501 
Webb,  W.  B.,  89,  122 
Wegner,  N.,  344 
Weinberg,  H.,  65 
Welker,  W.  I.,  555 
W^enar,  C.,  258 
White,  C.  T.,  545 
^^'hiting,  J.  W.  M.,  219 
Whittaker,  E.  M.,  514 
Wiener,  M.,  313 
Wilcox,  S.,  246 
\\'illiams,  J.  E.,  252 
\\'illiams,  M.,  230 
Wispe,  L.  G.,  284 
\\^olfe,  J.  B.,  174 
\\'oodrow.  P.,  65 


394 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


Woodworth,  R.  S.,  110 
Wycoff,  L.  B.,  Jr.,  274 
Wynne,  L.  C,  166,  167,  169,  304 


Yamaguchi,  H.  G,  81,  133 
Yerkes,  R.  M.,  91 


Young,  P.  T.,  24,  59,  76 
Yousem,  H.,  283 


Zanchetti,  A.,   348 
Zatskis,  J.,  242 
Zeaman,  D.,  344 


SUBJECT  INDEX 


Achievement  motivation: 

in  addition-task  performance,  243, 

244 
alternative   methods   of   definition, 

250-253 
in  anagrams  task  performance,  244, 

245 
effects  on  behavior,  242-246 
and  intelligence,  244,  245 
and  Rorschach  scores,  242 
and  tachistoscopic  recognition 

thresholds,  245,  246 
Acquired  drive: 

affective-arousal  model  of,   180- 

182 
associative-associative  theory  of, 

140,  141 
associative-motivational    theory   of, 

140,  141 
conditioned  fear  (anxiety)  as,  144- 

176 
{See  also  Fear) 
effects  of  primary  sources  of  drive 

on,  141,  142 
problem  of,  139-144 
and  response-produced  stimuli,  180 
Tg-s    mechanism  of,  176-180 
verbal  commands  as  sources  of, 

182-186 
(See  also  Drive,  secondary 

sources  of) 


Activation,  109,  110 
Additivity,  property  of,  54 
Affective  arousal: 
and  fear,  182 

as  motivating  agency,  239,  240 
motivating  role  of,  180-182 
and  Tg-Sg  mechanism,  182 
Aggressiveness  and  perception,  322, 

323 
Air  deprivation  as  motivating  variable, 

85,  86 
Air-puff  intensity  and  eyelid  condition- 
ing, 234 
Anticipatory  goal  responses  {Tg-Sg 

mechanism),  176-180 
Anticipatory  seeing  responses,  337 
Anxiety: 

and  acquired  drive  for  money,  171- 

176 
defined  by  manifest  anxiety  scale, 

253,  254 
drive  function  of,  in  exploratory 

behavior,  337,  338 
test  defined,  in  children,  262, 
263 
as  chronic  state,  257-259 
and  complex  tasks,  259-263 
and  distractibility,  260,  261 
in  eyelid  conditioning,  254-257 
and   GSR  conditioning,   256, 
257 


SUBJECT  INDEX 


395 


Anxiety  (continued) : 

and  relative  habit  strength,  259- 
263 
Aphagia,  66 

Apparent  size  as   function  of  value, 
289-295 
(See  also  Perception;  Size  estima- 
tion; Value ) 
Ascending  reticular  activating  system 

(see  Reticular  system) 
Associative-associative    theory    of    ac- 
quired drive,  140,  141 
Associative  interpretations,  110-113 
advocates  of,  129-131 
defined,  98,  110,  111 
generalization  version,  115-126 
and  choice  behavior,  123-126 
and  deprivation-time  shifts,  118- 

121 
and  need-state  changes,  121-123 
habit-change  version,  126-129 
and  choice  behavior,  128-129 
and  deprivation  shifts,  126-129 
and  need-state  shifts,  128 
probability-learning  version,  1 30 
stimulus-element  version,    111-115 
and  choice  behavior,  114-115 
and  deprivation  shifts,  111-114 
and  need-state  shifts,  114 
varieties  of.  111 
Associative-motivational  theory  of  ac- 
quired drive,  140,  141 
Associative   theories    (see  Associative 

interpretations) 
Asymmetry  in  logic  of  measurement, 

51 
Auditory  stimuli: 

drive-arousing  value  of,  and  explora- 
tion, 337 
rewarding  function  of,  332 

Backward  conditioning  in  emotional 

conditioning,   347 
Bar  pressing: 

and  deprivation  shifts,  102,  103 
inhibited  by  fear,  163 
reinforced,  by  fear  reduction,   157 
by  intracranial  stimulation,  352- 
356 


Behavior: 

general  methods  of  studying,  21-23 
and    primary    sources    of    drive    in 

animals,  70-94 
as  subject  matter  of  psychology,  1,  2 
(See  also  specific  types  of  behavior) 
Behavior  director,  habit  strength  as, 

58,  59,  61 
Behavioral  approach,  22,  23 
Behavioral  variability  and  concept  of 

purpose,  7 
Body -weight  deficit: 

and  discrimination,  91-93 
and  water  consumption,  72 
Brain  stimulation   (see  Intracranial 
stimulation) 


Cardiac  conditioning  and  UCS  dura- 
tion, 345 
Central  motive   state    (c.m.s.),    109, 

110 
Choice  behavior: 

and  deprivation,  generalization  in- 
terpretation of,  123-126 
motivational  theory  of,  103,  104 
and  food  deprivation,  habits 
equated,  89,  90 
habits  unequal,  90 
and  primary  motivational  variables, 
87-90 
Choice  box,  two-bar,  88 
Coins,  apparent  size  of,  289-295 
CS-UCS   interval   in   emotional   con- 
ditioning, 345 
Conditioned  hunger  (see  Hunger) 
Conditioning: 

and  anxiety  level  (see  Anxiety) 
dual  role  of  unconditioned  stimuli 

in,  233,  234 
of  fear  (see  Fear  conditioning) 
(See  also  Emotional  conditioning) 
Confinement,  escape  from,  in  explora- 
tory behavior,  338,  339 
Conflict  as  source  of  drive,  178,  219, 
220 
in  primitive  societies,  220 
(See  also  Frustration  behavior; 
Thwarting) 


396 


THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 


Consummatory  behavior: 

and  deprivation  time,  71-76 
drive-reducing  function  of,  68 
effects  of  experience  on,  76 
as  estimate  of  drive,  75 
and  internal  stimuli,  75,  76 
regulation  of,  62-66 

by  gastrointestinal  factors,  64-66 
by  oropharyngeal  stimulation, 

64-66 
role  of  nutrients  in,  66 
and  sham  feeding,  65 
Contiguity  in  fear  conditioning,  339- 
348 

Data  {see  Psychological  data) 
Defecation   as   index   of   conditioned 

fear,  155 
Definitions: 

operational,  44-46 
significant,  46,  47 
Delay  of  reinforcement  in  emotional 

conditioning,   343 
Demands,  108 
Deprivation  history  in  defining  drive, 

35-37 
Deprivation  schedules  as  determinants 

of  drive,  93 
Deprivation  time  {see  Air  deprivation; 
Food  deprivation;  Hunger; 
Thirst) 
Derived  measurement  {see  Drive, 

quantification  of) 
Difference    limens    and    motivational 

variables,  278,  279 
Discriminatory  behavior  and  primary 

motivational  variables,  90-94 
Disproportionality  of  stimulus  and  re- 
sponse, 29,  30 
Drinking  and  postshock  emotionality, 

156 
Drive: 

acquired  {see  Acquired  drive) 
conflicting  definitions  of,  67,  68,  72 
curiosity,  328 

as  distinguished  from  drives,  59,  60 
as  distinguished  from  needs,  67-70 
relation    to    drive-reduction    hy- 
pothesis, 69 


Drive  {continued) : 
emotion-produced,  178 
exploratory,  328 

circular  definitions  of,  334 
externalized,  187,  188 
frustration  {see  Frustration  drive) 
gregariousness,  175,  176 
hunger-produced,  as  affected  by 

rhythmical  feeding,  178,  179 
manifest  anxiety  scale,  definition  of, 
253,  254 
{See  also  Manifest  anxiety  scale) 
manipulative   and    selective    defini- 
tions of,  238,  239 
manipulatory,  328 
multiplicative  theory  of  {see  Multi- 
plicative-drive theory ) 
perceptual  curiosity,  335,  336 

and  Tg-Sg  mechanism,  335,  336 
primary  sources  of,  61,  62 
and  choice  behavior,  87-90 
in  discriminatory  behavior,  90-94 
and  instrumental  behavior,  76-87 
in  perception,  282-289 
quantification  of,  47-54 
bv  counting,  49,  50 
and  derived  measurement,  54 
and    fundamental   measurement, 

53,  54 
general  rules  for,  47-49 
by  ranking,  50-53 
response-defined,  in  humans,  237- 

262 
secondary  sources  of,  62 

compared  with  primary  sources, 

62 
defined,  139 

and  perception,  289-323 
{See  also  Acquired  drive) 
and  stimulus  intensity,  180 
thwarting-produced,    194-196 
visual  exploratory,  difficulties  with, 

336-338 
weight-loss  definition  of,  91-92 
Drive  reduction: 

and  consummatory  activity,  68 
and  saccharin,  69 
and  secondary  reinforcement,  70 
Drive  stimuli,  75 


SUBJECT   INDEX 


397 


Eating  and  postshock  emotionality, 

156 
Electric  shock: 

associative  consequences,  232,  233 
competing  responses  induced  by, 

232,  233 
and  escape  behavior,  83,  84 
and  human  performance,  231-233 
informative  effects  of,  232 
in  instrumental  behavior,  82-85 
intracranial,  86,  87 
motivating  and  directing  functions 

of,  58,  59 
motivating   effects  of,   in   animals, 

82,  86 
persisting  effects  of,  232,  233 
punishing  effects  of,  231,  232 
randomly  administered,  233 
reduction  of,  and  perceptual  thresh- 
olds, 308,  309 
Electroconvulsive  shock  and  con- 
ditioned fear,  163,  168 
Emotion    of    hope    as    drive    source, 

182 
Emotional  conditioning: 
backward  order  in,  347 
contiguity  plus  drive-reduction  view 

of,  340-348 
critical  variables  in,  341,  342 
distinguished   from  mechanisms, 
341,  342 
and  CS-UCS  interval,  345 
and  delay  of  reinforcement,  343 
"different-process"  theories  of,  340, 

341 
by  drive  reduction,  340 
experimental  designs,  342-348 
intermittent  shock  in,  345 
and  pupillary  conditioning,  348 
"same-process"  theories  of,    339, 

340 
temporal  intervals  in,  347 
and  UCS  duration,  342-346 
cardiac  conditioning  and,  345 
Emotional  responses,  role  as  motiva- 
tors, 107 
Emotionahty: 

associative  effects  of,  and  percep- 
tion, 305,  306 


Emotionality  {continued): 

contribution  to  drive,  and  percep- 
tion, 305 
postshock,  compared  with  fear,  155, 

156 
stimulus-produced,   and   perception 
{see  Perception) 
Energy  mobilization,  109 
Eyelid  conditioning: 

and  air-puff  intensity,  234,  256 
anxiety  and  UCS  intensity  in,  255, 
256 
Excitatory  potential,  determinants,  99 
Expectancy  (r^-s^  mechanism),  176- 

180 
Experience,  role  of,  in  drive  definition, 

35-37 
Exploratory  behavior : 

and  drive-reduction  theory,  337, 

338 
escape  from  confinement  in,    338, 

339 
extinction  of,  332 
and  fear,  333,  334 
generalization  of,  332 
and  nonexploratory  behavior,  334 
studies  of,  331-333 
Exploratory  drive  {see  Drive) 
Extensive  dimension,  53,  54 
External   stimuli,    motivational    attri- 
butes of,  327,  328 
Extinction  of  fear,  significant  variables 
in,  167,  168 


Facihtation,  selective,  of  responses, 

248-250 
Factor  X  as  hypothetical  behavior  de- 
terminant, 31-41 
Familiarity  with  words  in  perceptual 

recognition,  311-315 
Fear: 

acquisition  of,  and  startle  responses, 

149-151 
and  alcohol,  168 
and  audiogenic  seizures,  168 
and  bar  pressing,  163 
combined  with  hunger,  152-154 
and  defecation,  155 


398 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


Fear  (continued) : 

distinguished  from  residual  emo- 
tionality, 155,  156 
and  electroconvulsive  shock,  163, 

168 
as  energizer,  147-155 
extinction  of,  and  startle  responses, 
151 
variables  affecting,   167,   168 
in  human  subjects,  and  GSR,  154, 

155 
in   human    subjects,    higher-order 
conditioning  of,  170,  171 
as  learned  response,  169-171 
role  of  language,  170,  171 
(See  also  Anxiety) 
inhibition  of  drinking  by,  163,  164 
as  inhibitor  and  energizer,  165-166 
inhibitory  effects  of,  162-166 
procedures  for  estimating  strength 

of,  145-147 
reduction,  and  extinction  trials,  161 
and  fear-conditioning  trials,  160, 

161 
as  reinforcement,  156-162 
spontaneous  recovery  of,  and  startle 

responses,  151,  152 
and  startle  responses,  148-154 
variables  affecting  strength  of,  166- 
168 
Fear  conditioning: 

contiguity  in,  339-348 
procedures,  144,  145 
theories  of,  139,  142 
(See  also  Emotional  conditioning) 
Fistulas,   esophageal,  and  sham-feed- 
ing, 65 
Food  deprivation: 

facihtative  effects  of,   132 
and  human  performance,  225-230 
and  imaginative  responses,  241 
and  perception,  282-289 
and  running  speed,  77-79 
{See  also  Hunger) 
Fractional  anticipatory  goal  reactions 

{Tg-Sg  mechanism),    176-180 
Frustration : 

antecedents  of,  203,  204 
anticipator)',  205-207 


Frustration  (continued) : 
as  aversive  condition,  206 
conditioned,  205-207 
conflict-produced,  203,  204 
as  drive  source,  203-207 

(See  also  Thwarting) 
effects  on  behavior,  203,  204 
as  implicit  reaction,  205 
from  nonreward,  203,  205 
as  stimulus  source,  203,  204,  206 
unlearned  reactions  to,  204 

Frustration  behavior: 

associative  conceptions  of,  200-202 
and  extinction,  202 
motivational  theories  of,  202-207 
and  stimulus  similarity,  201 
and  transfer  of  training,  202 
(See  also  Thwarting) 

Frustration  drive: 

associative  conceptions  of,   210, 

211 
and  bar  pressing,  208-211 
and  delay,  218,  219 
and  deprivation  time,  209,  210 
as  energizer,  207-217 
and  goal  distance,  214-217 
inhibitory  effects  of,  218,  219 
and    massing    of    extinction    trials, 

209,  210 

reduction  of,  as  reinforcement,  218 
and  reinforcement  frequency,  209, 

210,  216 

and  response  vigor  (children),  214- 

218 
and   running  speed  in   rats,   211- 
214 
Frustration  stimuli,  inhibitory  proper- 
ties of,  206 
Function,  stepwise,  29,  30 
Functional  relations,  13-21 
OR,  17,  72 
OS-R,  20 
R-R,  14,  240,  241 
and  reliability,  15 
and  validity,  16,  17 
SO-R,  19 
S-R,  13 
Fundamental  measurement  (see 
Drive,  quantification  of) 


SUBJECT   INDEX 


399 


Galvanic  skin  response: 

conditioning  of,  and  anxiety,  256, 
257 

in  defining  subception,  306,  307 
Generalization : 

on   drive-stimulus   dimension,    178, 
179 

of  habit  strength,  116-118 

{See  also  Stimulus  generalization) 
Gregariousness,  drive  of,  175,  176 

Habit  strength: 

as  aflPected  by  stimulus  impoverish- 
ment, 281 
contribution  of,  to  excitatory  poten- 
tial, 99,  100 
directive  functions  of,   58,   59,   61 
generalized,  defined,   116-118 
inferred  from  psychophysical  data, 
273-274 
Hunger: 

conditionabihty  of,   186-191 
"conditioned,"  and  food  consump- 
tion, 190 
and  maze  performance,  187,  188 
and  response  acquisition,  189 
and  running-v/heel  activity,  187 
in  discriminatory  behavior,  91-93 
effect  of,  on  need-related  responses, 
227-229 
on  startle  responses,  152-154 
and  fear,  combination  of,  152-154 
and  food  consumption,  73,  74 
and  human  performance,  225-230 
and  imaginal  processes,  227-229 
in    instrumental   behavior,    acquisi- 
tion of,  76-79 
local  theory  of,  63-64 
and  resistance  to  extinction,  79-81 
and  retention  of  verbal  materials, 

230 
and  set,  228,  229 
stimulus  control  of,  66,  70 
and  verbal  food-response  proba- 
bility, 228,  229 
and  word  completion,  228,  229 
{See  also  Consummatory  behavior; 
Discriminatory  behavior;  In- 
strumental behavior) 


Hurdle-jumping,  reinforcement  of,  by 
fear  reduction,  157-162 

Hyperphagia,  66 

Hypnosis  in  value-size  judgments,  295, 
296 

Hypothalamus: 
and  eating,  66 
as  locus  of  central  motive  state,  110 

Hypothetical  constructs  {see  Inter- 
vening variables) 


Illuminance  matching: 

constant  errors  in,  and  drive,  287, 

288 
incentive  motivation  in,  287,  288 
interpreted,  286-288 
role  of  thirst  in,  285-289 
time  errors  in,  285-288 
Incentive  motivation   (K): 
defined,  107,  108 
as  exteroceptively  aroused  drive, 

329,  330 
and  valuable  objects,  290,  291 

group  differences  in,  291 
{See  also  Tg-Sg  mechanism) 
Instructions: 

cue  functions  of,  236,  237 
motivating  effects  of,  235-237 
success  and  failure,  236,  237 
{See  also  Motivating  instructions) 
Instrumental  behavior: 

acquisition  of,  and  deprivation  time, 

77,  78 
and  air-deprivation  time,  85,  86 
and  deprivation  time,  76-82 
and  electric  shock,  82-85 
extinction  of,  and  deprivation  time, 

79-82 
and  intracranial  stimulation,  86,  87 
{See  also  Intracranial  stimula- 
tion) 
noxious  stimulus  intensity  and,  82- 
87 
Insulin,  69 

Intensive  dimension,  53 
Interaction  in  empirical  laws,  20 
Intermediary  concepts   {see  Interven- 
ing variables) 


400 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


Intervening  variables,  23,  28-47 
defined  circularly,  34,  35 
independently  defined  in  terms,  of 
antecedent  conditions,    35-37 
of  organic  variables,  37,  38 
of  stimulus  conditions,  38-40 
of  task  performance,  37 
naming  of,  40,  41 
relations  suggesting  need  for,  29- 
34 
Intracranial  stimulation: 

and  drive-reduction  hypothesis, 

358,  359 
effects  of  alerting,  350 
inhibitory,  350,  351,  354 
positive  and  negative,  and  in- 
tensity, 354,  355 
specific,  351 
motivating  consequences  of,  86,  87, 

351 
nondirective  aspects  of,  356 
and  pleasure-pain  centers,  353-356 
reinforcing  properties  of,    352-356 
Iowa    Multiple    Choice   Achievement 

Imagery  Test,  252,  253 
Iowa  Picture  Interpretation  Test: 
achievement  motivation  defined  by, 

251,  252 
and  performance,  252 
reliabihty  of,  251,  252 
and  TAT-defined  achievement 
motivation,  251,  252 


Laws,  guessed  at,  23 

{See  also  Functional  relations) 
Learning: 

as  distinguished  from  performance, 

99,  100 
{See  also  Acquired  drive;  Condi- 
tioning; Instrumental  be- 
havior) 
Libido  need,   108 

Local  theory  of  hunger  and  thirst,  63, 
64 


Manifest  anxiety  {see  Anxiety;  Mani- 
fest anxiety  scale) 


Manifest  anxiety  scale: 
children's  form,  262,  263 
in  defining  drive,  253,  254 
relation  to  psychiatric  ratings,  254 
relation  of  scores  to  eyelid  condi- 
tioning, 254-257 
Manipulatory  behavior,   332,   333 

persistence  of,  333 
Masochistic   behavior: 
in  cats,   356,   357 
in  rats,    357 
Measurement: 
derived,  54 
fundamental,  53,  54 
nature  of,  48 
varieties  of,  49-54 
{See  also  Drive,  quantification  of) 
Method  of  constant  stimuli  and  mo- 
tivational   variables,    272-281 
Methods  of  data  collection,  2 
Molar  behavior,  23 
Money : 

acquired    drive    for,    and    anxiety, 

171-176 
rewarding  effects  of,  as  anxiety  re- 
duction, 174,  175 
as  secondary  reinforcement,  174 
Motivating  instructions: 

drive-like     effects     on     perception, 

276-281 
effects    on    recognition    thresholds, 

274-278 
{See  also  Instructions;  Verbal  com- 
mands as  drive  sources) 
Motivation: 

defined    by    imaginative    responses, 

239-253 
general  problem  of,  24-25 
response-defined,  in  human  subjects, 

237-262 
{See  also  Drive;  Motivational  vari- 
ables; Motives) 
Motivational  interpretations: 
advocates  of,  107-110 
defined,  98 

supporting  evidence,   132-135 
Motivational  variables: 
combinations  of,  133,  134 
criteria  for  identification  of,  41-44 


SUBJECT  INDEX 


401 


Motivational  variables  {continued) : 
and  difference  limens,  278,  279 
directing  and  motivating  functions 

of,   58,   59 
distinguished  from  steering  vari- 
ables, 57 
effects  of,  interpreted  associatively 
(see  Associative  interpretations) 
energizing  criterion  of,  41,  42 
learning  criterion  of,   42 
named  b}'  exclusion,  42,  43 
punishment  criterion  of,  42 
Motives : 

effects  of,  as  associative  phenomena, 
246,   247 
on  behavior,  theory  of,  246-248 
experimental  arousal  of,   241,   242 
interaction    with    cognitive    expec- 
tancies, 247,  248 
as  learned  affective  reactions,  239, 

240 
as  selective  facilitators,  247,  248 
Motor  tasks  and  anxiety  level,  260 
Multiplicative-drive  theory  (Hull),  60, 
61,  99,  100 
and  absolute   thresholds,   272-278 
applied,   101-107 
and  choice  behavior,   103-106 
and    habit-strength    equality,    105, 

106 
and  habit-strength  inequality,  104, 

105 
implications  of,  100,  101 
and   perception,    272-281 
prediction    of   poorer    performance 

by,    105,    106 
and  satiation  effects,  102,  103 
and  slope  of  psychophysical  func- 
tions,  276-279 
supporting  evidence,  134,  135 
Muscular   tension,    facilitative   effects 
of,  132 


Need-achie\'ement    motive,     1 84 
Needs,   biological: 

and  consummatorv  behavior,  61- 
66 

distinguished  from  dri\'e,  67-70 


Noise   and   human   performance, 

235 
Novel  stimuli: 

aversive  properties  of,  333 
drive  function  of,  330-339 
produced     by     motivation-variable 

shifts,  131 
reinforcing  properties  of,  331,  332 
Noxious  stimuli: 

and  instrumental  behavior,   82-87 
motivating   effects   on    human    be- 
havior,  230-235 
response-evoking  properties  of,  87 
Nutrients  and  consummatory  behav- 
ior, 66 


Operational   definitions,   44-46 
Ordinal  scale    {see  Drive,  quantifica- 
tion  of) 


Paired-associates    learning    and    anxi- 
ety, 261,  262 
Parameter  in  empirical  laws,  20 
Perception : 

without  awareness,    307,    308 
definitional  problem,  269,  270 
and  delayed  overt  responses,   268, 

269 
of  emotion-arousing  stimuli,    301- 
323 
and  acquired-drive  problem,  302 
associative  view  of,  305,  306 
and  drive,  305 

and  linguistic  behavior,  311,  312 
possible  mechanisms,  303-306 
and  stimulus  distinctiveness,  303 
and  stimulus  generalization,  302 
and  motivational  variables,  general 

problem  of,  271,  272 
and      multiplicative-drive      theory, 

272-281 
in  others,  267 
and    persisting    emotionality,    304, 

305 
and  personal  values,   320 

associative   and   other   views   of, 
321,  322 


402 


THE  MOTIVATION  OF  BEHAVIOR 


Perception  (continued) : 

phenomenological    conception    of, 

267 
reinforced  by  shock  reduction,  308, 

309 
of  stimuli  paired  with  shock,  306- 
310 
sex  differences  in,   309,   310 
of  taboo  words,  310-323 

associative    factors    in,    311-315 

and  familiarity,  311-315 

and    personality    characteristics, 

319-323 
R-R  relations  in,  319,  320 
and  set,  314,  315 
as  unnecessary  concept,  267,  268 
value  orientation  and,    320-322 
verbal  versus  autonomic  definitions 
of,  307,  308 
Perceptual    curiosity,    drive    of,    335, 

336 
Perceptual  defense,  303-323 

competing-response  theory  of,  315- 

319 
idiosyncratic  nature  of,  322,  323 
Perceptual     thresholds    and    motiva- 
tional variables,  interpreted  asso- 
ciatively,  282 
Perceptual  vigilance,  303-323 
Physiological  approach,  22 
Point  of  subjective  equality,  shift  with 

value,  299-301 
Primary    needs    [see    Drive,    primary 

sources  of) 
Primary  sources  of  drive  and  perform- 
ance {see  Drive) 
Psychological  data: 
basic,   11,  12 
characteristics  of,  2,  10 
methods  of  collecting,  2 
Pupillary  conditioning,  role  of  pain  in, 
348 

Quantification: 

of  drive  {see  Drive) 

logical  requirements  of,  51,  52 

R-R    relations    and    human    motive 
strength,  240,  241 


Tg-Sg  mechanism  as  source  of  drive, 

176-180 
Rank-order  scale    {see  Drive,  quanti- 
fication of) 
Reaction    time   and   postshock   emo- 
tionality, 156 
Resistance  to  extinction: 

as  affected  by  need  shifts,  122,  123 
and  deprivation,  74,  79-81 
associative  view  of,  80,  81 
problems  of  experimental  design, 
79-82 
Response  alternation,  331 
Response  classes: 
definition  of,  4-9 

as  actions  of  muscles  or  glands, 

5 
as  limb  movements,  5,  6 
by   reference   to    same   determi- 
nants, 8 
in  terms,  of  satisfaction  of  same 
needs,  7,  8 
of  similar  effects  on  environ- 
ment, 6,  7 
Response  constancy  with  stimuli  vari- 
able, 32,  33 
Response  facilitation,  selective,  248- 
250 
as  apparent  effect  of  drive  (D), 

248,  249 
as  associative  phenomenon,  249, 
250 
Response  suppression: 
methods  of  control,   314 
and    recognition    thresholds,    313, 
314 
Response  variation  with  stimuli  con- 
stant,   31 
Responses,  definition  of,    3-9 

without  reference  to  stimuli,  4 
in  terms  of  stimuli,  3,  4 
Reticular  system: 

control  of  alerting  function  by  stim- 
ulation of,  351,  352 
described,   348,   349 
electrocortical  activation  by,  349 
nonspecific  functions  of,    348-351 
Running  speed,  food  deprivation  and, 
77-79 


SUBJECT   INDEX 


403 


Saccharin  and  drive-reduction  hypoth- 
esis, 69 
Satiation: 
stimulus,  331 

and  T-maze  performance,  89,  90 
Secondary  drive  source  {see  Drive) 
Secondary  reinforcement,  drive-reduc- 
tion views  of,  70 
Selective    facilitation    {see    Response 

facilitation ) 
Self-stimulation  {see  Intracranial  stim- 
ulation;  Masochistic  behavior) 
Sensory-change    reinforcement,    357- 
359 
and  drive-reduction  hypothesis,  358, 

359 
and  stimulus  intensity,  358 
Sexual  behavior,  drive-reduction  prop- 
erty of,  68 
Sexual  words,  tachistoscopic  recogni- 
tion of,  322,  323 
{See  also  Perception) 
Sham  feeding  and  need-drive  distinc- 
tion, 68 
{See  also  Consummatory  behavior) 
Shock  {see  Electric  shock) 
Significant  definitions,  46,  47 
Size  estimation: 

as  affected  by  rewards,  298,  299 
and    hypnotically    induced    socio- 
economic status,   295,   296 
and  monetary  value,    289-295 
experimental     design     problems, 

292 
under  hypnosis,   295,  296 
and  object  value,  theories  of,  299- 

301 
of  paper  currency,  296,  297 
of  physically  present  coins,  293, 

294 
of  preferred  foods,  298 
and  socioeconomic  status,  294,  295 
and  symbolic  value,  297-299 
Spatial  choice  situations,  behavior  in, 
and  primary  drive  sources,   87- 
90 
Stabilimeter,  148,  149 
Starting  speed,  food  deprivation  and, 
77-79 


Startle  responses: 

augmented  by  fear,  148-154 
and  postshock  emotionality,  156 
Stimuli: 

definition  of,  9-12 

independently  of  responses,  9,  11 
in  relation  to  assorted  variables, 

12 
as  subclass  of  physical  incidents, 

11 
in  terms  of  responses,  12 
drive,  75 

eliciting,  definition  of  responses,  3, 4 
external,  as  drive  sources,  327,  328 
intense,  effects  on  behavior,  132 
motivation-variable,  75 
response-produced,  as  drive  source, 

180 
{See  also   Novel  stimuli;   Noxious 
stimuli ) 
Stimulus  constancy  and  response  vari- 
ability,   30-32 
Stimulus  dynamism,  178 
Stimulus    generalization: 

in    associative    interpretations    {see 

Associative   interpretations) 
empirical  phenomenon  of,  115,  116 
gradient  of,  115,  116 
in  perceptual  defense  theory,  317- 
319 
Stimulus    impoverishment: 
and  competing  habits,  281 
and  habit  strength,  281 
Stimulus  novelty: 

definitional  problems,  334,  335 
as  drive  source,   330-339 
{See  also  Novel  stimuli) 
Stimulus  satiation,    331 
Stimulus  variability  and  response  con- 
stancy,  32,  33 
Subception,  307 
Symbolic  constructs   {see  Intervening 

variables) 
Sjmbolic  value  and  size  estimation, 
297-299 
{See  also  Size  estimation) 

T  maze,  performance  in,  and  depriva- 
tion,  229,   230 


404 


THE  MOTIVATION   OF   BEHAVIOR 


Taboo  words: 

as  ambivalent  stimuli,    316-319 

contextually  produced,  313 

perception  of,  310-323 
Tachistoscopic  recognition  thresholds: 

and  familiarity,  284,  285 

and  hunger,  283-285 

and  set,  285 

{See  also  Perception) 
Thematic     Apperception     Test     and 

human   motives,   240-253 
Thirst: 

local  theory  of,  63-64 

and  perceptual  responses,  285-289 

and  water  consumption,  71,  72 
Thwarting: 

conflict-induced,  197 

criteria  of,  198-200 

defined,  by  repetitive  responses,  199 
by  response  failure,   199,  200 
by  response  resumption,  199 

as  drive  source,  history  of,  194-196 

by  incompatible  responses,  197 

methods  of,  196-198 

as  motivational  variable,  196 

by  physical  barriers,  196,  197 

by  stimulus  elimination,  197 
Time  errors  in  illuminance  matching, 

285-288 
Tobacco  deprivation  and  eyelid  condi- 
tioning,    229,     230 
Transitivity  in  logic  of  measurement, 
51,  52 


Unconditioned  stimuli: 
as  drive  sources,  233-235 
dual  role  of,  in  conditioning,  233, 
234 

Value: 

as  drive  source,  290,  291 
incentive -motivation  conception  of, 

291 
response-defined,   290-291 
Value    orientation     and    perception, 

320-322 
Variables,     psychological,     traditional 

names  for,  24 
Verbal   commands    as    drive    sources, 
182-186 
and  achievement  motivation,   184, 

185 
and  emotionality,   186 
and  muscular  tension,  185,  186 
Vicious-circle  phenomenon,  357 
Vigilance,  perceptual,  303-323 
Visual  exploration  drive,   336-338 
Visual  stimuli,  reinforcing  properties 
of,   332 

Water,  consumption  of,  and  depriva- 
tion time,  71,  72 

Word  frequency,  familiarity  defined 
by,  312,  313 

Yerkes-Dodson  law,  91 


Date    Due 
Due  Returned  Due 


/5-'=j.  -f 

C.Z 


The  motivation  ot  iKhaviof,  inain 
159,4B878mC2 


3  12bE  D32fl1  b137 


KEEP  CARD  IN  POCKET 

ResLib 


IT   IS   IMPORTANT  THAT  *; 
CARD  BE  KEPT  IN  POCKET  '